INFINITE VALUE and the BEST of ALL POSSIBLE WORLDS 367 Worlds

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

INFINITE VALUE and the BEST of ALL POSSIBLE WORLDS 367 Worlds Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. XCVII No. 2, September 2018 doi: 10.1111/phpr.12383 © 2017 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Infinite Value and the Best of All Possible Worlds1 NEVIN CLIMENHAGA University of Notre Dame A common argument for atheism runs as follows: God would not create a world worse than other worlds he could have created instead. However, if God exists, he could have created a better world than this one. There- fore, God does not exist. In this paper I challenge the second premise of this argument. I argue that if God exists, our world will continue without end, with God continuing to create value-bearers, and sustaining and perfecting the value-bearers he has already created. Given this, if God exists, our world—considered on the whole—is infinitely valuable. I further contend that this theistic picture makes our world’s value unsurpass- able. In support of this contention, I consider proposals for how infinitely valuable worlds might be improved upon, focusing on two main ways—adding value-bearers and increasing the value in present value-bearers. I argue that neither of these can improve our world. Depending on how each method is understood, either it would not improve our world, or our world is unsurpassable with respect to it. I conclude by considering the implications of my argument for the problem of evil more generally conceived. One atheistic argument from evil proceeds as follows: (1) If God exists, he would only create a world if there is no better world that he could have created instead. (2) If God exists, he could have created a better world than this one. Since, if God exists, he created this world, the consequents of (1) and (2) cannot both be true. It follows that their antecedent is false, and that (3) God does not exist. Call this argument the Argument from Surpassability, or AFS for short.2 Leibniz (1710) famously denied (2) of this argument, claiming that ours is the unique best of all possible 1 This paper was written with the support of a generous grant from the Templeton Foundation on Contemporary Moral Theory and the Problem of Evil (grant number 43655). I am grateful to Jim Sterba, the leader of that project, and my fellow research assistant Meg Schmitt for their helpful discussion and comments on early drafts of this paper. I would also like to thank participants in the Center for Philosophy of Religion Discussion Group at Notre Dame for their feedback on a draft of this paper, and Dustin Crummett in particular for his extensive written comments and extremely helpful discussion of the issues explored in this paper. 2 The AFS is expressed in basically this form by Perkins (1983), Sobel (2004: 468), Wielenberg (2004: 57), Hudson (2013: 236), and Kraay (2013: 399). Some presentations of the argument replace (1) above with the claim that God must create the best possible world. However, this presupposes that there is a single best possible world. (1) leaves open the possibility that there are multiple equally good or incom- parable worlds such that no world is better than any of these worlds. Another variation on this argument replaces (2) with the stronger claim that for any possible world, there is a better one creatable by God. Since the second premise of this argument is logically stronger than (2), my argument against (2) in this paper also challenges this argument. INFINITE VALUE AND THE BEST OF ALL POSSIBLE WORLDS 367 worlds. Contemporary theistic philosophers have generally been reticent to follow him in this. Robert Adams (1972) denies (1) by arguing that by failing to create a better world than he did God would not necessarily be violating anyone’s rights or manifesting a defect in character, and could in fact be manifesting grace.3 Other theistic philosophers have objected to (1) with the following argument: there is no best possible world; for ev- ery world that God can create, there is a better one that he could have created instead.4 Thus, it is unreasonable to blame God for not creating a better world, because it is logi- cally impossible for him to both create a world and satisfy the consequent of (1). Skep- tics of this move have responded that if (1) is false, this implies that a perfect being (like God) is impossible—for a perfect being would never perform a surpassable action, and yet the fact that there is no best possible world makes it impossible for a creator to avoid performing a surpassable action.5 In this paper I follow Leibniz in arguing against (2). Unlike Leibniz, however, I do not think that our world is the uniquely best world. Instead, I argue for the weaker con- clusion that there are not other worlds better than ours. It is compatible with this conclu- sion that the goodness of some other worlds is equal to or incomparable with that of ours. My argument proceeds in two stages. First, I argue that given theological assumptions that the proponent of the AFS ought to accept, if God created the world, then there is an infinite amount of value in our world. Second, I argue that, given these assumptions, not only is our world infinitely valuable, it is unsurpassable: on any