The Liberal Doctrine of Hell and Universalism: a Transcendental Approach

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Liberal Doctrine of Hell and Universalism: a Transcendental Approach 1 The Liberal Doctrine of Hell and Universalism: A Transcendental Approach By Daniel L. Broadstock BA (Hons), B.Ed A thesis submitted in fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Philosophy University of Divinity 2017 2 Abstract In this thesis I have applied a Kantian methodology to present a new approach to the problem of Hell. I have engaged with two leading perspectives in this debate, the ‘liberal doctrine of Hell’ and the doctrine of Universalism, and pursued dialogue with leading theologians of each view; Jerry Walls and Jurgen Moltmann respectively. The liberal model of Hell is a modern attempt to revitalise the doctrine by recasting its nature and purpose. Rather than an instrument for the punishment of sin, the liberal model interprets Hell as God’s response to human freedom. This theory holds that God has constituted human beings with free volition of the will and desires a free relationship with them. As it is possible to resist this invitation, he has also created Hell as a place of eternal separation for those who reject him. While the invitation of grace is never withdrawn, some will remain there forever. Universalism is the view that all human beings will be saved. I have sketched a general outline of these views, illustrating them with reference to arguments proposed by key thinkers in their respective fields. I conclude that they constitute an antinomy; an a priori dilemma abstract from experience and therefore unresolvable by philosophical reasoning. I suggest that the problem of Hell can be resolved by employing a theological adaptation of Kant’s transcendental idealism: eternal separation and universal salvation can both be true, if understood as compatible manifestations of different levels of reality and perception. 3 4 5 Acknowledgements I would like to express gratitude firstly to my supervisor, Dr. Sandy Yule. He has supported me with patient encouragement and gentle wisdom, leading my thinking in new and profitable directions. My thanks are also due to my parents, who taught me first about God’s love. They have supported and encouraged this project, whilst sensitively avoiding indelicate questions about its subject and the imminence of its deadline. I am grateful for the support of MCD University, and for the use of its excellent library. I owe thanks above all to God, who breathes life to reason. 6 Table of Contents Introduction 7 1. The Traditional View: Augustine and Arminius 23 2. Kant: Transcendental Idealism and the Postulates of Pure Practical Reason 33 3. The Liberal Doctrine of Hell: Jerry Walls 50 4. Universalism: Jurgen Moltmann 72 5. A Transcendental Approach to the Problem of Hell 92 Conclusion 121 Selected Bibliography 123 7 INTRODUCTION ‘Capricious’, ‘mean minded’, ‘utterly monstrous’. These are the words used by comedian Stephen Fry to describe God in an interview in February, 2015. Asked what he would say if he were confronted by God at his death, Fry replied, ‘I’d say, bone cancer in children? How dare you. How dare you create a world in which there is such misery that's not our fault? It’s not right. It's utterly, utterly evil.’1 The philosophical term for this view is ‘anti-theism’ or ‘protest atheism’.2 Anti-theism is an expression of disbelief in God that goes beyond atheism. Where the atheist claims that there is inadequate evidence to justify belief in God, the anti-theist charges theism with moral abhorrence. Fry is suggesting that, even were he to discover that he was mistaken and that God existed and loved him, he would want nothing to do with him. He believes that the moral conditions by which God governs the world renders him unworthy of worship. For all the popular interest that interview generated, it was a modern restatement of an ancient criticism. Perhaps the most famous statement of anti-theism occurs in Dostoyevsky’s The Brothers Karamazov. In the chapter named ‘Mutiny’ Ivan Karamazov passes judgement upon God. Like Fry, Ivan focuses his moral disgust upon the suffering of children. Ivan describes an atrocity practiced by Ottoman janissaries who would befriend children only to slaughter them before their mothers.3 For Ivan, no Christian theodicy can rationalize the existence of such evils; ‘Without it, they say, man would not be able to survive upon earth, for he would not know good from evil. Why recognize that devilish good-and-evil, when it costs so much? I mean, the entire universe of knowledge is not worth the tears of that little 1 Telegraph Reporter, "Stephen Fry's 'God Is Evil' Interview Shortlisted for Religious Award," The Telegraph, accessed 04/01/2016, 2016. http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/celebritynews/12200734/Stephen-Frys-God-is- evil-interview-shortlisted-for-religious-award.html. 2 Alister McGrath, The Twilight of Atheism: The Rise and Fall of Disbelief in the Modern World (New York: Doubleday, 2004), 146. 