Kant, Husserl, and Analyticity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Kant, Husserl, and Analyticity Kant, Husserl, and Analyticity Author: Evan Clarke Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/bc-ir:103735 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2014 Copyright is held by the author. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Philosophy KANT, HUSSERL, AND ANALYTICITY a dissertation by EVAN CLARKE submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2014 © EVAN DOUGLAS CLARKE 2014 KANT, HUSSERL, AND ANALYTICITY Evan Clarke Advisor: Andrea Staiti This study concerns the nature and role of analyticity in the work of Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl. Its initial goal is that of clarifying the place of analytic judgment in Kant's critical project. Against the widely held assumption that analytic judgment has no role to play in the critical project, I show that analytic judgment has a precise and genuinely important role to play in the context of Kant's metaphysics. Analytic judgment has the role of clarifying our a priori conceptual repertoire and thus of making possible the synthetic a priori judgments that are properly constitutive of metaphysics. The next goal of the study is that of unifying and defending Kant's various characterizations of analytic judgment. Whereas a number of commentators have suggested that Kant is vague or ambivalent as regards the properties of analytic judgment, I show that we can extract a clear, consistent picture of analytic judgment from his work. The key to seeing this, I argue, is becoming clear on Kant's basic assumptions concerning concepts, logic, and propositional form. Subsequently, I turn to Husserl. Picking up on the fact that for Husserl, too, analyticity has metaphysical, or ontological significance, I spell out his conception of analyticity in detail. I show that analyticity for Husserl embraces two essentially symmetrical domains of law: the a priori laws of objective givenness and the a priori laws of propositional form. I then bring Husserl and Kant together. After showing that Husserl fails to capture the essence of Kant's theory of analytic judgment, and so fails to see exactly where he stands relative to Kant, I argue that what ultimately distinguishes Husserl from Kant is the claim that analytic truth is properly articulated in a purely formal context. I show that this departure from Kant has extremely significant consequences. For example, it enables Husserl to describe whole systems of judgment, such as mathematics or logic, as analytic; and it enables Husserl to defend the possibility of analytic judgments having empirical content. TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction 1 Chapter 1 – Analytic Judgment and the Critical Project 11 Chapter 2 – Kant's Theory of Analytic Judgment 76 Chapter 3 – Two Questions About Concepts 114 Chapter 4 – A Kantian Defense of Analytic Judgment 138 Chapter 5 – Husserl's Theory of Analyticity 186 Chapter 6 – Kant and Husserl on Analyticity 245 Conclusion 271 Works Cited 278 Acknowledgments First and foremost, I want to thank Andrea Staiti. I couldn't have asked for a more supportive and responsive advisor. I look forward to many more years of friendship and collaboration. I also want to thank Robert Hanna for all of the support and guidance that he has provided me over the last three years. His work was a major source of inspiration for the dissertation, and it was a great pleasure to be able to work with him directly. Thanks also to Marius Stan and Susan Shell for serving on my defense committee. I am very grateful for the feedback that they have given me on my work. Finally, I want to thank Sophie and Agnes for all of the love, support, and goodness. This dissertation is dedicated to them. Introduction In the Introduction to the first edition of Critique of Pure Reason, Kant proposes an apparently exhaustive distinction between two different kinds of subject-predicate judgment. "In all judgments in which the relation of a subject to the predicate is thought", he explains, "this relation is possible in two ways". Either the predicate concept already belongs to the subject concept, "as something that is (covertly) contained in this concept", or the predicate concept "lies entirely outside" the subject concept. In the first case, we have what Kant calls an 'analytic' judgment; in the second case, we have a 'synthetic' judgment " (A7/B10).1 Why does Kant introduce this distinction? Is it merely a formal distinction for the sake of a formal distinction? On the contrary, the context in which Kant introduces this distinction makes it clear that he has something rather more ambitious in mind. What Kant wants to do, it seems, is to illuminate the nature of scientific inquiry. By developing a language in which to characterize the kinds of judgments that this or that science generates, Kant hopes to shed light on the sciences themselves. Mathematics offers a good example of what Kant has in mind here. Just a few lines after he first introduces the analytic-synthetic distinction, Kant takes up the judgment 7 + 5 = 12. He notes that while this judgment might look initially like an 1 References to the Critique of Pure Reason will be given, as above, as parenthetical citations specifying the edition(s) of the first Critique to which I am referring and the page number on which the passage in question appears. The page numbers are taken from the Academy edition of Kant's works. (The A-edition of the Critique of Pure Reason is the third volume in the Academy edition; the B-edition of the Critique of Pure Reason is the fourth volume). References to other works by Kant will be given as parenthetical citations listing the volume and page number from the Academy edition. All quotations of Kant in English are taken from the Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant (Cambridge University Press). 