plausible principles that allow us to rank different infinitely valuable worlds, there are no other infinitely valuable worlds better than this world. I should stress at the outset that I do not think that my argument solves the “prob- lem of evil” more generally. There remain serious philosophical objections to theism based on the existence of the evil we find in our world even if my argument works. However, I think that my argument does show that the AFS is not the best way to formulate the problem of evil. While God’s existence may be incompatible with or disconfirmed by the evils in the world, this is not because those evils make the world as a whole worse than it may have otherwise been. I explore the relation between my argument and the problem of evil more generally in the final section of this paper. 3 For criticisms of Adams, see Quinn (1992), Grover (2003), Wielenberg (2004), and Rowe (2004: 74–87). 4 See, e.g., Plantinga (1976: 61), Schlesinger (1977: ch. 9–10), Forrest (1981), Reichenbach (1982: 122– 28), Morris (1993), and Swinburne (1994: 134–36) and (2004: 113–15). 5 See Quinn (1992), Perkins (1983: 247), Grover (1988, 2004), Wielenberg (2004: 56–59), Rowe (2004: 88– 142), and Kraay (2010). Leibniz explicitly rejected the possibility of an infinitely improving series of worlds, on the grounds that this would make God’s choice to create violate the Principle of Sufficient Reason (see Blumenfeld [1975] for discussion). Contemporary defenders of the claim that a God with no best world to create could not be perfect frequently appeal to the possibility of morally or rationally superior “rival cre- ators.” This basic idea was suggested in Kant’s Lectures on Philosophical Theology (1978: 137): That the world created by God is the best of all possible worlds, is clear for the following reason. If a better world than the one willed by God were possible, then a will better than the divine will would also have to be possible. For indisputably that will is better which chooses what is better. But if a better will is possible, then so is a being who could express this better will. And therefore this being would be more perfect and better than God. But this is a contradiction; for God is omnitudo realitatis. 368 NEVIN CLIMENHAGA I. Preliminary Remarks In this essay I understand God to be the omnipotent, omniscient, and perfectly good cre- ator of all contingent things. I understand the world to include all of space and time and anything that exists outside of space and time. In other words, ‘the world’ refers to all of reality (including God). Importantly, on this definition of ‘world,’ there can be only one actual world. Now, (for all I know) God could create multiple spatiotemporally closed systems; in this case I will say that God creates several universes. So there can be only one world, but many universes. Strictly speaking God creates universes (and the things in them), not worlds, since a world includes God. However, I will sometimes speak loosely of God creating worlds; the reader should understand this to mean God’s creating the contingent things in a world, including the universe(s) it contains. I assume, for simplicity’s sake, that God has knowledge of all future events, including (if such there be) indeterministic events or libertarian free actions, and I will ignore pos- sible constraints on what possible worlds God can create arising from indeterministic events or libertarian free actions. I will also speak as if God acts in time; later, I will con- sider how to reformulate relevant parts of my argument without this assumption. I further assume that it is possible to rank worlds according to their goodness or value.6 (In this paper, I use ‘value’ and ‘goodness’ interchangeably.) Although I proceed as if world-values are measurable by some precise number, my arguments could be refor- mulated with ranges or sets of numbers representing the values of worlds. (In section V I consider whether the AFS can be defended if it turns out that world-values are not mea- surable at all.) The remainder of this paper is structured as follows. In section II I present the three most common arguments for (2) in the literature.
Recommended publications
  • Metaphysics. by Peter Van Inwagen Review By: Timothy O'connor the Philosophical Review, Vol
    Philosophical Review Metaphysics. by Peter van Inwagen Review by: Timothy O'Connor The Philosophical Review, Vol. 104, No. 2 (Apr., 1995), pp. 314-317 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2185999 . Accessed: 25/06/2014 03:49 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 185.44.77.146 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 03:49:57 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions BOOK REVIEWS such issues as the completeness of quantum mechanics and whetherit is a local theory.Part of the problem has been in figuringout what is meant by 'completeness' and 'locality'.A lot of hard work has also been done in designing and performingexperiments to test quantum mechanics and compare it to rival theories. Shimony has made importantcontributions to all aspects of this endeavor-for example, his proof that quantum mechanical nonlocality,what he refersto as passion-at-a-distance,cannot be exploited for the purposes of sending signals at velocitiesgreater than the velocityof light (2:134-36).
