This Thesis Is Submitted in Fulfilment of The. Requirements of the Degree Of

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

This Thesis Is Submitted in Fulfilment of The. Requirements of the Degree Of The Problem of Evil and Theodicy in Jewish, Christian, and Islamic Thought Muhsin Akbaý This thesisis submittedin fulfilment of the. requirementsof the degreeof Doctor of Philosophy of the University of Wales University of Wales,Lampeter 1999 1 Acknowledgements I would like to expressmy sinceregratitude to ProfessorPaul Badham,who has supervisedmy research,for his valuableattention, guidance, suggestions, and comments. I would also like to thank to ProfessorRabbi Dan Cohn-Sherbokfor his helpful supervision in the Jewish side of this study, and to Dr. Dawüd al-`Alanü for his valuable suggestionsin the Islamic side of this work. It is necessarythat I extend my deepestgratitude to the Higher Educational Counsel of Turkey and canakkale Onsekiz Mart University for their financial support without which this studywould not haveemerged. I would also like to thank to Professor Mehmet Aydm and ProfessorHanifi Özcanat the Faculty of Divinity at Dokuz Eylül University, Izmir for they encouragedme to pursue an academic career in Philosophy of Religion. I am very happy to thank to the members of the library and the ACS at Lampeter for their assistance during my research. Finally, I would like to express my deepest gratitude to my wife, Emine, for her patience, support, and encouragement throughout my research. Il Abstract This thesisis the study of the problemof evil and theodicyin Jewish,Christian, and Islamic traditions.The principal aim of the study is to explore,discuss, and compare and contrastthe major responsesto the problem of evil offered in the sacredwritings, theology and philosophy of the three Abrahamic faiths. I have demonstratedhow Judaism,Christianity, and Islam understoodthe problem of evil, and respondedto the atheisticargument from evil. In Preamble,I give a brief introductoryto the discussionsof the problem of evil in the westernphilosophy of religion. I outline the atheisticformulations of the problem of evil, the theistic conceptof God, evil, and theodicy. In the Part Two, I explore the Jewish, Christian, and Islamic responsesto the problem of suffering. In Part Three, I compare and contrast the responsesoffered in the Part Two. I conclude from the discussion of the responsesthat some features of Augustinianand Irenaeantheodicy in Christiantradition can be detectedin Jewish and Islamic theodicies.While the former doesnot provide a reasonableanswer to the fact of evil, the latter is promising. However,the Irenaeantype of theodicies,too, do not solve the problem of evil conclusively. They provide a reasonable solution affirming both the belief in God and evil. III Abbreviations AH: Anno Hegirae("Year of the Hijra") Am.: The Book ofAmos in Tanakh Art.: Article c.: Circa ("about") CE: CommonEra cf.: Confer("compare") ch.: Chapter Col.: TheLetter of Paul to the Colossiansin the New Testament 2 Cor.: TheSecond Letter of Paul to the Corinthiansin the New Testament d.: Death Deut.: TheBook of Deuteronomyin Tanakh Gen.: TheBook of Genesisin Tanakh Ecc.: The Book of Ecclesiastes in Tanakh Ed(s).: Editor(s) e.g.: Exemplia gratia ("for example") et al.: Et alia ("and others") etc.: Etcetera ("and so on") Ex.: The Book of Exodus in Tanakh Ezek.: The Book of Ezekiel in Tanakh Heb.: The Letter to the Hebrews in the New Testament i. e.: Id est ("that is") Isa.: TheBook of Isaiah in Tanakh Jas.: The Letter of James in the New Testament Jer.: The Book ofJeremiah in Tanakh Matt.: The Gospel According to Matthew in the New Testament n.d.: No date n.: Footnote/endnote Num.: TheBook of Numbersin Tanakh IV p: Part 1 Pet.: TheFirst Letter of Peter in the New Testament Phil.: TheLetter of Paul to the Philippiansin the New Testament Prov.: TheBook of Proverbsin Tanakh Ps.: TheBook of Psalmsin Tanakh Q.: Question Rev.: TheRevelation to John in the New Testament Rom.: TheLetter of Paul to the Romansin the New Testament 2 Sam.: TheBook of 2 Samuelin Tanakh 1 Thes.: TheFirst Letter of Paul to the Thessaloniansin the New Testament Trans.: Translated V Transliterations of Arabic Words and Names ": a t long b: vowel: a . z Y: b u: t gh 4!d: th f C: j i: q k kh 1 d m 1: dh 0: n r A: h z j consonant: w long ,.e: s j vowel: ü sh 4 consonant: y $ 4 long vowel: i d ShortVowels au vi CONTENTS Acknowledgments 1 Abstract II Abbreviations 111 Transliterations Y INTRODUCTION 1 PART ONE: PREAMBLE 1.THE CONSTITUENTSOF TIlE PROBLEMOF EVIL 4 A. The Formulationsof the Problemof Evil 5 B. The TheisticConcept of God 9 C. Evil, Sufferingand Pain 14 D. Theodicy 15 PART TWO: THE THEODICIES II. THE JEWISH THEODICIES 17 E. The Major Responsesof Tanakh 19 1. Sufferingas Retribution 19 2. Suffering as Discipline and Test 23 3. The Free-Will Explanation 