Realizability Categories

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Realizability Categories Realizability Categories W. P. Stekelenburg August 20, 2012 ii Introduction This thesis contains a collection of results of my Ph.D. research in the area of real- izability and category theory. My research was an exploration of the intersection of these areas focused on gaining a deeper understanding rather than on answering a specific question. This gave us some theorems that help to define what realizability is, or at least what realizability categories are. To provide some context, this chapter introduces realizability and category the- ory and makes a small survey of their intersection. In the end it summarizes our contributions. 0.1 Realizability Realizability is a collection of tools in the study of constructive logic, where it tackles questions about consistency and independence that are not easily answered by other means. We have no overview of this ever growing collection and know no general criterion for what can be considered realizability and what can not. Therefore, instead of giving a definition, we will present the historical starting point of realizability, and a selection of some later developments. In [35] Kleene introduces recursive realizability. It interprets arithmetical propo- sitions by assigning sets of numbers to them. Definition 0.1.1. Let N be the natural numbers. Let (m, n) 7→ hm, ni : N × N → N and n 7→ (n0, n1): N → N×N be a recursive bijection and let (m, n) 7→ mn : N×N * N be a universal partial recursive function, i.e., for each partial recursive f : N * N there is an e ∈ N such that for all n ∈ domf, en is defined and equal to f(n). We write mn↓ if (m, n) is in the domain of the universal partial recursive function. We define the realizability relation r. as follows. • n r. x = y if and only if x = y; • n r. p ∧ q if n0 r. p and n1 r. q; • n r. p ∨ q if n0 = 0 and n1 r. p, or n0 = 1 and n1 r. q; • n r. p → q if for all n0 r. p, nn0↓ and nn0 r. q; • n r. ¬p if no n0 r. p. • n r. ∀x.p(x) if for all n0 ∈ N, nn0↓ and nn0 r. p(n0); iii iv INTRODUCTION 0 0 0 • n r. ∃x.p(x) if some n ∈ N, n0 = n and n1 r. p(n ). A proposition p is valid if there is some n ∈ N such that n r. p. The realizers encode some justification for the validity of the formulas they realize. In particular, realizers of p → q are indices of partial recursive functions that send realizers of q to realizers of p. The resulting structure has the following features: • it is a model of Heyting arithmetic; • because every proposition p either has a realizer or doesn’t, p∨¬p and (¬¬p) → p are valid; • nonetheless, there is a predicate p such that ¬(∀n.p(n) ∨ ¬p(n)) is realized. We see the paradox that q(n) = p(n) ∨ ¬p(n) is valid for all n, while ∀x.q(x) can be false, thanks to an interpretation of universal quantification quite different from the one in classical model theory. Kleene proposed a number of variations on recursive realizability. • We can consider whether the existence of realizers is formally provable in Heyt- ing arithmetic or in other formal systems. • We can restrict the set of realized negations, implications, or universal quantifi- cations to a preselected set to avoid realizing false propositions like the unde- cidability of a set of numbers. This restriction allows a more faithful approach to intuitionistic logic. • Kleene developed function realizability, where functions f : N → N take the place of numbers. There is a universal partial continuous function NN×NN * NN for the product topology in NN, which takes the place of the universal partial recursive function. • A further variation on function realizability is that a formula is valid if there is a total recursive function that realizes it [37]. This idea of using a special set of realizers to determine validity is called relative realizability. Others proposed further extensions. • Besides N and NN other sets are suitable for building realizability interpre- tations, namely Feferman’s partial applicative structures (see [18]) and their generalizations. • Instead of a single set of realizers, one can work with a system of sets of realizers. The first example of this was Troelstra’s reformulation of Kreisel’s modified realizability [38], [66]. • Troelstra extended realizability beyond arithmetic, to higher order systems [67]. • Realizability can be combined with sheaf semantics by developing it in the internal language of a Grothendieck topos [68], [22], [44]. 