1 analytic judgment, because it might look as if the concept of the number 12 is contained in the concept of the sum of 7 and 5, this appearance is deceptive. In reality, Kant suggests, the judgment is synthetic in nature: when we reflect on the concept of 7 + 5, we find that the concept 12 is actually not contained in the former after all. This makes possible an important conclusion about mathematics in general: although the judgments of mathematics are manifestly a priori, in the sense that they hold with absolute necessity and can be known without recourse to experience, they do not owe their apriority to their formal, propositional structure. This in turn makes possible an important task for the philosopher of mathematics—that of unearthing the extra-conceptual principle on which the apriority of mathematical judgments actually rests. Given that 7 + 5 = 12 is not simply a statement of identity, how can we explain the fact that this judgment admits of no counter-example and can be grasped independently of experience? The case of natural science is similar. Although we might think that judgments like "matter persists" are analytic, because we might think that what distinguishes matter as such is the fact that it survives the deformation and reformation to which it is subject, reflection on what we actually think in the concept matter suggests that this is not the case. According to Kant, what we actually think in the concept matter is "only its presence in space through the filling of space" (B18). The understanding that matter endures across changes in its sensible properties reflects a logically subsequent judgment, a judgment that is synthetic in the sense that it draws together essentially distinct concepts. How, therefore, are we to explain the apparent necessity of this judgment? Again, since we cannot appeal to propositional form or to conceptual content, we are obliged to seek out a "completely different principle". Supposing that we can identity 2 such a principle, according to Kant, then it will be possible to give a meaningful account of natural scientific judgments like "matter persists". The case of metaphysics is slightly different. As Kant explains in the Preface to the second edition of the first Critique, he is less concerned to understand how metaphysics actually works than to reform it. Since metaphysics has hitherto been "a mere groping, and what is the worst, a groping amount mere concepts", it is necessary to set metaphysics on a more fruitful, progressive path. Having just learned something about successful sciences such as mathematics and natural science, it is possible to see what this will entail. Rather than remaining at the level of conceptual analysis, metaphysics should pursue conceptual synthesis. Like mathematics and natural science, metaphysics should seek out the principle that will enable it to grasp the a priori relations between essentially distinct concepts. What, therefore, can we conclude regarding scientific inquiry? On the one hand, it looks as though the sciences that Kant is concerned with are strongly oriented toward the production of synthetic judgments. Conversely, it looks as if analytic judgment plays no real role in scientific inquiry. In each case, the idea of analytic judgment seems to be introduced in a purely negative sense—as way of clarifying what successful sciences are not, or should not, be engaged in. This, perhaps, is one way of understanding a widespread tendency, that of illustrating Kant's theory of analytic judgment by means of the judgment "all bachelors are unmarried men". Perhaps since Kant does not give analytic judgment anything to do, epistemologically speaking, it is appropriate to exemplify analytic judgment by means of a judgment that does very little.
Recommended publications
  • Frege and the Logic of Sense and Reference
    FREGE AND THE LOGIC OF SENSE AND REFERENCE Kevin C. Klement Routledge New York & London Published in 2002 by Routledge 29 West 35th Street New York, NY 10001 Published in Great Britain by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane London EC4P 4EE Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper. Copyright © 2002 by Kevin C. Klement All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any infomration storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Klement, Kevin C., 1974– Frege and the logic of sense and reference / by Kevin Klement. p. cm — (Studies in philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index ISBN 0-415-93790-6 1. Frege, Gottlob, 1848–1925. 2. Sense (Philosophy) 3. Reference (Philosophy) I. Title II. Studies in philosophy (New York, N. Y.) B3245.F24 K54 2001 12'.68'092—dc21 2001048169 Contents Page Preface ix Abbreviations xiii 1. The Need for a Logical Calculus for the Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 3 Introduction 3 Frege’s Project: Logicism and the Notion of Begriffsschrift 4 The Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 8 The Limitations of the Begriffsschrift 14 Filling the Gap 21 2. The Logic of the Grundgesetze 25 Logical Language and the Content of Logic 25 Functionality and Predication 28 Quantifiers and Gothic Letters 32 Roman Letters: An Alternative Notation for Generality 38 Value-Ranges and Extensions of Concepts 42 The Syntactic Rules of the Begriffsschrift 44 The Axiomatization of Frege’s System 49 Responses to the Paradox 56 v vi Contents 3.