3 Fyodor Dostoyevsky, The Brothers Karamazov, trans. David McDuff (London, England: Penguin Books, 2003), 312. 8 child addressed to “dear Father God”.’4 For Ivan, neither the damnation of wrongdoers in Hell nor even the coming of God in glory could atone for the suffering of a child. Neither the punishment of the sinner nor the reconciliation of perpetrator and victim can atone. The promise of future justice is not enough for him: I don’t want harmony. Out of a love for mankind I do not want it. I want rather to be left with sufferings that are unavenged. Let me rather remain with my unavenged sufferings and unassuaged indignation, even though I am not right. And in any case, harmony has been overestimated in value, we don’t have the money to pay so much to get in. And so I hasten to return my entry ticket.5 ‘That’s rebellion,’ says his brother Aloysha. Ivan does not want salvation, because to be saved is to consent. He is a conscientious objector: he would rather go to prison than acknowledge the authority of the court. In this, Ivan represents the paradigm of damnation suggested by the liberal doctrine of Hell: Hell is not the place to which God banishes human beings. Rather, Hell is the place from which human beings banish God. * The doctrine of Hell relies upon the conviction that humans can and will be held morally responsible for their actions. This in turn rests upon assumed frameworks of divine and human agency: God’s freedom to judge, and the genuine moral responsibility of human beings. Christian theologians have suggested varied interpretations of this agency, ranging from libertarian freedom expressed by both God and humanity, to absolute divine sovereignty, and any number of compatibilist models in between. Meanwhile, the popularity of any one interpretation of Hell has waxed and waned as our understanding of freedom and moral responsibility have contested and evolved. While the doctrine remains alive and well amongst a broad cross-section of theologians and believers, the concept itself has come under increasing attack on moral, theological and philosophical grounds from theists and atheists alike.6 A prominent view now held by those who defend the doctrine consists of a free will theodicy. In this view, for which 4 Ibid., 316. 5 Ibid., 320. 6 Jonathon L. Kvanvig, The Problem of Hell (New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 3-23. 9 I use the term ‘The liberal doctrine of Hell’7, Hell is understood as God’s response to human freedom. It is merely the provision made for those who wish to be separate from God. While God desires the salvation of all, he will not compel the compliance of any human being to ensure this outcome. Instead, he sustains them in Hell, where they may enjoy the illusory satisfaction of self-worship. This is not a punishment, and the invitation to repentance and salvation is never withdrawn. But however long God pursues the damned, some will resist him forever. This view is a relatively modern response to an ancient dilemma. Given the relative youth of this view, it is timely to assess the current state of this debate, the arguments and chief premises of its protagonists, and the primary theological and philosophical traditions upon which it draws. Methodology The overall aim of this project will be to assess the claims of the liberal doctrine of Hell in the context of its dialogue with Universalism, and to suggest a possible solution to the controversy. I will sketch out the various theological claims and assumptions that animate these competing views, and assess the force of the arguments which they present. In order to illuminate the contours of this debate I will take Jerry Walls and Jurgen Moltmann as my primary dialogue partners, both of whom are prominent exponents of Liberalism and Universalism respectively.8 Wall’s relevant work, 'Hell: The Logic of Damnation' is, in my judgment, the most sustained and rigorous defense of the liberal doctrine of Hell to date.9 It incorporates a broad and representative range of arguments deployed by other theologians in this field. As a Universalist, Jurgen Moltmann constructs his soteriological framework upon interpretations of human freedom which differ sharply from Walls, and as such he will serve as a theological counterpoint to the libertarian defense of Hell. My investigation of the debate itself will be confined largely to my evaluation of these 7 John Kronen and Eric Reitan, God's Final Victory: A Comparative Case for Universalism, Blomsbury Studies in Philosophy of Religion (London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2011), 127. 8 In this thesis, the term ‘liberal’ or ‘liberalism’ will refer narrowly to the Liberal doctrine of Hell, except where otherwise indicated.