0.2. EFFECTIVE TOPOS v An area of application of realizability is computer science, after all, computers are inherently recursive. Practical limitations of computers, in particular the amount of time and memory required to finish a computation, gave us realizability interpre- tations for languages that are different from first order languages and realizability counter-models for weaker formal systems than classical or intuitionistic first order logic, see [14]. On the other hand, the desire to extract computational information from proofs in classical mathematics has led Krivine to introduce a realizability in- terpretation for classical set theory, see [39]. 0.2 Effective topos We combine realizability with category theory. For an introduction to category theory, see [47]. Category theory started as a part of algebraic topology, as a language for describing the connections between algebraic invariants of topological spaces, see [17]. The theory proved useful in other areas of mathematics, in particular in other parts of algebra and geometry, but also in the more remote areas. Lawvere initiated the application of category theory to logic, see [41] and [42]. Several subjects from category theory, in particular from categorical logic, play a prominent role in this thesis: elementary toposes, regular, exact and Heyting cate- gories, fibred locales, complete fibred Heyting algebras and triposes. Toposes are categories that have finite limits and power objects: an object PX is a power object of X, if there is a monomorphism m : EX → X × PX such that for each monomorphism n : U → X × Y there is a unique f : Y → PX such that n is the pullback of m along g. U / EX y n m X × Y / X × PX X×f This definition of toposes comes from Lawvere and Tierney (see [40], [64] and [63]), although a more restricted notion of toposes appeared earlier in Grothendieck’s work. See [48], [33] or [32] for more information on topos theory. Toposes have an internal language [55]: a higher order intuitionistic logic. Heyting categories where defined in [58]. They also have an internal language, but this internal language is a many sorted predicate logic that does not always have higher order quantification. An early reference of regular and exact categories is [3]. First Mac Lane developed Abelian categories (see [49]) for algebraic topology. Subsequent authors looked at categories that omitted parts of the algebraic structure of Abelian categories, while retaining the non algebraic properties, until Barr settled on the regular and exact categories we use in this thesis. In [11] we find a construction of exact categories out of categories with finite limits – the ex/lex completion – and subsequently many similar constructs have been defined: [10], [12]. Menni worked out under which conditions these completion constructions result in toposes [52], [53]. Lawvere introduced hyperdoctrines in [43]. Both fibred locales and complete fibred Heyting algebras are – up to a 2-equivalence of 2-categories – examples of hyperdoc- vi INTRODUCTION trines and we could have called them regular and first order hyperdoctrines. We de- cided to work with the fibred categories instead of category valued (pseudo)functors, in order to make our work less dependent on set theory, therefore new names seemed appropriate. Grothendieck introduced fibred categories (see [23]) for algebraic geom- etry. B´enabou started applying them to logic [4], [5]. A tripos is a special type of complete fibred Heyting algebra. In [56] and [29], one can find a construction of toposes out of triposes. The tripos-to-topos construction was soon applied to realizability, resulting in Hyland’s effective topos, see [27]. We give a definition of this category here. Definition 0.2.1. The effective topos Eff is the category whose objects are pairs (X, E ⊆ N × X × X) for which s, t ∈ N exists such that for all (m, x, y) ∈ E and (n, z, x) ∈ E, sm and tmn are defined and (sm, y, x) and (tmn, z, y) ∈ E. Morphisms are defined as follows. For all X and all U, V ⊆ N × X we let U |=X V if there is an m ∈ N such that for all (n, x) ∈ U, mn↓ and (mn, x) ∈ V . Then U ⇐⇒ X V if 0 0 U |=X V and V |=X U. A morphism (X, E) → (X ,E ) is an ⇐⇒X -equivalence class 0 φ of F ⊆ N × X × X for which e, r, s0, s1, u ∈ N exists such that • for all (m, x, x) ∈ E, there is a z ∈ X0 such that em↓ and (em, x, z) ∈ F ; • for all (m, x, y) ∈ F ,(n, x, x0) ∈ E and (p, y, y0) ∈ E0, ((rm)n)p↓ and (((rm)n)p, x0, y0) ∈ F ; • for all (m, x, y) ∈ F , s0m and s1m are defined, (s0m, x, x) ∈ E and 0 (s1m, y, y) ∈ E ; • for all (m, x, y), (n, x, z) ∈ F ,(um)n↓ and ((um)n, y, z) ∈ E0. The composition of two morphisms φ :(X, E) → (X0,E0) and χ :(X00,E00) → 0 0 (X ,E ) is the ⇐⇒X -equivalence class χ ◦ φ that for all F ∈ φ and G ∈ χ contains 00 G ◦ F = {(hn, mi, x, y) ∈ N × X × X |∃z.(n, x, z) ∈ F, (m, z, y) ∈ G} Here, h−, −i is the pairing combinator from the definition at the beginning of this introduction.