    [Show full text]
  • The Semantics and Pragmatics of Polysemy: a Relevance-Theoretic Account
    The Semantics and Pragmatics of Polysemy: A Relevance-Theoretic Account Ingrid Lossius Falkum Thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University College London January 2011 I, Ingrid Lossius Falkum, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. _____________________ Sign. 2 Abstract This thesis investigates the phenomenon of polysemy: a single lexical form with two or multiple related senses (e.g. catch the rabbit/order the rabbit; lose a wallet/lose a relative; a handsome man/a handsome gift). I develop a pragmatic account of polysemy within the framework of Sperber and Wilson’s relevance theory, where new senses for a word are constructed during on-line comprehension by means of a single process of ad hoc concept construction, which adjusts the meanings of individual words in different directions. While polysemy is largely unproblematic from the perspective of communication, it poses a range of theoretical and descriptive problems. This is sometimes termed the polysemy paradox. A widely held view in lexical semantics is that word meanings must consist of complex representations in order to capture the sense relations involved in polysemy. Contrary to this view, I argue that a conceptual atomist approach, which treats word meanings as unstructured atoms and thereby avoids the range of problems associated with decompositional theories of word meaning, may be at least as able to account for polysemy when paired with an adequate pragmatic theory. My proposed solution to the polysemy paradox is to treat polysemy as a fundamentally communicative phenomenon, which arises as a result of encoded lexical concepts being massively underdetermining of speaker-intended concepts, and is grounded in our pragmatic inferential ability.
    [Show full text]
  • Structuralism, Indispensability, and the Access Problem Russell Marcus
    Structuralism, Indispensability, and the Access Problem Russell Marcus, Ph.D. Chauncey Truax Post-Doctoral Fellow Department of Philosophy, Hamilton College 198 College Hill Road Clinton NY 13323 [email protected] (315) 859-4056 (office) (315) 381-3125 (home) (917) 903-7483 (mobile) January 2008 2783 words Abstract: The central problem in the philosophy of mathematics concerns access. The access problem arises from the common supposition that the referents of mathematical terms inhabit a realm separate from us. Quine’s approach in the philosophy of mathematics, his indispensability argument, dissolves the access problem, though his solution sometimes goes unrecognized, even by those who are sympathetic to his work. According to the indispensability argument, we are justified in believing in a limited mathematical ontology, even if we lack any special faculty for acquiring mathematical knowledge. This paper highlights both Quine’s position and its neglect. As an example, I defend Michael Resnik’s structuralism from recent criticism. Resnik has no access problem for the so-called mathematical objects he posits, since he relies on a Quinean indispensability argument. Still, the indispensabilist does not provide an account of our access to the objects of a traditional mathematical ontology, and this may be seen as a real access problem. Structuralism, Indispensability, and the Access Problem, page 1 §1: Structuralism and the Problem of Mathematics The central epistemological problem for mathematics is sometimes called the access problem. The access problem arises from a two-realm view, the supposition that the referents of mathematical singular terms inhabit a realm which is separate from us. The history of philosophy is littered with attempts to solve the access problem, which is just the old question of how concrete humans can have knowledge of abstract mathematical objects.
    [Show full text]
  • Proquest Dissertations
    INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand comer and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps. Each original is also photographed in one exposure and is Included in reduced form at the back of the book. Photographs included in the original manuscript have been reproduced xerographically in this copy. Higher quality 6” x 9” black and white photographic prints are available for any photographs or illustrations appearing in this copy for an additional charge. Contact UMI directly to order. UMI' Bell & Howell Information and Learning 300 North Zeeb Road, Ann Art)or, Ml 48106-1346 USA 800-521-0600 THE METAPHYSICS OF CLASSICAL LOGIC: SEMANTIC ANTI-REALISM, QUASI-REALISM AND LOGICAL REVISIONISM DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Joseph Roy Salerno, B.A., M.A.