    [Show full text]
  • Department of Philosophy the University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-4619 Russell's China Teapot Peter Van Inwagen
    Department of Philosophy The University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-4619 [email protected] Russell’s China Teapot Peter van Inwagen St Thomas Aquinas has presented five well-known arguments for the existence of God, but he has also presented—although not, of course, endorsed—two arguments that might be described as “arguments to the contrary” or as “objections to belief in God.” Summa Theologiae, I, q.2, a.3 (the “Five Ways” article, the article whose topic is indicated by the heading “Whether God exists”) opens with those two arguments. The first, Objection 1, is a version of the argument from evil—the argument that since the existence of evil is incompatible with the existence of God, God does not exist. The second Objection is as follows: Objection 2. It is, moreover, superfluous to suppose that what can be accounted for by a few principles has been produced by many. But it seems that everything we see in the world can be accounted for by other principles, without supposing God to exist. For all natural things can be accounted for by one principle, which is nature; and all voluntary things can be accounted for by one principle, which is human reason or will. Hence, there is no need to suppose that God exists. Here is a formulation of the essential point of this argument in language the modern mind may find more congenial than Thomas’s talk of “principles”: 2 The only reason we could have for believing in God would be that it was necessary to postulate his existence to account for some observed fact or facts.
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal for Philosophy of Religion
    EUROPEAN JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION VOLUME 4 NUMBER 4 WINTER 2012 ARTICLES David S. ODERBERG Survivalism, Corruptionism, and Mereology 1 Dale JACQUETTE Anselm’s Metaphysics of Nonbeing 27 Erik J. WIELENBERG An Inconsistency in Craig’s Defence of the Moral Argument 49 Andrei A. BUCKAREFF Omniscience, the Incarnation, and Knowledge de se 59 T. Ryan BYERLY Infallible Divine Foreknowledge Cannot Uniquely Threaten Human Freedom, But Its Mechanics Might 73 T. J. MAWSON On Determining How Important It Is Whether or Not There Is a God 95 Jerome GELLMAN A Theistic, Universe-Based, Theodicy of Human Suffering and Immoral Behaviour 107 Anders KRAAL Hedenius’ Soteriological Argument from Evil 123 Peter JONKERS Redefining Religious Truth as a Challenge for Philosophy of Religion 139 Louis CARUANA Science, Religion and Common Sense 161 DISCUSSIONS AND REPLIES John BISHOP In Quest of Authentic Divinity: Critical Notice of Mark Johnston’s ‘Saving God: Religion after Idolatry’ 175 BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES Timothy O’Connor. Theism and Ultimate Explanation: The Necessary Shape of Contingency Reviewed by Sho Yamaguchi 193 Georg Gasser (ed.). Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? Reviewed by Joshua Farris 196 Timothy Yoder. Hume on God: Irony, Deism and Genuine Theism Reviewed by Dan O’Brien 201 Earl Stanley B. Fronda. Wittgenstein’s (Misunderstood) Religious Thought Reviewed by Klaus von Stosch 206 Neil Spurway (ed.). Theology, Evolution and the Mind Reviewed by Aku Visala 208 SURVIVALISM, CORRUPTIONISM, AND MEREOLOGY DAVID S. ODERBERG University of Reading Abstract. Corruptionism is the view that following physical death, the human being ceases to exist (until Resurrection) but their soul persists in the afterlife.
    [Show full text]
  • Following the Argument Where It Leads
    Following The Argument Where It Leads Thomas Kelly Princeton University [email protected] Abstract: Throughout the history of western philosophy, the Socratic injunction to ‘follow the argument where it leads’ has exerted a powerful attraction. But what is it, exactly, to follow the argument where it leads? I explore this intellectual ideal and offer a modest proposal as to how we should understand it. On my proposal, following the argument where it leaves involves a kind of modalized reasonableness. I then consider the relationship between the ideal and common sense or 'Moorean' responses to revisionary philosophical theorizing. 1. Introduction Bertrand Russell devoted the thirteenth chapter of his History of Western Philosophy to the thought of St. Thomas Aquinas. He concluded his discussion with a rather unflattering assessment: There is little of the true philosophic spirit in Aquinas. He does not, like the Platonic Socrates, set out to follow wherever the argument may lead. He is not engaged in an inquiry, the result of which it is impossible to know in advance. Before he begins to philosophize, he already knows the truth; it is declared in the Catholic faith. If he can find apparently rational arguments for some parts of the faith, so much the better: If he cannot, he need only fall back on revelation. The finding of arguments for a conclusion given in advance is not philosophy, but special pleading. I cannot, therefore, feel that he deserves to be put on a level with the best philosophers either of Greece or of modern times (1945: 463). The extent to which this is a fair assessment of Aquinas is controversial.1 My purpose in what follows, however, is not to defend Aquinas; nor is it to substantiate the charges that Russell brings against him.