Recommended publications
  • Categorical Semantics of Constructive Set Theory
    Categorical semantics of constructive set theory Beim Fachbereich Mathematik der Technischen Universit¨atDarmstadt eingereichte Habilitationsschrift von Benno van den Berg, PhD aus Emmen, die Niederlande 2 Contents 1 Introduction to the thesis 7 1.1 Logic and metamathematics . 7 1.2 Historical intermezzo . 8 1.3 Constructivity . 9 1.4 Constructive set theory . 11 1.5 Algebraic set theory . 15 1.6 Contents . 17 1.7 Warning concerning terminology . 18 1.8 Acknowledgements . 19 2 A unified approach to algebraic set theory 21 2.1 Introduction . 21 2.2 Constructive set theories . 24 2.3 Categories with small maps . 25 2.3.1 Axioms . 25 2.3.2 Consequences . 29 2.3.3 Strengthenings . 31 2.3.4 Relation to other settings . 32 2.4 Models of set theory . 33 2.5 Examples . 35 2.6 Predicative sheaf theory . 36 2.7 Predicative realizability . 37 3 Exact completion 41 3.1 Introduction . 41 3 4 CONTENTS 3.2 Categories with small maps . 45 3.2.1 Classes of small maps . 46 3.2.2 Classes of display maps . 51 3.3 Axioms for classes of small maps . 55 3.3.1 Representability . 55 3.3.2 Separation . 55 3.3.3 Power types . 55 3.3.4 Function types . 57 3.3.5 Inductive types . 58 3.3.6 Infinity . 60 3.3.7 Fullness . 61 3.4 Exactness and its applications . 63 3.5 Exact completion . 66 3.6 Stability properties of axioms for small maps . 73 3.6.1 Representability . 74 3.6.2 Separation . 74 3.6.3 Power types .
    [Show full text]
  • Notes Towards Homology in Characteristic One
    Notes Towards Homology in Characteristic One David Jaz Myers Abstract In their paper Homological Algebra in Characteristic One, Connes and Consani develop techniques of Grandis to do homological calculations with boolean modules { commutative idempotent monoids. This is a writeup of notes taken during a course given by Consani in Fall of 2017 explaining some of these ideas. This note is in flux, use at your own peril. Though the integers Z are the initial ring, they are rather complex. Their Krull dimension is 1, suggesting that they are the functions on a curve; but each of the epimorphisms out of them has a different characteristic, so they are not a curve over any single field. This basic observation, and many more interesting and less basic observations, leads one to wonder about other possible bases for the algebraic geometry of the integers. Could there be an \absolute base", a field over which all other fields lie? What could such a “field” be? As a first approach, let's consider the characteristic of this would-be absolute base field. Since it must lie under the finite fields, it should also be finite, and therefore its characteristic must divide the order of all finite fields. There is only one number which divides all prime powers (and also divides 0): the number 1 itself. Therefore, we are looking for a “field of characteristic one". Now, the axioms of a ring are too restrictive to allow for such an object. Let's free ourselves up by considering semirings, also known as rigs { rings without negatives.