    [Show full text]
  • Katz, Jerrold J. (1932–2002) D
    Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics (Second Edition), 2006, Pages 165–167. Katz, Jerrold J. (1932–2002) D. Terence Langendoen Department of Linguistics University of Arizona P O Box 210028 Tucson AZ 85721-0028 USA [email protected] Abstract This biography of Jerrold J. Katz focuses on his main contributions to linguistic theory and the philosophy of language. His accomplishments include (1) developing the first comprehensive theory of semantics within generative grammar, (2) proposing that language is an abstract rather than a physical or mental object, and (3) challenging the Fregean notions that sense determines reference and that semantic form is equivalent to logical form. In addition to his general semantic theory, Katz worked out detailed accounts of presupposition, illocutionary force, idioms and names, and published authoritatively on the work of such philosophers as René Descartes, Gottlob Frege, Willard van Orman Quine, and Ludwig Wittgenstein. Jerrold Katz’s career Katz received a PhD in Philosophy from Princeton University in 1960. In 1961 he became Research Associate in Linguistics at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, and was appointed Assistant Professor of Philosophy there in 1963. He quickly rose through the ranks at MIT, becoming Professor of Philosophy in 1969. He was appointed Distinguished Professor of Philosophy and Linguistics at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York in 1975, a position he held until his death. He wrote or coauthored 11 books and over 75 articles on philosophy and linguistics, and edited or coedited three books. Semantics in generative grammar Katz started out with the goal “to try to understand meaning in natural language using some form of Fregean intensionalism to provide a semantic theory for Chomsky’s theory of generative grammar, which ..
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Linguistics to Appear in Kelly Michael Becker and Iain Thomson, Eds., the Cambridge History of Philosophy, 1945-2015
    Philosophy of Linguistics To appear in Kelly Michael Becker and Iain Thomson, eds., The Cambridge History of Philosophy, 1945-2015 Geoffrey K. Pullum School of Philosophy, Psychology and Language Sciences, University of Edinburgh Draft of June 5, 2018 Linguistics in 1945 was a modest discipline, with much to be modest about.1 Very few universities had linguistics departments; the profession was tiny. The history of American linguistics (on which this brief chapter concentrates, because it has been the main focus of philosophical interest) goes back barely a hundred years. Its foundational documents include the Handbook of American Indian Languages (Boas 1911), a posthumously reconstructed lecture course by Ferdinand de Saussure (1916), and Leonard Bloomfield’s general survey of the field Language (1933). Linguistics may not have been on the radar for philosophers of science in the 1940s, but lin- guists had philosophical interests. Much influenced by the positivism and operationalism of the Vienna Circle, they sought general analytical procedures not just for practical use by field lin- guists working on undocumented languages but as theoretically rigorous methods, applicable to any language, that would both yield a scientifically adequate analysis and confer epistemological justification upon it. They were divided between realists and antirealists. Householder (1952) introduced the epi- thets “God’s-truth” and “hocus-pocus” for the two camps. God’s-truthers believed linguistic ex- pressions had structure that linguists should try to discover. Hocus-pocus linguists believed that no structural properties inhered in the acoustic mush of utterances as physically experienced: linguists imputed structure and systematicity to them to render language more scientifically tractable.