Recommended publications
  • The Problem of Evil and the Probity of Theodicy from William Rowe's
    Liberty University Department of Philosophy The Problem of Evil and the Probity of Doing Theodicy from William Rowe’s Evidential Argument from Evil ------------------------------------------- A Thesis Presented to the Faculty of Philosophy Department of Liberty University In Partial Fulfilment Of the Requirement for the Degree Master of Arts in Philosophical Studies -------------------------------------------- By Olaoluwa Apata -------------------------------------------- Lynchburg, VA May 2016 Abstract In this research, we discussed the types of evil: moral and natural, which are cited by atheistic philosophers as evidence against the existence of God. The so-called evidence from evil has been used by the atheistic and other non-theistic scholars to raise hypothesis on evaluating the possibility or likelihood that an omnipotent, omniscient, and wholly good God exists in a world that is littered with evil. Moral evil is evil that arise from the misuse of free will by moral agents, while natural evils are natural disasters such as: earthquakes, famine, floods, hurricanes, tornadoes etc. We discussed moral evil and Plantinga’s free will defense. We also discussed the natural evil and how it poses threat to theism. The logical and the evidential arguments from evil are the forms of arguments developed from moral and natural evils. While many scholars have agreed that Plantinga’s free will defense adequately responds to the problem of logical evil, the same consensus does not necessarily apply to the evidential argument from evil. We also examined William Rowe’s evidential argument which he developed from cases of intense animal and human sufferings considered by him to be pointless or gratuitous with no known reasons or goods for which God should have allowed the visceral experience of such sufferings.
    [Show full text]
  • This Thesis Is Submitted in Fulfilment of The. Requirements of the Degree Of
    The Problem of Evil and Theodicy in Jewish, Christian, and Islamic Thought Muhsin Akbaý This thesisis submittedin fulfilment of the. requirementsof the degreeof Doctor of Philosophy of the University of Wales University of Wales,Lampeter 1999 1 Acknowledgements I would like to expressmy sinceregratitude to ProfessorPaul Badham,who has supervisedmy research,for his valuableattention, guidance, suggestions, and comments. I would also like to thank to ProfessorRabbi Dan Cohn-Sherbokfor his helpful supervision in the Jewish side of this study, and to Dr. Dawüd al-`Alanü for his valuable suggestionsin the Islamic side of this work. It is necessarythat I extend my deepestgratitude to the Higher Educational Counsel of Turkey and canakkale Onsekiz Mart University for their financial support without which this studywould not haveemerged. I would also like to thank to Professor Mehmet Aydm and ProfessorHanifi Özcanat the Faculty of Divinity at Dokuz Eylül University, Izmir for they encouragedme to pursue an academic career in Philosophy of Religion. I am very happy to thank to the members of the library and the ACS at Lampeter for their assistance during my research. Finally, I would like to express my deepest gratitude to my wife, Emine, for her patience, support, and encouragement throughout my research. Il Abstract This thesisis the study of the problemof evil and theodicyin Jewish,Christian, and Islamic traditions.The principal aim of the study is to explore,discuss, and compare and contrastthe major responsesto the problem of evil offered in the sacredwritings, theology and philosophy of the three Abrahamic faiths. I have demonstratedhow Judaism,Christianity, and Islam understoodthe problem of evil, and respondedto the atheisticargument from evil.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Religion
    Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Religion INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY: PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION BEAU BRANSON, MARCUS WILLIAM HUNT, TIMOTHY D KNEPPER, ROBERT SLOAN LEE, STEVEN STEYL, HANS VAN EYGHEN, BEAU BRANSON (BOOK EDITOR), AND CHRISTINA HENDRICKS (SERIES EDITOR) Rebus Community Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Religion by Beau Branson, Marcus William Hunt, Timothy D Knepper, Robert Sloan Lee, Steven Steyl, Hans Van Eyghen, Beau Branson (Book Editor), and Christina Hendricks (Series Editor) is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted. DEDICATION To Roger Branson — the best dad I ever had. For all the sacrifices I know ouy made. And for all the ones I don’t. CONTENTS What is an Open Textbook? ix Christina Hendricks How to Access and Use the Books xi Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Series xiii Christina Hendricks Praise for the Book xvi Acknowledgements xviii Beau Branson and Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Book 1 Beau Branson 1. The Intertwining of Philosophy and Religion in the Western Tradition 7 Beau Branson 2. Reasons to Believe – Theoretical Arguments 18 Marcus William Hunt 3. Non-Standard Arguments for God’s Existence 30 Robert Sloan Lee 4. Reasons Not to Believe 49 Steven Steyl 5. Debunking Arguments against Theistic Belief 62 Hans Van Eyghen 6. From Philosophy of (Mono)theism to Philosophy of Religions 74 Timothy D Knepper Glossary 87 About the Contributors 91 Feedback and Suggestions 94 Adoption Form 95 Licensing and Attribution Information 96 Review Statement 98 Accessibility Assessment 99 Version History 101 WHAT IS AN OPEN TEXTBOOK? CHRISTINA HENDRICKS An open textbook is like a commercial textbook, except: (1) it is publicly available online free of charge (and at low-cost in print), and (2) it has an open license that allows others to reuse it, download and revise it, and redistribute it.
    [Show full text]
  • A Craigian Theodicy of Hell
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 17 Issue 1 Article 6 1-1-2000 A Craigian Theodicy of Hell Charles Seymour Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Seymour, Charles (2000) "A Craigian Theodicy of Hell," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 17 : Iss. 1 , Article 6. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol17/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. A CRAIGIAN THEODICY OF HELL Charles Seymour Problem: if God has middle knowledge, he should actualize a world con­ taining only persons whom he knows would freely choose heaven. Thus there should be no hell. Craig offers an answer to this problem in his article " 'No Other Name': a Middle Knowledge Perspective on the Exclusivity of Salvation Through Christ." Craig is mainly concerned to give a logically possible defense of hell, though he thinks his suggestion does not lack the sort of plausibility needed for a theodicy. I consider various objections to the latter assessment. My conclusion is that, although Craig's argument is implausible as a theodicy of conservative exclusivist soteriology, it is useful for less traditional ideas of hell.
    [Show full text]
  • The Incompatibility Between Free Will Theodicies and Religious Experience
    The Incompatibility between Free Will Theodicies and Religious Experience A thesis submitted to the University of Birmingham as part of the fulfilment of MASTER OF PHILOSOPHY in Philosophy By Benjamin Matheson Department of Philosophy School of Philosophy, Theology and Religion The University of Birmingham April 2010 University of Birmingham Research Archive e-theses repository This unpublished thesis/dissertation is copyright of the author and/or third parties. The intellectual property rights of the author or third parties in respect of this work are as defined by The Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988 or as modified by any successor legislation. Any use made of information contained in this thesis/dissertation must be in accordance with that legislation and must be properly acknowledged. Further distribution or reproduction in any format is prohibited without the permission of the copyright holder. i Abstract This thesis suggests a novel problem for theists. This problem is that there is an incompatibility between free will theodicies and religious experience. Free will theodicies are responses to the problem of evil and religious experience is form of interaction between God and people. The free will theodicies that are discussed say that God gives us free will for two purposes. These purposes are to excuse God from direct responsibility for evil in the world and to act as a qualifying factor in who goes where when we die (i.e. either Heaven or Hell). Religious experience, it will be argued, usually, if not always, gives recipients of religious experience moral benefits. The giving of moral benefits in religious experience acts to undermine the second purpose we are said to have been given free will and hence generates the incompatibility between free will theodicies and religious experience.