25 4. Suffering as Redemption: 26 5. Mystery 30 F. The JewishTheological And PhilosophicalTheodicies 33 1. The TraditionalTheodicies 33 a. The Privationof Good 33 b. The Free-Will Explanation 37 c. The VicariousSuffering 41 d. The EschatologicalResolution 46 2. The Modern Theodicies 51 a. The Holocaustas a New Revelation 51 VII b. The Holocaustas TheTremendson 56 c. A New VoluntaryCovenant 60 3. The Anti-Theodicies 67 a. The Protestof God'sSilence 67 b. The DeathOf God 71 III. THE CHRISTIAN THEODICIES 75 G. The Major Responsesof the New Testament 75 1. Sufferingas Retribution 0 77 2. Suffering as Discipline and Test 83 3. Sufferingas Redemption 84 4. The EschatologicalResolution 90 IL The ChristianTheological And PhilosophicalTheodicies 94 1. The TraditionalTheodicies 95 a. The AugustinianTheodicy 95 b. The IrenaeanTheodicy 114 2. The Modem Theodicies 126 a. ProcessTheodicy 126 b. The Free-W'dl Defence 135 c. TheNatural Law Theodicy 148 d. The Soul-MakingTheodicy 167 IV. THE MUSLIM THEODICIES 185 1. Sufferingas Retribution 191 2. The Free-Will Explanation 195 3. Sufferingas Discipline andTest 200 4. The EschatologicalResponse 205 J. The Muslim TheologicalAnd PhilosophicalTheodicies 210 1. The Privationof Good 210 2. The Free-Will Explanation 217 3. The Best-Possible-WorldTheodicy 224 4. Sufferingas Redemption 233 VIII PART THREE: ANALYSIS V. A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS 244 K. An Analysisof the ScripturalTheodicies 247 L. An Analysisof the Theologicaland Philosophical Theodicies 262 M. Conclusion 280 GLOSSARY 288 BIBLIOGRAPHY 291 1 INTRODUCTION The problem of evil is one of the major issuesof the Westernphilosophy of religion. It is the genericname for to the atheisticargument from the existenceof evil against the theistic belief in God. As an academicdiscipline, philosophy of religion examinesthe reasonablenessand coherenceof religiousbeliefs suchas belief in God, life after death, miracle and the like taking into account the data available in modern knowledge,particularly scienceand philosophy. Sincethe perceptionof religion differs from one religion to another, and interpretationsof knowledge, and methodology of philosophyvary with eachphilosophical theory, philosophyof religion showsa manifold structure consisting of various theological and philosophical viewpoints including of atheism. The problem of evil is one of these atheistic arguments based on the so-called inconsistencyof the reality of evil, suffering, and pain in the world with the existenceof all-powerful and compassionateGod. Atheism as a philosophical position can be characterisedas a way of denial of the theistic belief in God. Atheist philosophersput forward several argumentsto justify the atheistic assertionthat religious claims, and particularly that God exists, are logically inconsistent and unreasonable.Personal experiencesof pain and sorrow may also lead individuals to ask themselvessuch questionsas "why me?" and "what have I done to deservethis? ". This is what can be calledthe practicalproblem of evil, which requiresapplicable solutions suited to personal circumstances. On the other hand, the philosophical problem is a challenge and threat of the reality evil to the theistic belief in God. Atheist philosophersformally statethis as a philosophicalargument in the westernphilosophy of religion. 2 The major theistic religions of the world againstwhich the questionof evil is raised particularly are Judaism,Christianity, and Islam. It is the claim of the three religions that they have originatedfrom the sameancestral source, namely the patriarch Abraham.That is why they are often called the Abrahamic faiths. Moreover, the three religions all affirm that there is a good and all-powerful God. For that reason,they are also called the theistic andmonotheistic faiths. Furthermore,I can saythis much at this point that Jewish,Christian, and Islamic traditions agree with the fact that there is evil, suffering and pain in the world even though there are different interpretations regarding to the nature of evil. The happenings of evil are,in fact, partly a reasonfor the existenceof religions.That is to say,the theistic faiths aim at removing evil and suffering from human lives providing peace and happiness in this world as well as in life after death. Therefore, the atheistic argument from evil directly challenges each three theistic faiths requiring an answer that reconciles the existenceof evil in the world with the existenceof all-powerful and compassionate God. It is the purposeof this study to explore,discuss and comparethe responsesto the problem of evil offeredby the major theistic faiths, namely,Judaism, Christianity and Islam. In pursuingthis purpose,I shall, firstly, look up the sacredwritings of the three theistic faiths as the foundation of theological and philosophicalresponses to evil and suffering. I shall focus on the canonof Jewishscriptures, namely,