    [Show full text]
  • Article Precises
    Philosophy 408: The Language Revolution Hamilton College Spring 2009 Russell Marcus Tuesdays and Thursdays, 2:30pm - 3:45pm [email protected] Article Prècises Assignments In preparing for most classes, you should write an article prècis. Article prècises are 100- to 150- word summaries of an assigned reading. I will collect all of your prècises at the end of the term, May 7, unless you display a need for me to collect them earlier. You will mainly be graded on the completion of twenty prècises, rather than their quality. I expect that the prècises will be useful to you in preparing both for classes and for the final exam. You need not complete a prècis for the three classes in which you are presenting a seminar paper. In lieu of up to five prècises, you can write a list of 6-8 detailed questions on the reading. The following is a list readings for which prècises are assigned; for readings which we will discuss in more than one class, you may be asked to write more than one prècis. John Locke, “Of Words” Gottlob Frege, “The Thought: A Logical Inquiry” Gottlob Frege, “On Sense and Nominatum” Bertrand Russell, “Descriptions” P.F. Strawson, “On Referring” Keith Donnellan, “Reference and Definite Descriptions” Saul Kripke, “Naming and Necessity” (twice) Hilary Putnam, “Meaning and Reference” Ayer, “The Principle of Verification” W.V. Quine, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” (twice) W.V. Quine, “Ontological Relativity” H.P. Grice, “Meaning” Mark Johnston, “The End of the Theory of Meaning” Alfred Tarski, “The Semantic Conception of Truth and the Foundations of Semantics” Donald Davidson, “Truth and Meaning” Jerrold Katz, “Introduction” and “Sense” Wittgenstein, “On Private Language” (twice) Saul Kripke, “On Rules and Private Languages” Ruth Millikan, “Truth Rules, Hoverflies, and the Kripke-Wittgenstein Paradox” Noam Chomsky, “Language and Problems of Knowledge” Jerrold Katz, “The Unfinished Chomskyan Revolution” Michael Devitt, “Linguistics is Not Psychology”.
    [Show full text]
  • Remembering Jerry Fodor and His Work
    DOI: 10.1111/mila.12206 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Remembering Jerry Fodor and his work1 Georges Rey Department of Philosophy, University of Maryland, College Park, Maryland This is a reminiscence and short biographical sketch of Correspondence the late philosopher and cognitive scientist Jerry Fodor. It Department of Philosophy, University of includes a summary of his main proposals about the mind: Maryland, College Park, MD 20742. his “Language of Thought” hypothesis; his rejection of Email: [email protected] analyticity and conceptual role semantics; his “mad dog nativism”; his proposal of mental modules and—by contrast—his skepticism about a computational theory of central cognition; his anti-reductionist, but still physicalist, views about psychology; and, lastly, his attacks on selec- tionism. I conclude with some discussion of his idiosyn- cratic style and of his aesthetic and other interests. An appendix provides some memorable quotes. KEYWORDS antiselectionism, confirmation holism, language of thought, nativism, referentialism 1 | SOME INTRODUCTORY PERSONAL NOTES After a long illness, the philosopher Jerry Fodor died on November 29, 2017. This was a great loss not only to his family and many friends but also to philosophy and cognitive science. For reasons I hope will emerge in this remembrance, he was indisputably the most important philosopher of psy- chology of his generation.2 I first met Fodor on a wintry evening in February 1974. I had been a graduate student at Harvard for several years, still to some extent under the spell of Wittgenstein and Quine, whose views then dominated the philosophy of mind, there and elsewhere. My entering class had been expressly warned by Quine's close colleague, Burton Dreben, to avoid (in Wittgenstein's famous phrase) “the grip of the picture” of traditional mentalism—which, he claimed, underlay the work of Chomsky and 1 I make no pretense of covering all of Fodor's views, which are far too rich for summary in a journal article.
    [Show full text]
  • Issues in the Philosophical Foundations of Lexical Semantics
    Issues in the Philosophical Foundations of Lexical Semantics by Brian Edward Ulicny B.A. Philosophy, B.S. Electrical Engineering, University of Notre Dame (1986) Submitted to the Department of Linguistics and Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy at the MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY May 1993 © Massachusetts Institute of Technology 1993. All rights reserved. Author ................ ......... ................................. Department of Linguistics and Philosophy April 20, 1993 Certified by... ........ .... ........... ................. .......... James Higginbotham Professor, Linguistics and Philosophy Thesis Supervisor A ccepted by ................................. George Boolos Chairman, Departmental Committee on Graduate Studies ARCHIVES MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TFCHNOLOGY ¶JUN 03 1993 Issues in the Philosophical Foundations of Lexical Semantics by Brian Edward Ulicny Submitted to the Department of Linguistics and Philosophy on April 20, 1993, in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy Abstract My dissertation defends and explores the thesis that in order for a speaker to un- derstand a natural language it is not only sufficient but necessary that the speaker tacitly know or "cognize" the truth-conditional contribution of the words and other sentential elements to the truth-conditions of the whole expression. A speaker's se- mantic competence is to be explained as the employment of an internally-represented axiomatized truth theory for that speaker's first language. By providing a theory of truth for a language, the truth of certain sentences follows on the basis of that theory alone. In the first chapter, I develop and defend a notion of analyticity suggested by Noam Chomsky in his Language and Problems of Knowledge (1986) against skeptical worries due to Quine and Burge.