    [Show full text]
  • Harish-Chandra 1923–1983
    NATIONAL ACADEMY OF SCIENCES HARISH- C HANDRA 1 9 2 3 – 1 9 8 3 A Biographical Memoir by R O G E R H O W E Any opinions expressed in this memoir are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the National Academy of Sciences. Biographical Memoir COPYRIGHT 2011 NATIONAL ACADEMY OF SCIENCES WASHINGTON, D.C. Photo by Herman Landshoff; Courtesy Archives of the Institute for Advanced Study. HARISH-CHANDRA October 11, 1923–October 12, 1983 BY ROGER HOWE He taught them the Kshatria code of honor: that a warrior may never refuse a challenge…. The Five Sons of Pandu, The Story of the Mahabharata Retold by Elizabeth Seeger ARISH-CHANDRA WAS, if not the exclusive architect, cer- Htainly the chief engineer of harmonic analysis on semisimple Lie groups. This subject, with roots deep in mathematical physics and analysis, is a synthesis of Fou- rier analysis, special functions and invariant theory, and it has become a basic tool in analytic number theory, via the theory of automorphic forms. It essentially did not ex- ist before World War II, but in very large part because of the labors of Harish-Chandra, it became one of the major mathematical edifices of the second half of the twentieth century. Harish-Chandra was born in 1923 in Uttar Pradesh, in northern India. His family belonged to the Kshatria (war- rior) caste. Kshatria traditionally were rulers, landowners, and military leaders, and more recently have commonly been businessmen or civil servants. Harish-Chandra’s father, Chandrakishore, was a civil engineer who monitored and maintained the dikes and irrigation canals that sustain agri- 3 B IOGRA P HICAL MEMOIRS culture on the North Indian plains.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1305.5974V1 [Math-Ph]
    INTRODUCTION TO SPORADIC GROUPS for physicists Luis J. Boya∗ Departamento de F´ısica Te´orica Universidad de Zaragoza E-50009 Zaragoza, SPAIN MSC: 20D08, 20D05, 11F22 PACS numbers: 02.20.a, 02.20.Bb, 11.24.Yb Key words: Finite simple groups, sporadic groups, the Monster group. Juan SANCHO GUIMERA´ In Memoriam Abstract We describe the collection of finite simple groups, with a view on physical applications. We recall first the prime cyclic groups Zp, and the alternating groups Altn>4. After a quick revision of finite fields Fq, q = pf , with p prime, we consider the 16 families of finite simple groups of Lie type. There are also 26 extra “sporadic” groups, which gather in three interconnected “generations” (with 5+7+8 groups) plus the Pariah groups (6). We point out a couple of physical applications, in- cluding constructing the biggest sporadic group, the “Monster” group, with close to 1054 elements from arguments of physics, and also the relation of some Mathieu groups with compactification in string and M-theory. ∗[email protected] arXiv:1305.5974v1 [math-ph] 25 May 2013 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Generaldescriptionofthework . 3 1.2 Initialmathematics............................ 7 2 Generalities about groups 14 2.1 Elementarynotions............................ 14 2.2 Theframeworkorbox .......................... 16 2.3 Subgroups................................. 18 2.4 Morphisms ................................ 22 2.5 Extensions................................. 23 2.6 Familiesoffinitegroups ......................... 24 2.7 Abeliangroups .............................. 27 2.8 Symmetricgroup ............................. 28 3 More advanced group theory 30 3.1 Groupsoperationginspaces. 30 3.2 Representations.............................. 32 3.3 Characters.Fourierseries . 35 3.4 Homological algebra and extension theory . 37 3.5 Groupsuptoorder16..........................