Recommended publications
  • Theodicy: an Overview
    1 Theodicy: An Overview Introduction All of us struggle at one time or another in life with why evil happens to someone, either ourselves, our family, our friends, our nation, or perhaps some particularly disturbing instance in the news—a child raped, a school shooting, genocide in another country, a terrorist bombing. The following material is meant to give an overview of the discussion of this issue as it takes place in several circles, especially that of the Christian church. I. The Problem of Evil Defined Three terms, "the problem of evil," "theodicy," and "defense" are important to our discussion. The first two are often used as synonyms, but strictly speaking the problem of evil is the larger issue of which theodicy is a subset because one can have a secular problem of evil. Evil is understood as a problem when we seek to explain why it exists (Unde malum?) and what its relationship is to the world as a whole. Indeed, something might be considered evil when it calls into question our basic trust in the order and structure of our world. Peter Berger in particular has argued that explanations of evil are necessary for social structures to stay themselves against chaotic forces. It follows, then, that such an explanation has an impact on the whole person. As David Blumenthal observes, a good theodicy is one that has three characteristics: 1. "[I]t should leave one with one’s sense of reality intact." (It tells the truth about reality.) 2. "[I]t should leave one empowered within the intellectual-moral system in which one lives." (Namely, it should not deny God’s basic power or goodness.) 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Creation As Theodicy: in Defense of a Kabbalistic Approach to Evil
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 14 Issue 4 Article 6 10-1-1997 Creation as Theodicy: In Defense of a Kabbalistic Approach to Evil Robert Oakes Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Oakes, Robert (1997) "Creation as Theodicy: In Defense of a Kabbalistic Approach to Evil," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 14 : Iss. 4 , Article 6. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil199714441 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol14/iss4/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. CREATION AS THEODICY: IN DEFENSE OF A KABBALISTIC APPROACH TO EVIL Robert Oakes The doctrine of Tzimzum (or divine "withdrawal") occupies pride of place in the Jewish mystical tradition as a response to what is arguably the chief theo­ logical or metaphysical concern of that tradition: namely, how God's Infinity or Absolute Unlimitedness does not preclude the existence of a distinct domain of finite being. Alternatively, how can it be that God, by virtue of His Maximal Plenteousness, does not exhaust the whole of Reality? I attempt to show that, while a plausible argument - one that does not involve the idea of Tzimzum - can be mounted against this "pantheism" problem, the doctrine of Tzimzum has considerable force as the nucleus of a theodicy.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy As a Path to Happiness
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto Philosophy as a Path to Happiness Attainment of Happiness in Arabic Peripatetic and Ismaili Philosophy Janne Mattila ACADEMIC DISSERTATION To be publicly discussed, by due permission of the Faculty of Arts at the University of Helsinki in auditorium XII, University main building, on the 13th of June, 2011 at 12 o’clock. ISBN 978-952-92-9077-2 (paperback) ISBN 978-952-10-7001-3 (PDF) http://ethesis.helsinki.fi/ Helsinki University Print Helsinki 2011 2 Abstract The aim of this study is to explore the idea of philosophy as a path to happiness in medieval Arabic philosophy. The starting point is in comparison of two distinct currents within Arabic philosophy between the 10th and early 11th centuries, Peripatetic philosophy, represented by al-Fārābī and Ibn Sīnā, and Ismaili philosophy represented by al-Kirmānī and the Brethren of Purity. These two distinct groups of sources initially offer two contrasting views about philosophy. The attitude of the Peripatetic philosophers is rationalistic and secular in spirit, whereas for the Ismailis philosophy represents the esoteric truth behind revelation. Still, the two currents of thought converge in their view that the ultimate purpose of philosophy lies in its ability to lead man towards happiness. Moreover, they share a common concept of happiness as a contemplative ideal of human perfection, merged together with the Neoplatonic goal of the soul’s reascent to the spiritual world. Finally, for both happiness refers primarily to an otherworldly state thereby becoming a philosophical interpretation of the Quranic accounts of the afterlife.