    [Show full text]
  • Structuralism, Indispensability, and the Access Problem Russell Marcus
    203 Facta Philosophica 9, 2007: 203–211 © Peter Lang, Switzerland Structuralism, Indispensability, and the Access Problem Russell Marcus §1: Structuralism and the Problem of Mathematics The central epistemological problem for mathematics is sometimes called the access problem. The access problem arises from a two-realm view, the supposition that the referents of mathematical singular terms in- habit a realm which is separate from us. The history of philosophy is littered with attempts to solve the access problem, which is just the old question of how concrete humans can have knowledge of abstract math- ematical objects. Quine’s approach in the philosophy of mathematics, his indispensability argument, dissolves the access problem, though his solution sometimes goes unrecognized, even by those who are sympa- thetic to his work. This paper shows that the proponent of the indis- pensability argument can, to a certain extent, deflect criticisms based on the access argument. One way to try to solve the access problem involves positing a spe- cial human ability to learn about abstract objects. This rationalist ap- proach is exemplified by Plato, Descartes, Gödel, and Jerrold Katz, among many others. The central complaints about rationalism involve accusations of mysticism and desperation, and failure of parsimony, both epistemological parsimony and parsimony of the resulting ontology.1 A second approach to the access problem denies the supposition that mathematical objects are separate from us. This approach is exem- plified by Aristotle and Mill, and by Penelope Maddy’s early work. The central complaints about the Aristotelian approach involve the insuffi- ciency of concrete objects as models of mathematical theories.2 1 Gödel 1961 discusses a special faculty of mathematical insight.
    [Show full text]
  • Prototype Semantics: the English Word Lie Author(S): Linda Coleman and Paul Kay Reviewed Work(S): Source: Language, Vol
    Linguistic Society of America Prototype Semantics: The English Word Lie Author(s): Linda Coleman and Paul Kay Reviewed work(s): Source: Language, Vol. 57, No. 1 (Mar., 1981), pp. 26-44 Published by: Linguistic Society of America Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/414285 . Accessed: 09/12/2011 09:51 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Linguistic Society of America is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Language. http://www.jstor.org PROTOTYPE SEMANTICS: THE ENGLISH WORD LIE LINDA COLEMAN and PAUL KAY University of California, Berkeley The meaning of the word lie ('prevaricate') consists in a cognitive prototype to which various real or imagined events may correspond in varying degrees. This view contrasts with the familiar one in which word meanings consist of sets of necessary and sufficient conditions, and distinguish discretely between instances and non-instances. The rele- vance of the notions of PROTOTYPEand GRADIENCEin semantics has previously been established in physical and sensory lexical domains. The present paper shows that these notions are also relevant in abstract and social domains. Results are reported from an experiment which supports this view.* Received notions of word meaning in linguistics are based on the idea of the semantic feature or component:' semantic features are discrete properties (or relations), and they contrast discretely with one another.
    [Show full text]
  • A Biopsychological Foundation for Linguistics
    Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 7-28-2015 12:00 AM A Biopsychological Foundation for Linguistics Jonathan J. Life The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Robert Stainton The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Jonathan J. Life 2015 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the Philosophy of Language Commons Recommended Citation Life, Jonathan J., "A Biopsychological Foundation for Linguistics" (2015). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 3205. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/3205 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A BIOPSYCHOLOGICAL FOUNDATION FOR LINGUISTICS (Thesis format: Monograph) by Jonathan J. Life Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The School of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies The University of Western Ontario London, Ontario, Canada © Jonathan J. Life 2015 Abstract: In this dissertation, I defend the view that natural languages are concrete biopsychological phenomena to be studied empirically. In Section One, I begin with an historical explanation. Some analytic philosophers, I argue, misapply formal logic as an analysis of natural language, when it was in fact originally developed as an alternative to natural language, employed for scientific purposes. Abstract, quasi-mathematical philosophies of language, I argue, are partially a result of this misunderstanding.
    [Show full text]