Class of Coanalytic (= U,')4 Sets Based on the (Known) Determinateness of Open (= Iol) Sets

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Class of Coanalytic (= U,')4 Sets Based on the (Known) Determinateness of Open (= Iol) Sets SOME CONSEQUENCES OF THE AXIOM OF DEFINABLE DETERMINA TENESS* BY J. W. ADDISON AND YIANNIs N. MOSCHOvAKIS UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY, AND UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, LOS ANGELES Communicated by David Blkckwell, January 11, 1968 Introduction.-With each sut set A of the set "w of functions from X to W we associate the following game: Players I and II successively choose natural numbers with I starting, and if the resulting infinite sequence is in A, then I wins; otherwise II wins. The set A is determinate' iff either I or II has a winning strategy. It can be shown in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC) that nondeterminate sets exist;l however, no definable set has been proved in ZFC to be nondeterminate.2 Recently, Blackwell3 found an elegant proof of the reduction principle for the class of coanalytic (= U,')4 sets based on the (known) determinateness of open (= Iol) sets. In this note we show that the hypothesis of determinateness for projective (= 2;, for some k) sets yields consequences about the projective hier- archy on 'o and the analytical (= 2,' for some k) hierarchies on cW and 'W: in particular, the separation and reduction problems at all levels of these hier- archies are settled and hierarchies are constructed for the classes Ak' (all k > 0) and Ak' (all odd k). One of the oldest puzzles in the theory of definability has been the strange "flip-flop" behavior of separation principles in the projective hieratchy-since 1935 they have been known to hold for Ho,0111, and H12' sets and to fail for oe,1 I111, and Z2' sets.5 In 1962, one of us (J. W. A.) found a clue to the hidden forces responsible for this behavior in the discovery of a proof of the strong separation theorem for Z11 sets6 which was a "vectorization" of the corresponding theorem for Hol sets; he proposed' that this vectorization be extended to 121 and 1131 sets as a method of "smoking out" a new axiom of set theory.8 Blackwell's proof suggested to him a way of developing the vectorization technique to carry the first separation principle from s-l (where true) to tI+ki1, for all k.9 Upon inspection of this argument, the sought-for axiom was apparent. When one of us (Y. N. M.) saw this work, he recognized that the determinateness of projective sets implies the prewellordering theorem below (for k > 0), which then settles separation, reduction, and several other definability questions at all levels of the hierarchies. D. A. Martin, also inspired by Blackwell's proof, independently found several of the results below, including the separation and reduction theorems.10 Steinhauss" has urged for several years the adoption as an axiom of set theory of "the axiom of determinateness," according to which all subsets of '0w are determinate. But since this axiom contradicts the axiom of choice, it has not found wide support. We would propose instead the axiom of definable deter- minateness, according to which every subset of 'w ordinal definable from elements of Wa is determinate. For several reasons, including its spontaneous emergence as 708 Downloaded by guest on October 3, 2021 VOL. 59,1968 MATHEMATICS: ADDISON AND MOSCHOVAKIS 709 a key to the rich and orderly consequences given below, we foresee an increas- ingly important role for it in the future of set theory. (1) Terminology.-The universes whose subsets we study are all product spaces t= X1 X . X Xi, where each Xi is either w or low. We let x, y, z, w be variables over SC, let k, 1, m, n be variables over co, and let a, fl, -y be variables over '%o. If x is an i-tuple and y a j-tuple, by (xy) we mean the (i + j)-tuple whose first i components are the components of x and whose last j components are the components of y. Similarly, if S = X. X ... X Xiand% = Y, X... X Yithen9C X = X, X ... XXiX Y X ... X Yi. Strategies o, r are functions from the set Sq (= I -w:n E w }) of finite sequences of natural numbers to co. By a * r (read: sigma-clash-tau) we mean the play resulting by pitting a against r-formally (a * r)o(n) = a((a * T)iln), (a * r)i(n) = T((T * T)oln+i), (where (a)o(n) = a(2n) and (a),(n) = a(2n + 1)). A prewellordering of a set S is a reflexive, transitive, connected, well-founded relation with field S-from being a wellordering it lacks only antisymmetry. (A prewellordering _ of S is determined by a unique order-preserving function f from S to an ordinal: x < y <- f(x) <f(y).) The effect of the prewellordering theorem below is to force the behavior of the higher levels in the projective hierarchy back to that of the lo' and [lo' sets and thus to make an inner-quantifier rather than an outer-quantifier notation more convenient in presenting our results. Accordingly, we let Ek' (epsilon-i-k) and Tk' (upsilon-1ik) be the classes of sets definable in (k + l)-function-quantifier forms on a recursive matrix with inner quanti- fier existential and universal, respectively. Thus Ea 1 = 2;2,, T2k' = H2k', E2k + 11 = HU + 11 T2U + 11 = 22k + 1', and An' = 2;fln lln = E flnTn'. The classes boldface Ek', TO' are defined similarly. A subset C of w X 9 is Ekl-universal for 9C iff C is Ek' and for every Ek' subset A of 9C there is some n E Xso that x E A *-* (n,x) E C. It is easy to see that if C is Ek'-uni- versal for Qw X $C, then for every Ekl subset A of $X there is some n E co and some a E low so that x C A *-* (n,a,x) E C. For each X and each k choose a fixed Ekl subset Ck(Q ) of X X $ which is EkL-universal for $C. An Ek -code for a subset A of $C is any n C w such that x E A +-* (n,x) e Ck(C). An EJ' code for a subset A of $C is any (n,a) C w X low such that t E A -* (nac,x) E Ck(ww X $). A Akl-code (Akl-code) for A is any (xy) such that x and y are Ekl-codes (Ekl- codes) for A and $C - A, respectively. (2) THE PREWELLORDERING THEOREM.-Let $C be anyfinite product of copies of wand 'w, let 1 be an even number inw, and let kbelor 1+1. If every All subset of Ax is determinate, then there is a subset Wk of w X $C, Ekl-universal for SC, and a pre- wellordering <k of Wk whose initial segments are uniformly Akl, i.e., for which there is a primitive recursive f such that for each w C Wk, f(w) is a Akl-code for {Z: ZCEWk&Z<kW}. Proof: By induction on 1. For 1 = 0, let Wo (= tz: 3mR(zm)} for re- cursive R) be 240-universal for 9C (Wo C woX 9C), and put z <ow ÷- z,w E Wo & the least m such that R(z,m) < the least n such that R(w,n). Induction step. Case I: k (= 1) is even. Let z E Wk +-*3 a (za) C Wk- and let z < k W (- zW C Wk & the < k-l-least (z, a) < k-1 the <k-l-least (w43). Case II: k (= 1 + 1) is odd. Let z E Wk - Va (za) C Wk-1 and let Z <k W "-ZW £ Wk & (3 strategy r for II)(V strategy orfor I) [(z, (a * T)o) <k-1 (WY (a * 7)1) ]- Downloaded by guest on October 3, 2021 710 MATHEMATICS: ADDISON AND MOSCHOVAKIS PROC. N. A. S. Note that in defining Wk and < k for $C we use the induction hypothesis for 9 X co. That W1 is Ek-universal for $t is immediate and that the initial segments of <k are uniformly Ak' follows easily by induction using the determinateness hypothesis on All. That <k is a prewellordering is immediate in the basis, easy in Case I of the induction step, and follows by an elementary argument from Al determinateness in Case II of the induction step. (3) Logical Analysis of the Argument.-The argument above is intimately involved with quantifiers on ordered pairs of variables or binary quantifiers, including the standard "decomposable" quantifiers 33, ]V, V3, and VV (where 33ab = 3a 3b, etc.). The conditional 3Va,b 4- V3b,a 4) is a basic principle of logic; on the other hand, many central ideas in mathematics revolve about a special circumstance where the not logically valid converse conditional V3'b,aa 3Va,b 4 holds. For example, let < be a prewellordering of 9C; then {(x,y): 3v'a,/ (x,a) < (yS)} equals (x,y): V 3, a (x,a) < (y,3)} and prewellorders St. (i) This can be viewed as a key combinatorial fact behind the odd-to-even steps of the theorem. The dual principle with 3V13,a and V3a,# (which corresponds to taking suprema instead of infima) fails, suggesting a search for other quantifiers TV and 3V squeezing so closely together between 3V and V3 that they more often coincide, i.e., so that for more S 3V13,a S(al3) -* 3V/,a S(a,3) V3a,g> S(a,3) -- V3a,3 S(a,3).12 (#) Now the "game quantifiers" 3V and V3 defined by 3V3,a S(a,13) -> (3 -rEzw)(VEw) S((a * r)o, (a * r)1) and its dual satisfy (#a) and satisfy (# *-) just if S is codeferminate.