    [Show full text]
  • Taking Monism Seriously
    Philos Stud DOI 10.1007/s11098-015-0620-0 Taking monism seriously David M. Cornell1 Ó The Author(s) 2016. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract Monism is the view that there is only a single material object in exis- tence: the world. According to this view, therefore, the ordinary objects of common sense—cats and hats, cars and stars, and so on—do not actually exist; there is only the world. Because of this, monism is routinely dismissed in the contemporary literature as being absurd and obviously false. It is simply obvious that there is a plurality of material things, thus it is simply obvious that monism is false, or so the argument goes. I call this the common sense argument against monism and in this paper I offer a response. I argue that providing the monist can make his view consistent with the appearance that there is a multiplicity of material things, then it is not rationally acceptable to reject monism solely on the basis of that appearance. Through an appeal to a particular type of property—distributional properties—I sketch out a plausible story of how monism is perfectly consistent with the appearance of plurality, and thus nullify the common sense argument. There may be any number of arguments that serve to undermine monism, but the common sense argument is not one of them. Monism deserves to be taken more seriously than that. Keywords Monism Á Mereology Á Common sense Á Properties Á Distributional properties & David M. Cornell [email protected] 1 Department of History, Politics, and Philosophy, Manchester Metropolitan University, Geoffrey Manton Building, Rosamund Street West, Manchester M15 6LL, UK 123 D.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 1, Metaphysics, 1987
    Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 1, Metaphysics, 1987 Front Matter (7 pp.) Preface (1 p.) James E. Tomberlin Entities Without Identity, pp. 1-19 Terence Parsons When Are Objects Parts?, pp. 21-47 Peter van Inwagen Existence, pp. 49-108 Nathan Salmon How To Build a Person: The Physical Basis for Mentality, pp. 109-154 John L. Pollock Subjects Among Other Things, pp. 155-187 Ernest Sosa Two Concepts of Modality: Modal Realism and Modal Reductionism, pp. 189-231 Alvin Plantinga Are Concept-Users World-Makers?, pp. 233-267 Nicholas Wolterstorff Conceptual Relativism, pp. 269-288 Bruce Aune The Philosophical Limits of Scientific Essentialism, pp. 289-365 George Bealer Event Causation: The Counterfactual Analysis, pp. 367-386 Jonathan Bennett Phenomenological Ontology Revisited: A Bergmannian Retrospective, pp. 387-404 Jay F. Rosenberg Self-Consciousness, Demonstrative Reference, and the Self-Ascription View of Believing, pp. 405-454 Hector-Neri Castaneda The `Fido'-Fido Theory of Belief, pp. 455-480 Stephen Schiffer Objects of Consciousness: The Non-Relational Theory of Sensing, pp. 481-500 Romane Clark An Argument for a Modified Russellian Principle of Acquaintance, pp. 501-512 Felicia Ackerman Phenomenal Objects: A Backhanded Defense, pp. 513-526 William G. Lycan Back Matter (1 p.) Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 2, Epistemology, 1988 Front Matter (7 pp.) Preface (1 p.) James E. Tomberlin Positive Epistemic Status and Proper Function, pp. 1-50 Alvin Plantinga Strong and Weak Justification, pp. 51-69 Alvin I. Goldman The Evidence of the Senses, pp. 71-90 Roderick M. Chisholm How to be a Fallibilist, pp. 91-123 Stewart Cohen Coherence, Justification, and Chisholm, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Evil and Van Inwagen
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 20 Issue 2 Article 8 4-1-2003 Evil and Van Inwagen Jeff Jordan Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Jordan, Jeff (2003) "Evil and Van Inwagen," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 20 : Iss. 2 , Article 8. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol20/iss2/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. EVIL AND VAN INWAGEN Jeff Jordan A proposition employed in many versions of the evidential argument from evil is that every evil is necessary, or God does not exist. This proposition is so widely accepted that we might dub it the "Standard Claim". In several articles Peter van Inwagen has argued that the Standard Claim is false. Van Inwagen's argument depends upon what we might call the UNo Minimum Claim". In this note I argue that the No Minimum Claim is either false or implausible. Theists and nontheists both typically hold that the existence of God is incompatible with the occurrence of any evil which God need not permit in order to bring about a greater good, or to prevent an equally bad or worse evil from occurring. Indeed this view is so widely accepted and so rarely questioned that we will dub it the "Standard Claim." Expressed briefly, the Standard Claim asserts that every evil is necessary, or God does not exist.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Evil and the Probity of Theodicy from William Rowe's