    [Show full text]
  • Ordered Tensor Categories and Representations of the Mackey Lie Algebra of Infinite Matrices
    Ordered tensor categories and representations of the Mackey Lie algebra of infinite matrices Alexandru Chirvasitu, Ivan Penkov To Jean-Louis Koszul on his 95th birthday Abstract We introduce (partially) ordered Grothendieck categories and apply results on their structure to the study of categories of representations of the Mackey Lie algebra of infinite matrices M M gl (V; V∗). Here gl (V; V∗) is the Lie algebra of endomorphisms of a nondegenerate pairing of countably infinite-dimensional vector spaces V∗ ⊗ V ! K, where K is the base field. Tensor M representations of gl (V; V∗) are defined as arbitrary subquotients of finite direct sums of tensor ∗ ⊗m ⊗n ⊗p ∗ products (V ) ⊗ (V∗) ⊗ V where V denotes the algebraic dual of V . The category 3 M which they comprise, extends a category M previously studied in [5, 15, Tgl (V;V∗) Tgl (V;V∗) 3 20]. Our main result is that M is a finite-length, Koszul self-dual, tensor category Tgl (V;V∗) with a certain universal property that makes it into a “categorified algebra" defined by means of a handful of generators and relations. This result uses essentially the general properties of ordered Grothendieck categories, which yield also simpler proofs of some facts about the 3 category M established in [15]. Finally, we discuss the extension of M obtained Tgl (V;V∗) Tgl (V;V∗) ∗ by adjoining the algebraic dual (V∗) of V∗. Key words: Mackey Lie algebra, tensor category, Koszulity MSC 2010: 17B65, 17B10, 16T15 Contents 1 Background 3 2 Ordered Grothendieck categories5 2.1 Definition and characterization of indecomposable injectives..............5 2.2 Bounds on non-vanishing ext functors..........................7 2.3 C as a comodule category.................................8 2.4 C as a highest weight category...............................8 2.5 Universal properties for C and CFIN ............................9 2.6 The monoidal case....................................
    [Show full text]
  • Between Model Theory and Combinatorics
    INFINITE LIMITS OF FINITE-DIMENSIONAL PERMUTATION STRUCTURES, AND THEIR AUTOMORPHISM GROUPS: BETWEEN MODEL THEORY AND COMBINATORICS BY SAMUEL WALKER BRAUNFELD A dissertation submitted to the School of Graduate Studies Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in Mathematics Written under the direction of Gregory Cherlin And approved by New Brunswick, New Jersey May, 2018 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Infinite Limits of Finite-Dimensional Permutation Structures, and their Automorphism Groups: Between Model Theory and Combinatorics by SAMUEL WALKER BRAUNFELD Dissertation Director: Gregory Cherlin In the course of classifying the homogeneous permutations, Cameron introduced the viewpoint of permutations as structures in a language of two linear orders [7], and this structural viewpoint is taken up here. The majority of this thesis is concerned with Cameron's problem of classifying the homogeneous structures in a language of finitely many linear orders, which we call finite-dimensional permutation structures. Towards this problem, we present a construction that we conjecture produces all such structures. Some evidence for this conjecture is given, including the classification of the homogeneous 3-dimensional permutation structures. We next consider the topological dynamics, in the style of Kechris, Pestov, and Todorˇcevi´c,of the automorphism groups of the homogeneous finite-dimensional per- mutation structures we have constructed, which requires proving a structural Ramsey theorem for all the associated amalgamation classes. Because the ;-definable equiv- alence relations in these homogeneous finite-dimensional permutation structures may form arbitrary finite distributive lattices, the model-theoretic algebraic closure opera- tion may become quite complex, and so we require the framework recently introduced ii by Hubiˇcka and Neˇsetril [16].
    [Show full text]
  • ON the UNIVERSAL EXTENSIONS in TANNAKIAN CATEGORIES Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Notation 4 3. Universal Extensions 5 4. Variat
    ON THE UNIVERSAL EXTENSIONS IN TANNAKIAN CATEGORIES MARCO D'ADDEZIO AND HEL´ ENE` ESNAULT Abstract. We use the notion of universal extension in a linear abelian category to study extensions of variations of mixed Hodge structure and convergent and overconvergent isocrystals. The results we obtain apply, for example, to prove the exactness of some homotopy sequences for these categories and to study F -able isocrystals. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Notation 4 3. Universal extensions 5 4. Variations of mixed Hodge structure 7 5. Isocrystals 10 Appendix A. Observable functors 14 References 17 1. Introduction In this note we define and construct universal extensions (Definition 3.1) of objects belonging to a linear abelian category. This construction is convenient to study all the possible extensions of two objects of the category at the same time. On the one hand, a universal extension enjoys more properties than single extensions. On the other hand, every non-trivial extension between two objects embeds into a universal extension (Proposition 3.4). Some examples of universal extensions appeared already in the literature. For example, in [EH06, x4], universal extensions are used to study the category of flat connections over a smooth variety in characteristic 0. In our article, we use universal extensions to solve some open problems on variations of mixed Hodge structure and convergent and overconvergent isocrystals. Let us present our first application. Let X be a smooth connected complex variety. Write MHS for the category of graded-polarisable finite-dimensional mixed Q-Hodge structures, LS(X) for the category of finite-rank Q-local systems over X, and M(X) for the category of (graded-polarisable) admissible variations of mixed Q-Hodge structure.