Recommended publications
  • The Envelope of a Pointclass Under a Local Determinacy Hypothesis
    THE ENVELOPE OF A POINTCLASS UNDER A LOCAL DETERMINACY HYPOTHESIS TREVOR M. WILSON Abstract. Given an inductive-like pointclass Γ and assuming the Ax- iom of Determinacy, Martin identified and analyzede the pointclass con- taining the norm relations of the next semiscale beyond Γ, if one exists. We show that much of Martin's analysis can be carriede out assuming only ZF + DCR + Det(∆Γ). This generalization requires arguments from Kechris{Woodin [10] ande e Martin [13]. The results of [10] and [13] can then be recovered as immediate corollaries of the general analysis. We also obtain a new proof of a theorem of Woodin on divergent models of AD+, as well as a new result regarding the derived model at an inde- structibly weakly compact limit of Woodin cardinals. Introduction Given an inductive-like pointclass Γ, Martin introduced a pointclass (which we call the envelope of Γ, following [22])e whose main feature is that it con- tains the prewellorderingse of the next scale (or semiscale) beyond Γ, if such a (semi)scale exists. This work was distributed as \Notes on the nexte Suslin cardinal," as cited in Jackson [3]. It is unpublished, so we use [3] as our reference instead for several of Martin's arguments. Martin's analysis used the assumption of the Axiom of Determinacy. We reformulate the notion of the envelope in such a way that many of its essen- tial properties can by derived without assuming AD. Instead we will work in the base theory ZF+DCR for the duration of the paper, stating determinacy hypotheses only when necessary.
    [Show full text]
  • The Realm of Ordinal Analysis
    The Realm of Ordinal Analysis Michael Rathjen Department of Pure Mathematics, University of Leeds Leeds LS2 9JT, United Kingdom Denn die Pioniere der Mathematik hatten sich von gewissen Grundlagen brauchbare Vorstellungen gemacht, aus denen sich Schl¨usse,Rechnungsarten, Resultate ergaben, deren bem¨achtigten sich die Physiker, um neue Ergebnisse zu erhalten, und endlich kamen die Techniker, nahmen oft bloß die Resultate, setzten neue Rechnungen darauf und es entstanden Maschinen. Und pl¨otzlich, nachdem alles in sch¨onste Existenz gebracht war, kamen die Mathematiker - jene, die ganz innen herumgr¨ubeln, - darauf, daß etwas in den Grundlagen der ganzen Sache absolut nicht in Ordnung zu bringen sei; tats¨achlich, sie sahen zuunterst nach und fanden, daß das ganze Geb¨audein der Luft stehe. Aber die Maschinen liefen! Man muß daraufhin annehmen, daß unser Dasein bleicher Spuk ist; wir leben es, aber eigentlich nur auf Grund eines Irrtums, ohne den es nicht entstanden w¨are. ROBERT MUSIL: Der mathematische Mensch (1913) 1 Introduction A central theme running through all the main areas of Mathematical Logic is the classification of sets, functions or theories, by means of transfinite hierarchies whose ordinal levels measure their ‘rank’ or ‘complexity’ in some sense appropriate to the underlying context. In Proof Theory this is manifest in the assignment of ‘proof the- oretic ordinals’ to theories, gauging their ‘consistency strength’ and ‘computational power’. Ordinal-theoretic proof theory came into existence in 1936, springing forth from Gentzen’s head in the course of his consistency proof of arithmetic. To put it roughly, ordinal analyses attach ordinals in a given representation system to formal theories.