    [Show full text]
  • The Spiritual Theology of Julian of Norwich As a Resource for Issues In
    The Spiritual Theology of Julian of Norwich as a Resource for Issues in Theoretical and Pastoral Theodicy by Kwang-Cheol Oh A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Knox College and the Pastoral Department of the Toronto School of Theology in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Theology awarded by the University of St. Michael’s College © Copyright by Kwang-Cheol Oh 2013 The Spiritual Theology of Julian of Norwich as a Resource for Issues in Theoretical and Pastoral Theodicy Kwang-Cheol Oh Doctor of Philosophy University of St. Michael’s College 2013 ABSTRACT This thesis analyzes the spiritual theology of Julian of Norwich in light of certain developments in contemporary theodicy. It begins by exploring in a creative and critical fashion the current debates between theoretical and practical (or pastoral) theodicy. Some theologians who favor pastoral responses to evil and suffering argue that theoretical theodicy is mistaken, misguided and even immoral because it legitimizes and perpetuates evil in the world, silences the voices of victims, and justifies the social structures that produce suffering. In critically exploring these claims, I argue that these views of pastoral theodicists and the responses from those who support theoretical theodicy trigger three significant issues for contemporary theodicy: (1) the question of theoretical support for practical theodicy; (2) the nature and actions of God in relation to human suffering; and (3) the question of destructive suffering experienced by people. This thesis then focuses on Julian of Norwich’s (1342-1416) spiritual theology and its implications and relevance to these contemporary issues in theodicy.
    [Show full text]
  • Modern Theological Debates of Hell in the USA
    Polonia Sacra 25 (2021) nr 2 (64) ∙ s. 115–130 ISSN 1428-5673; e-ISSN 2391-6575 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.15633/ps.3984 Received: Nov 22, 2020 | Accepted: Jan 23, 2021 | Published: June 30, 2021 Sydney Sadowski1 ORCID: 0000-0002-9117-4086; [email protected] The Pontifical University of John Paul II in Krakow Modern Theological Debates of Hell in the USA Abstract Among the differing Christian denominations there are various viewpoints regarding hell. This article presents differing viewpoints of the theological questions concerning hell that have been debated over the last ten years (2010–2020) in the United States in the theological arena as well as the popular press. The positions of annihilationism, universalism, and the traditional viewpoint are to be surveyed. The differing philosophical, theological and biblical viewpoints are presented for each general category. The article strives to give a general overview of the various theologies and to show that such theological investigation is of urgent importance for Christians today. Keywords: Hell, annihilationism, universalism, traditional viewpoint Streszczenie Współczesna debata teologiczna o piekle w USA Wśród różnych wyznań chrześcijańskich istnieją rozmaite poglądy na temat piekła. W artykule przedstawiono różnorodne stanowiska teologiczne dotyczące piekła, nad którymi debatowano w ciągu ostatnich dziesięciu lat (2010–2020) w Stanach Zjednoczonych na płaszczyźnie teologicznej oraz w prasie popularnej. Badane są tutaj: anihilacjonizm, uniwersalizm i tradycyjny punkt widzenia. Dla każdej generalnej kategorii przedstawiono różne teorie filozoficzne, teologiczne i biblijne. W artykule starano się zaprezentować ogólny przegląd rozmaitych teologii, aby pokazać, że takie teologiczne dociekania powinny być niezwłocznie podjęte, bo mają bardzo ważne znaczenie dla współczesnych chrześcijan.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Religion