    Liberty University Department of Philosophy The Problem of Evil and the Probity of Doing Theodicy from William Rowe’s Evidential Argument from Evil ------------------------------------------- A Thesis Presented to the Faculty of Philosophy Department of Liberty University In Partial Fulfilment Of the Requirement for the Degree Master of Arts in Philosophical Studies -------------------------------------------- By Olaoluwa Apata -------------------------------------------- Lynchburg, VA May 2016 Abstract In this research, we discussed the types of evil: moral and natural, which are cited by atheistic philosophers as evidence against the existence of God. The so-called evidence from evil has been used by the atheistic and other non-theistic scholars to raise hypothesis on evaluating the possibility or likelihood that an omnipotent, omniscient, and wholly good God exists in a world that is littered with evil. Moral evil is evil that arise from the misuse of free will by moral agents, while natural evils are natural disasters such as: earthquakes, famine, floods, hurricanes, tornadoes etc. We discussed moral evil and Plantinga’s free will defense. We also discussed the natural evil and how it poses threat to theism. The logical and the evidential arguments from evil are the forms of arguments developed from moral and natural evils. While many scholars have agreed that Plantinga’s free will defense adequately responds to the problem of logical evil, the same consensus does not necessarily apply to the evidential argument from evil. We also examined William Rowe’s evidential argument which he developed from cases of intense animal and human sufferings considered by him to be pointless or gratuitous with no known reasons or goods for which God should have allowed the visceral experience of such sufferings.
    [Show full text]
  • Full Dissertation
    Animal Suffering in an Unfallen World: A Theodicy of Non-Human Evolution Submitted by Bethany Noël Sollereder to the University of Exeter as a dissertation for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Theology In October 2014 This thesis is available for Library use on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. I certify that all material in this thesis which is not my own work has been identified and that no material has previously been submitted and approved for the award of a degree by this or any other University. Signature: ………………………………………………………….. !2 Abstract The publication of The Origin of Species in 1859 raised a host of theological issues. Chief amongst them is the question of how a good, loving, and powerful God could create through an evolutionary process that involved so much suffering, pain, and violence. The traditional Christian answers for suffering in the natural world are not plausible in an evolutionary world. We cannot blame natural evil on human sin, since earth history shows that non- human suffering long preceded humans. Nor can we say that God allows suffering because it allows opportunity for moral choice, spiritual closeness with God, and the development of virtue, as none of these apply to the non-human realm. A new approach is needed to address the question of suffering and violence amongst non-human animals. In this dissertation, I address the question of evolutionary suffering with a multi-disciplinary approach of biblical studies, philosophical theology, and systematic theology to build a compound theodicy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Liberal Doctrine of Hell and Universalism: a Transcendental Approach
    1 The Liberal Doctrine of Hell and Universalism: A Transcendental Approach By Daniel L. Broadstock BA (Hons), B.Ed A thesis submitted in fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Philosophy University of Divinity 2017 2 Abstract In this thesis I have applied a Kantian methodology to present a new approach to the problem of Hell. I have engaged with two leading perspectives in this debate, the ‘liberal doctrine of Hell’ and the doctrine of Universalism, and pursued dialogue with leading theologians of each view; Jerry Walls and Jurgen Moltmann respectively. The liberal model of Hell is a modern attempt to revitalise the doctrine by recasting its nature and purpose. Rather than an instrument for the punishment of sin, the liberal model interprets Hell as God’s response to human freedom. This theory holds that God has constituted human beings with free volition of the will and desires a free relationship with them. As it is possible to resist this invitation, he has also created Hell as a place of eternal separation for those who reject him. While the invitation of grace is never withdrawn, some will remain there forever. Universalism is the view that all human beings will be saved. I have sketched a general outline of these views, illustrating them with reference to arguments proposed by key thinkers in their respective fields. I conclude that they constitute an antinomy; an a priori dilemma abstract from experience and therefore unresolvable by philosophical reasoning. I suggest that the problem of Hell can be resolved by employing a theological adaptation of Kant’s transcendental idealism: eternal separation and universal salvation can both be true, if understood as compatible manifestations of different levels of reality and perception.