    [Show full text]
  • Determinacy and Large Cardinals
    Determinacy and Large Cardinals Itay Neeman∗ Abstract. The principle of determinacy has been crucial to the study of definable sets of real numbers. This paper surveys some of the uses of determinacy, concentrating specifically on the connection between determinacy and large cardinals, and takes this connection further, to the level of games of length ω1. Mathematics Subject Classification (2000). 03E55; 03E60; 03E45; 03E15. Keywords. Determinacy, iteration trees, large cardinals, long games, Woodin cardinals. 1. Determinacy Let ωω denote the set of infinite sequences of natural numbers. For A ⊂ ωω let Gω(A) denote the length ω game with payoff A. The format of Gω(A) is displayed in Diagram 1. Two players, denoted I and II, alternate playing natural numbers forming together a sequence x = hx(n) | n < ωi in ωω called a run of the game. The run is won by player I if x ∈ A, and otherwise the run is won by player II. I x(0) x(2) ...... II x(1) x(3) ...... Diagram 1. The game Gω(A). A game is determined if one of the players has a winning strategy. The set A is ω determined if Gω(A) is determined. For Γ ⊂ P(ω ), det(Γ) denotes the statement that all sets in Γ are determined. Using the axiom of choice, or more specifically using a wellordering of the reals, it is easy to construct a non-determined set A. det(P(ωω)) is therefore false. On the other hand it has become clear through research over the years that det(Γ) is true if all the sets in Γ are definable by some concrete means.
    [Show full text]
  • Effective Descriptive Set Theory
    Effective Descriptive Set Theory Andrew Marks December 14, 2019 1 1 These notes introduce the effective (lightface) Borel, Σ1 and Π1 sets. This study uses ideas and tools from descriptive set theory and computability theory. Our central motivation is in applications of the effective theory to theorems of classical (boldface) descriptive set theory, especially techniques which have no classical analogues. These notes have many errors and are very incomplete. Some important topics not covered include: • The Harrington-Shore-Slaman theorem [HSS] which implies many of the theorems of Section 3. • Steel forcing (see [BD, N, Mo, St78]) • Nonstandard model arguments • Barwise compactness, Jensen's model existence theorem • α-recursion theory • Recent beautiful work of the \French School": Debs, Saint-Raymond, Lecompte, Louveau, etc. These notes are from a class I taught in spring 2019. Thanks to Adam Day, Thomas Gilton, Kirill Gura, Alexander Kastner, Alexander Kechris, Derek Levinson, Antonio Montalb´an,Dean Menezes and Riley Thornton, for helpful conversations and comments on earlier versions of these notes. 1 Contents 1 1 1 1 Characterizing Σ1, ∆1, and Π1 sets 4 1 1.1 Σn formulas, closure properties, and universal sets . .4 1.2 Boldface vs lightface sets and relativization . .5 1 1.3 Normal forms for Σ1 formulas . .5 1.4 Ranking trees and Spector boundedness . .7 1 1.5 ∆1 = effectively Borel . .9 1.6 Computable ordinals, hyperarithmetic sets . 11 1 1.7 ∆1 = hyperarithmetic . 14 x 1 1.8 The hyperjump, !1 , and the analogy between c.e. and Π1 .... 15 2 Basic tools 18 2.1 Existence proofs via completeness results .
    [Show full text]
  • Souslin Quasi-Orders and Bi-Embeddability of Uncountable
    Souslin quasi-orders and bi-embeddability of uncountable structures Alessandro Andretta Luca Motto Ros Author address: Universita` di Torino, Dipartimento di Matematica, Via Carlo Alberto, 10, 10123 Torino, Italy E-mail address: [email protected] Universita` di Torino, Dipartimento di Matematica, Via Carlo Alberto, 10, 10123 Torino, Italy E-mail address: [email protected] arXiv:1609.09292v2 [math.LO] 18 Mar 2019 Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Preliminaries and notation 14 3. The generalized Cantor space 22 4. Generalized Borel sets 30 5. Generalized Borel functions 37 6. The generalized Baire space and Baire category 41 7. Standard Borel κ-spaces, κ-analyticquasi-orders,andspacesofcodes 47 8. Infinitary logics and models 55 9. κ-Souslin sets 65 10. The main construction 76 11. Completeness 85 12. Invariant universality 91 13. An alternative approach 106 14. Definable cardinality and reducibility 115 15. Some applications 126 16. Further completeness results 132 Indexes 147 Concepts 147 Symbols 148 Bibliography 151 iii Abstract We provide analogues of the results from [FMR11, CMMR13] (which correspond to the case κ = ω) for arbitrary κ-Souslin quasi-orders on any Polish space, for κ an infinite cardinal smaller than the cardinality of R. These generalizations yield a variety of results concerning the complexity of the embeddability relation between graphs or lattices of size κ, the isometric embeddability relation between complete metric spaces of density character κ, and the linear isometric embeddability relation between (real or complex) Banach spaces of density κ. Received by the editor March 19, 2019. 2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. 03E15, 03E60, 03E45, 03E10, 03E47.