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Cumulative Index Volumes 1-38 (1970-1995) Compiled by NAYNA }IVAN and EUGENE THOMAS LONG With the assistance of PATAKIANTAL Part One: Articles Part Two: Review Articles Part Three: Book Reviews Kluwer Academic Publishers DORDRECHT / BOSTON / LONDON 184 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL FOR PlllLOSOPHY OF RELIGION Part One: Articles Special issues 1970 (Volume 1, No.3) Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: Commemorating the 200th anniversary of his birth (27 August 1770) with contributions by Darrel E. Christensen, Murray Greene, Edgar H. Henderson, Robert 1. Perkins, Efraim Shmeli & Frederick G. Weiss 1988 (Volume 24, Nos. 1-2) The problem of evil with contributions by Keith Chrzan, David A. Conway, R. Z. Friedman, C. Robert Mesle, Bruce R. Reichenbach & Jane Mary Trau 1992 (Volume 31, Nos. 2-3) The epistemic status of religious belief guest-edited by Bowman 1. Clarke & William 1. Power with contributions by William P. Alston, Bowman L. Clarke, Frederick Ferre, Eugene Th. Long, William L. Power, Theodore Runyon & Keith E. Yandell 1995 (Volume 38, Nos. 1-3) God, reason and religions edited by Eugene Th. Long with contributions by William P. Alston, David B. Burrell, Bowman 1. Clarke, Eugene Th. Long, Robert Cummings Neville, Philip 1. Quinn, William 1. Rowe, Robert P. Scharlemann, John E. Smith, Richard Swinburne & Merold Westphal Articles on author's name in alphabetical/chronological order Adams, E. M. (1985) The accountability of religiOUS discourse, 18(1-2): 3-17. Alon, Ilai see Graves, David & Alon, Ilai (1995). Alston, William P. (1985) Divine foreknowledge and alternative conceptions of human freedom, 18(1-2): 19-32.
    [Show full text]
  • Hell and the Problem of Evil
    Hell and the Problem of Evil Andrei A. Buckareff and Allen Plug Marist College and Malone University 1. Introduction While accounts of the nature of hell vary within and between religious traditions, formulations of the traditional doctrine include at least the following five elements. E1 Some persons do or will reside in hell and will be there for an infinite period of time. E2 Hell is the residence of those persons who have failed to satisfy some condition(s) dictated by God as necessary to avoid hell and enjoy heaven. E3 The cumulative well-being and well-being at any moment of any resident of hell is negative. E4 Those in hell are blocked from leaving. E5 Those in hell are consigned to hell as punishment for either failing to satisfy the condition(s) God requires for one to avoid hell or for actual sins committed or both. In this essay we explain why the doctrine of hell poses a problem of evil for traditional theists in the Abrahamic religions (Christianity, Judaism, and Islam) and how some have responded to the problem. Our focus is entirely on recent work in analytic philosophical theology. Given that the recent philosophical debates over hell have largely transpired within the context of the Christian theistic tradition, Christian theism provides the backdrop for how we frame the problem and some of the responses in much of what follows. However, this should not be taken as an indication of the problem as unique to traditional Christianity or even that the responses to the problem considered are only available to those who are working from within the Christian tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • The Tough-Love Proposal: a Novel Theodicy Le Pham Thai
    THE TOUGH-LOVE PROPOSAL: A NOVEL THEODICY LE PHAM THAI A doctoral thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in the DEPARTMENT OF SYSTEMATIC AND HISTORICAL THEOLOGY FACULTY OF THEOLOGY AND RELIGION UNIVERSITY OF PRETORIA PROMOTER: PROFESSOR JERRY PILLAY June 2020 i TABLE OF CONTENTS TABLE OF CONTENTS…………………………………………………………………………ii DECLARATION OF ORIGINALITY……………………………………………………………x ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ……………………………………………………………………...xi SUMMARY……………………………………………………………………………………...xii CHAPTER ONE: OVERVIEW AND OBJECTIVES OF THE STUDY………………………...1 1.1 Introduction……………………………………………………………………………1 1.2 The Research Problem………………………………………………………………...6 1.3 Research Objectives…………………………………………………………………...7 1.4 Research Methodology………………………………………………………………..8 1.5 Delimitations of Study……………………………………………………………….12 1.6 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………………...12 CHAPTER TWO: LITERATURE REVIEW……………………………………………………14 2.1 Introduction…………………………………………………………………………..14 2.2 Definitions of Terms…………………………………………………………………15 2.2.1 Definition of Evil……………………………………………………………….16 2.2.2 Definition of Moral Evil………………………………………………………..17 ii 2.2.3 Definition of Natural Evil……………………………………………………....18 2.2.4 Definition of Social Evil………………………………………………………..20 2.2.5 A Combination of Evils………………………………………………………...22 2.2.6 Definition of Suffering………………………………………………………….22 2.2.7 The Problems of Evil…………………………………………………………...24 2.3 The Logical Problem of Evil………………………………………………………....24 2.3.1 The Logical Argument………………………………………………………….24