    [Show full text]
  • An Induction Theorem for the Unit Groups of Burnside Rings of 2-Groups
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Journal of Algebra 289 (2005) 105–127 provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector www.elsevier.com/locate/jalgebra An induction theorem for the unit groups of Burnside rings of 2-groups Ergün Yalçın Department of Mathematics, Bilkent University, Ankara 06800, Turkey Received 11 May 2004 Communicated by Michel Broué Abstract × Let G be a 2-group and B(G) denote the group of units of the Burnside ring of G. For each × × subquotient H/K of G, there is a generalized induction map from B(H/K) to B(G) defined as the composition of inflation and multiplicative induction maps. We prove that the product of × × generalized induction maps B(H/K) → B(G) is surjective when the product is taken over the set of all subquotients that are isomorphic to the trivial group or a dihedral 2-group of order 2n with n 4. As an application, we give an algebraic proof for a theorem by Tornehave [The unit group for the Burnside ring of a 2-group, Aarhus Universitet Preprint series 1983/84 41, May 1984] × which states that tom Dieck’s exponential map from the real representation ring of G to B(G) is surjective. We also give a sufficient condition for the surjectivity of the exponential map from the × Burnside ring of G to B(G) . 2005 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. Keywords: Units of Burnside ring; Real representation ring 1. Introduction The Burnside ring of a finite group G is defined to be the Grothendieck ring of the semi-ring generated by isomorphism classes of finite (left) G-sets where the addition and E-mail address: [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • Graph Minor from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia Contents
    Graph minor From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Contents 1 2 × 2 real matrices 1 1.1 Profile ................................................. 1 1.2 Equi-areal mapping .......................................... 2 1.3 Functions of 2 × 2 real matrices .................................... 2 1.4 2 × 2 real matrices as complex numbers ............................... 3 1.5 References ............................................... 4 2 Abelian group 5 2.1 Definition ............................................... 5 2.2 Facts ................................................. 5 2.2.1 Notation ........................................... 5 2.2.2 Multiplication table ...................................... 6 2.3 Examples ............................................... 6 2.4 Historical remarks .......................................... 6 2.5 Properties ............................................... 6 2.6 Finite abelian groups ......................................... 7 2.6.1 Classification ......................................... 7 2.6.2 Automorphisms ....................................... 7 2.7 Infinite abelian groups ........................................ 8 2.7.1 Torsion groups ........................................ 9 2.7.2 Torsion-free and mixed groups ................................ 9 2.7.3 Invariants and classification .................................. 9 2.7.4 Additive groups of rings ................................... 9 2.8 Relation to other mathematical topics ................................. 10 2.9 A note on the typography ......................................