    [Show full text]
  • Contributions to Descriptive Inner Model Theory by Trevor Miles Wilson Doctor of Philosophy in Mathematics University of California, Berkeley Professor John R
    Contributions to Descriptive Inner Model Theory by Trevor Miles Wilson A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Mathematics in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor John R. Steel, Chair Professor W. Hugh Woodin Professor Sherrilyn Roush Fall 2012 Abstract Contributions to Descriptive Inner Model Theory by Trevor Miles Wilson Doctor of Philosophy in Mathematics University of California, Berkeley Professor John R. Steel, Chair Descriptive inner model theory is the study of connections between descript- ive set theory and inner model theory. Such connections form the basis of the core model induction, which we use to prove relative consistency results relating strong forms of the Axiom of Determinacy with the existence of a strong ideal on }!1 (R) having a certain property related to homogeneity. The main innovation is a unified approach to the \gap in scales" step of the core model induction. 1 Contents Introduction iii Acknowledgements v Chapter 1. Forcing strong ideals from determinacy 1 1.1. The theory \ADR + Θ is regular" 1 1.2. Col(!; R)-generic ultrapowers 2 1.3. A covering property for ideals in generic extensions 5 1.4. The covering property for NS!1;R 8 1.5. A c-dense ideal with the covering property 10 Chapter 2. The core model induction 13 2.1. Model operators 14 2.2. F -mice 18 2.3. The Kc;F construction and the KF existence dichotomy 22 F;] 2.4. M1 from a strong pseudo-homogeneous ideal 28 2.5.
    [Show full text]
  • THREE DAYS of Ω-LOGIC the Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms for Set
    THREE DAYS OF Ω-LOGIC PAUL B. LARSON The Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms for set theory with the Axiom of Choice (ZFC) form the most commonly accepted foundations for mathematical practice, yet it is well-known that many mathematical statements are neither proved nor refuted from these axioms. One example is given by G¨odel'sSecond Incompleteness Theorem, which says that no consistent recursive axiom system which is strong enough to describe arithmetic on the integers can prove its own consistency. This presents a prob- lem for those interested in finding an axiomatic basis for mathematics, as the consistency of any such theory would seem to be as well justi- fied as the theory itself. There are many views on how to resolve this situation. While some logicians propose weaker foundations for mathe- matics, some study the question of how to properly extend ZFC. Large cardinal axioms and their many consequences for small sets have been studied as a particularly attractive means to this goal. Large cardinals resolve the projective theory of the real line and banish the various measure-theoretic paradoxes derivable from the Axiom to Choice from the realm of the definable. Moreover, the large cardinal hierarchy itself appears to serve as universal measuring stick for consistency strength, in that the consistency strength of any natural statement of mathemat- ics (over ZFC) can be located on this hierarchy (see [7] for the definitive reference on large cardinals). While there is no technical definition of \large cardinal," Woodin's Ω-logic is an attempt to give a formal definition for the set of con- sequences of large cardinals for rank initial segments of the universe.