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Hell
    THE PROBLEM OF HELL John M. DePoe The Christian doctrine of hell has long been a stumbling block for people to overcome when accepting Christianity. For surely a good God would not send people to hell, especially those who lead a pretty good life and had no possible opportunity to accept Christianity. Below, I will proceed to resolve this problem by first sharpening the apparent disharmony of the doctrine of hell, then pointing out some misconceptions, and finally by providing a positive Christian defense for the classic doctrine of hell. THE PROBLEM Typically the problem for the doctrine of hell is established as an unlikely consequence given that if the Christian God exists, he would essentially possess the characteristics of love, mercy, goodness, kindness, etc. Thus, based on the fact that God essentially possesses these characteristics maximally, then it is inconsistent for God also to create a place for the purpose of punishing those who chose not to believe in him, especially those who aren't overtly evil and/or had minimal or zero opportunity to accept Christianity. Some proponents of this objection go further to claim that if God creates hell and damns people to it, then God is positively evil. Another problem for the doctrine of hell comes from certain interpretations in the Bible. For example, in Matthew 7:13-14 Jesus seems to teach that the broad path, which is populated by those bound for hell, has a larger following than the narrow way, which leads to heaven. If this is so, one wonders why a good God would create a world knowing that a lopsided outcome was inevitable? Moreover, 1 Timothy 2:4 and 2 Peter 3:9 both seem to teach that God desires no one to go to hell.
    [Show full text]
  • Atheist Symbols Atheism
    Atheist symbols Atheism What is it? Atheism Defined • Atheism [ey-thee-iz-uhm] -noun : a lack of belief in a god or gods. • Atheism deals with belief, not knowledge. • Atheism makes no positive claims. • Percent of Atheists in the U.S. population. Degrees of Atheism • Strong Atheists- I believe that No gods exists • Weak Atheists- I have no belief in any gods • Anti-theist- I am opposed to all religions. • Agnostic- Used by many to mean a “fence- sitter” or undecided. Misconceptions about Atheism • Atheism is a religion. • Atheists don’t believe in anything. • Atheists hate god. • Atheists worship the devil. • Atheists are unhappy angry people. • Atheists just need to hear the “good news”. • Atheists that have lost their faith were never true believers. • Atheists have no morals • Atheists want to take away peoples faith. • Atheism leads to other societal woes. • Atheists don’t exist. History of Atheism • Earliest form of the Word recorded in 600 B.C. in ancient Greek. • 1566 first recorded use of Atheist. (French) • Late 1700’s was first used as a self description. • In the 1840’s the first major self-avowed American Atheists were Elizabeth Cody Stanton and Susan B. Anthony. Both were active in women’s Suffrage. • 1885 -Col. Robert Ingersoll was elected the president of the American Secular Union. This was the first organized secular organization in America. Mark Twain was one of the first members. History of Atheism • 1859-Darwin published his world changing book “On the origin of species” • Mid-1800’s to the first world war, Atheist and Secularist’s were involved in many social issues: -Abortion, slavery, contraception, sufferage • 1925- Scope’s Monkey trail was the beginning of the culture wars in America.
    [Show full text]