    [Show full text]
  • Quillen K-Theory: Lecture Notes
    Quillen K-Theory: Lecture Notes Satya Mandal, U. of Kansas 2 April 2017 27 August 2017 6, 10, 13, 20, 25 September 2017 2, 4, 9, 11, 16, 18, 23, 25, 30 October 2017 1, 6, 8, 13, 15, 20, 27, 29 November 2017 December 4, 6 2 Dedicated to my mother! Contents 1 Background from Category Theory 7 1.1 Preliminary Definitions . .7 1.1.1 Classical and Standard Examples . .9 1.1.2 Pullback, Pushforward, kernel and cokernel . 12 1.1.3 Adjoint Functors and Equivalence of Categories . 16 1.2 Additive and Abelian Categories . 17 1.2.1 Abelian Categories . 18 1.3 Exact Category . 20 1.4 Localization and Quotient Categories . 23 1.4.1 Quotient of Exact Categories . 27 1.5 Frequently Used Lemmas . 28 1.5.1 Pullback and Pushforward Lemmas . 29 1.5.2 The Snake Lemma . 30 1.5.3 Limits and coLimits . 36 2 Homotopy Theory 37 2.1 Elements of Topological Spaces . 37 2.1.1 Frequently used Topologies . 41 2.2 Homotopy . 42 2.3 Fibrations . 47 2.4 Construction of Fibrations . 49 2.5 CW Complexes . 53 2.5.1 Product of CW Complexes . 57 2.5.2 Frequently Used Results . 59 3 4 CONTENTS 3 Simplicial and coSimplicial Sets 61 3.1 Introduction . 61 3.2 Simplicial Sets . 61 3.3 Geometric Realization . 65 3.3.1 The CW Structure on jKj ....................... 68 3.4 The Homotopy Groups of Simplicial Sets . 73 3.4.1 The Combinatorial Definition . 73 3.4.2 The Definitions of Homotopy Groups .
    [Show full text]
  • Awodey-Butz-Simpson
    Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (2014) 428–502 Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect Annals of Pure and Applied Logic www.elsevier.com/locate/apal Relating first-order set theories, toposes and categories of classes ∗ Steve Awodey a,CarstenButzb,1, Alex Simpson c, ,2, Thomas Streicher d a Department of Philosophy, Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, USA b IT University of Copenhagen, Denmark c LFCS, School of Informatics, University of Edinburgh, UK d Fachbereich Mathematik, Technische Universität Darmstadt, Germany article info abstract Article history: This paper introduces Basic Intuitionistic Set Theory BIST, and investigates it as a first- Received 22 December 2010 order set theory extending the internal logic of elementary toposes. Given an elementary Received in revised form 12 December 2012 topos, together with the extra structure of a directed structural system of inclusions (dssi) Accepted 12 May 2013 on the topos, a forcing-style interpretation of the language of first-order set theory in the Available online 8 July 2013 topos is given, which conservatively extends the internal logic of the topos. This forcing MSC: interpretation applies to an arbitrary elementary topos, since any such is equivalent to one 03E70 carrying a dssi. We prove that the set theory BIST+Coll (where Coll is the strong Collection 03F50 axiom) is sound and complete relative to forcing interpretations in toposes with natural 03G30 numbers object (nno). Furthermore, in the case that the structural system of inclusions is 18B05 superdirected, the full Separation schema is modelled. We show that all cocomplete and realizability toposes can (up to equivalence) be endowed with such superdirected systems Keywords: of inclusions.
    [Show full text]
  • Group Structures on Families of Subsets of a Group
    Group Structures on Families of Subsets of a Group Mario G´omez, Sergio R. L´opez-Permouth , Fernando Mazariegos, Alejandro Jos´eVargas De Le´on and Rigoberto Zelada Cifuentes October 18, 2018 Abstract A binary operation on any set induces a binary operation on its sub- sets. We explore families of subsets of a group that become a group under the induced operation and refer to such families as power groups of the given group. Our results serve to characterize groups in terms of their power groups. In particular, we consider when the only power groups of a group are the factor groups of its subgroups and when that is the case up to isomorphism. We prove that the former are precisely those groups for which every element has finite order and provide examples to illustrate that the latter is not always the case. In the process we consider sev- eral natural questions such as whether the identity element of the group must belong to the identity element of a power group or the inverse of an element in a power group must consist of the inverses of its elements. 1 Introduction Traditionally, group theory has been built upon understanding the subgroups and the factor groups of a given group. In other words, our understanding of groups has largely rested on understanding their subquotients (factors of subgroups or subgroups of factors; it’s the same.) We propose the power groups of a group as a larger collection of groups that might give us a better insight into arXiv:1604.01119v2 [math.GR] 26 Aug 2016 the structure of the original group.
    [Show full text]