    [Show full text]
  • Descriptive Set Theory Second Edition
    Mathematical Surveys and Monographs Volume 155 Descriptive Set Theory Second Edition Yiannis N. Moschovakis American Mathematical Society http://dx.doi.org/10.1090/surv/155 Descriptive Set Theory Second Edition Mathematical Surveys and Monographs Volume 155 Descriptive Set Theory Second Edition Yiannis N. Moschovakis American Mathematical Society Providence, Rhode Island EDITORIAL COMMITTEE Jerry L. Bona Michael G. Eastwood Ralph L. Cohen, Chair J. T. Stafford Benjamin Sudakov 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 03–02; Secondary 03D55, 03E15, 28A05, 54H05. For additional information and updates on this book, visit www.ams.org/bookpages/surv-155 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Moschovakis, Yiannis N. Descriptive set theory / Yiannis N. Moschovakis. – 2nd ed. p. cm. — (Mathematical surveys and monographs ; v. 155) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-8218-4813-5 (alk. paper) 1. Descriptive set theory. I. Title. QA248.M66 2009 511.322—dc22 2009011239 Copying and reprinting. Individual readers of this publication, and nonprofit libraries acting for them, are permitted to make fair use of the material, such as to copy a chapter for use in teaching or research. Permission is granted to quote brief passages from this publication in reviews, provided the customary acknowledgment of the source is given. Republication, systematic copying, or multiple reproduction of any material in this publication is permitted only under license from the American Mathematical Society. Requests for such permission should be addressed to the Acquisitions Department, American Mathematical Society, 201 Charles Street, Providence, Rhode Island 02904-2294, USA. Requests can also be made by e-mail to [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • The Normed Induction Theorem
    The Normed Induction Theorem Yiannis N. Moschovakis UCLA and University of Athens The Soskov meeting, Gjuletchica, 20 September, 2014 and the meeting in honor of Costas Dimitracopoulos, Athens, 3 October, 2014 What it is about ² An operator © : P(X ) !P(X ) on the powerset of a set X is monotone if S ⊆ T =) ©(S) ⊆ ©(T )(S ⊆ T ⊆ X ); and every monotone © has a least ¯xed point © characterized by ©(©) = ©; (8S ⊆ X )[©(S) ⊆ S =) © ⊆ S] ² This set © built up by © is de¯ned explicitly by T © = fS ⊆ X j ©(S) ⊆ Sg; (Exp) and inductively by the ordinal recursion S S © = » ©»; where ©» = ©( ´<» ©´): (Ind) ² The Normed Induction Theorem gives simple|often best possible|classi¯cations of ©, especially in Descriptive Set Theory Yiannis N. Moschovakis: The Normed Induction Theorem 1/16 Outline ² The arithmetical and analytical hierarchies on ! and N (3 slides) ² Borel sets and their codings (2 slides) ² Norms and the prewellordering property (2 slides) ² The main result and some of its consequences (5 slides) ² The story of O (2 slides) ² Results by several people will be discussed ² The basic references for proofs are the Second Edition of my Descriptive Set Theory book and the article Kleene's amazing 2nd Recursion Theorem, both posted on www.math.ucla.edu/»ynm Yiannis N. Moschovakis: The Normed Induction Theorem 2/16 Notation and terminology ² ! = f0; 1;:::; g; s; t 2 !, N = (! ! !), the Baire space, ®; ¯ 2 N ² A space is a product X = X1 £ ¢ ¢ ¢ £ Xk where each Xi is ! or N ² A pointset is any P ⊆ X = X1 £ ¢ ¢ ¢ £ Xk and we write synonymously x 2 P () P(x) () P(x1;:::; xk ) ² A pointclass is any collection ¡ of pointsets ² Restriction: For each X ,¡¹X = fP ⊆ X j P 2 ¡g ² Relativization: ¡(®) = fP® j P 2 ¡g where P®(x) () P(®; x) t0+1 t1+1 tn¡1+1 ht0;:::; tn¡1i = 2 3 ¢ ¢ ¢ pn¡1 ®(t) = h®(0); : : : ®(t ¡ 1)i; n(t) = n if x = (x1;:::; xk ) 2 X ; then x(t) = hx1(t);:::; xk (t)i 0 ® = ¸t®(t + 1) (®)i = ¸s®(hi; si) ² The results we will discuss hold for all recursive Polish spaces |and \boldface versions" of them hold for all Polish spaces Yiannis N.