    [Show full text]
  • Against Monism∗ Analysis 67 (2007): 1–7
    Against Monism∗ Analysis 67 (2007): 1–7. Final version at: Theodore Sider http://www.blackwell-synergy.com/ toc/anal/67/293 Abstract Jonathan Schaffer distinguishes two sorts of monism. Existence monists say that only one object exists: The World. Priority monists admit the existence of The World’s parts, but say that their features are derivative from the properties of The World. Both have trouble explaining the features of statespace, the set of possibilities available to The World. 1. Monism and pluralism Let’s agree to take ontology seriously. We must then take monism seriously. According to monism, there exists only one (nonabstract1) object: the entire world.2 To be sure, monism clashes with what we ordinarily think and say. But so do other revisionary ontologies that we ought to take seriously. Consider nihilism, the thesis that the only objects that exist are the partless elementary particles of physics.3 Although the nihilist says that tables and chairs do not exist, she is quick to add that there do exist “particles arranged tablewise”, “particles arranged chairwise”, and so on.4 Here are three reasons to take nihilism seriously, despite its revisionary nature. (1) Nihilism is not refuted by mere perception. If there were no tables, only particles arranged tablewise, ∗Thanks to Dave Chalmers, John Hawthorne, Jonathan Schaffer (whose paper “From Nihilism to Monism” sparked my interest in the topic), and especially Frank Arntzenius for discussion of the connection between fundamental properties and statespaces. 1I have no particular de nition of ‘abstract’ in mind; but I mean to count spacetime points, tropes, etc., as concrete.
    [Show full text]
  • This Thesis Is Submitted in Fulfilment of The. Requirements of the Degree Of
    The Problem of Evil and Theodicy in Jewish, Christian, and Islamic Thought Muhsin Akbaý This thesisis submittedin fulfilment of the. requirementsof the degreeof Doctor of Philosophy of the University of Wales University of Wales,Lampeter 1999 1 Acknowledgements I would like to expressmy sinceregratitude to ProfessorPaul Badham,who has supervisedmy research,for his valuableattention, guidance, suggestions, and comments. I would also like to thank to ProfessorRabbi Dan Cohn-Sherbokfor his helpful supervision in the Jewish side of this study, and to Dr. Dawüd al-`Alanü for his valuable suggestionsin the Islamic side of this work. It is necessarythat I extend my deepestgratitude to the Higher Educational Counsel of Turkey and canakkale Onsekiz Mart University for their financial support without which this studywould not haveemerged. I would also like to thank to Professor Mehmet Aydm and ProfessorHanifi Özcanat the Faculty of Divinity at Dokuz Eylül University, Izmir for they encouragedme to pursue an academic career in Philosophy of Religion. I am very happy to thank to the members of the library and the ACS at Lampeter for their assistance during my research. Finally, I would like to express my deepest gratitude to my wife, Emine, for her patience, support, and encouragement throughout my research. Il Abstract This thesisis the study of the problemof evil and theodicyin Jewish,Christian, and Islamic traditions.The principal aim of the study is to explore,discuss, and compare and contrastthe major responsesto the problem of evil offered in the sacredwritings, theology and philosophy of the three Abrahamic faiths. I have demonstratedhow Judaism,Christianity, and Islam understoodthe problem of evil, and respondedto the atheisticargument from evil.
    [Show full text]