    [Show full text]
  • Set Theory and the Analyst
    European Journal of Mathematics (2019) 5:2–48 https://doi.org/10.1007/s40879-018-0278-1 REVIEW ARTICLE Set theory and the analyst Nicholas H. Bingham1 · Adam J. Ostaszewski2 For Zbigniew Grande, on his 70th birthday, and in memoriam: Stanisław Saks (1897–1942), Cross of Valour, Paragon of Polish Analysis, Cousin-in-law Then to the rolling heaven itself I cried, Asking what lamp had destiny to guide Her little children stumbling in the dark. And ‘A blind understanding’ heaven replied. – The Rubaiyat of Omar Khayyam Received: 14 January 2018 / Revised: 15 June 2018 / Accepted: 12 July 2018 / Published online: 12 October 2018 © The Author(s) 2018 Abstract This survey is motivated by specific questions arising in the similarities and contrasts between (Baire) category and (Lebesgue) measure—category-measure duality and non-duality, as it were. The bulk of the text is devoted to a summary, intended for the working analyst, of the extensive background in set theory and logic needed to discuss such matters: to quote from the preface of Kelley (General Topology, Van Nostrand, Toronto, 1995): “what every young analyst should know”. Keywords Axiom of choice · Dependent choice · Model theory · Constructible hierarchy · Ultraproducts · Indiscernibles · Forcing · Martin’s axiom · Analytical hierarchy · Determinacy and large cardinals · Structure of the real line · Category and measure Mathematics Subject Classification 03E15 · 03E25 · 03E30 · 03E35 · 03E55 · 01A60 · 01A61 B Adam J. Ostaszewski [email protected] Nicholas H. Bingham [email protected] 1 Mathematics Department, Imperial College, London SW7 2AZ, UK 2 Mathematics Department, London School of Economics, Houghton Street, London WC2A 2AE, UK 123 Set theory and the analyst 3 Contents 1 Introduction ............................................
    [Show full text]
  • Determinacy Maximum
    Dmytro Taranovsky November 5, 2003 Determinacy Maximum Abstract: We propose a new determinacy hypothesis for transfinite games, use the hypothesis to extend the perfect set theorem, prove relationships between various determinacy hypotheses, expose inconsistent versions of determinacy, and provide a philosophical justification for determinacy. Introduction Many natural propositions that are undecidable in ZFC can be resolved by determinacy hypotheses. For example, projective determinacy provides a reasonably complete theory of second order arithmetic. This paper introduces a strong determinacy hypothesis, which we hope resolves more of the natural undecidable propositions. First, we formalize the notion of the transfinite game and the strategies. The game is a perfect information game played by two players. The players move in turns, and at limit ordinals the first player moves. Each move consists of picking a member of the nonempty set of allowed moves, called the move set. A game on S means a game whose move set is S. A position is a sequence of moves at a point before the game ends. Once the sequence reaches a certain ordinal length, called the length of the game, the game ends. The play is the sequence of all moves selected by the players. If the sequence of moves belongs to the payoff set for the game (the payoff set is determined before the game starts), then the first player wins; otherwise, the second player wins. A strategy for a player is a mapping that for every position for which it is the player's turn to move assigns a valid move. For a particular game, a strategy for one player is called winning if the player wins the game provided that he follows the strategy regardless of the choices of the other player.
    [Show full text]
  • An Undecidable Extension of Morley's Theorem on the Number Of
    AN UNDECIDABLE EXTENSION OF MORLEY’S THEOREM ON THE NUMBER OF COUNTABLE MODELS CHRISTOPHER J. EAGLE1, CLOVIS HAMEL2, SANDRA MULLER¨ 3, AND FRANKLIN D. TALL4 Abstract. We show that Morley’s theorem on the number of countable mod- els of a countable first-order theory becomes an undecidable statement when extended to second-order logic. More generally, we calculate the number of equivalence classes of σ-projective equivalence relations in several models of set theory. Our methods include random and Cohen forcing, Woodin cardinals and Inner Model Theory. 1. Introduction Vaught’s Conjecture, which asserts that a countable first-order theory must have either at most countably many or exactly 2ℵ0 many non-isomorphic countable mod- els, is one of the most important problems in Model Theory. While the question itself is model-theoretic, it is known to have deep connections to both Descriptive Set Theory and Topological Dynamics. Since Vaught’s original paper [46], Vaught’s Conjecture has been verified for a number of classes of theories, such as theories of trees [39], ω-stable theories [37], o-minimal theories [28], and varieties (in the sense of universal algebra) [14], among others. A strong positive result about Vaught’s Conjecture that applies to all first-order theories is a result of the late Michael Morley [29], which states that the number of isomorphism classes of countable models of a countable first-order theory is always ℵ0 either at most ℵ1 or exactly 2 . In this form Morley’s Theorem requires no proof at all if we are in a universe of set theory where the continuum hypothesis holds.
    [Show full text]