    [Show full text]
  • |FREE| God, Freedom and Evil
    GOD, FREEDOM AND EVIL EBOOK Author: Alvin Plantinga Number of Pages: 121 pages Published Date: 21 Mar 1989 Publisher: William B Eerdmans Publishing Co Publication Country: Grand Rapids, United States Language: English ISBN: 9780802817310 Download Link: CLICK HERE God, Freedom And Evil Online Read Hick claims that it would be impossible Freedom and Evil the deity to have created human with free will and yet not with the ability to choose evil. Now that we have these definitions, Plantinga returns to the original question: could God have created any world He wanted to? Therefore, every world that God creates must have not only the possibility of evil in it but actual evil as well. Freedom and Evil contingent being is dependent on external states of affairs for its existence; it could either God or not exist. For those who hold that Freedom and Evil attempt at proving that there is a deity of any kind have failed because they are not psychologically convincing or logically compelling there is no Problem of Evil. God for the Existence of God. Feb 12, Wyatt Houtz rated it did not like it Shelves: abandoned. Coming Soon. God is not a contingent being. Related Papers. July 8, at pm. Why create a universe with even the possibility of corruption? Reviews God, Freedom And Evil Plantinga argues convincingly, I think the contrary: there is no contradiction. Now, add to this the observation that there is evil in the world. I worry a bit that modal logic is too weak of a tool to prove the existence of God in the sense that he is a being of maximal greatness.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Evil S2
    Theodicy Episode 190 THE PROBLEM OF EVIL S2 I. KEY THOUGHTS S3 1. The existence of evil is the greatest challenge for theism. S4 1. “There is little doubt that the problem of evil is the most serious intellectual difficulty for theism.” Stephen Davis, Encountering Evil (Knox Press, 1981), 2 THE PROBLEM S5 IF God is all-knowing, THEN he must know about evil IF God is all-loving, THEN he must want to abolish evil IF God is all-powerful, THEN he must be able to abolish evil BUT evil exists THEREFORE God is not all-loving & not all-powerful OR God does not exist THE SOLUTION S6 Theodicy èåïò (theos) God äéêç (dikç) justice DEF: arguments justifying the existence of evil in a world created by an all-loving, all-powerful, and all-knowing God 2. ALL theodicies include the notion of “Greater Good” S7 God allows evil because it serves an ultimate purpose in bringing overall good into the world º EG selling of Joseph by his brothers he ends up in Egypt & his family is saved from famine S8 2. “You [his brothers] intended to harm me, but God intended it for good to accomplish what is now being done, the saving of many lives.” Gen 50:20 3. Christian Theodicies have been intimately connected to Gen 3 & the Fall S9 K especially the COSMIC FALL Protestant Reformer John Calvin S10 3. “The earth was cursed on account of Adam [Gen 3:18] ... the whole order of nature was subverted by the sin of man ... Moses does not enumerate all the disadvantages in which man, by sin, has involved himself; for it appears that all the evils of the present life, which experience proves to be innumerable, have proceeded from the same fountain.
    [Show full text]
  • A Response to Adams in the Augustinian Tradition
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 19 Issue 1 Article 6 1-1-2002 The Abolition of Sin: A Response to Adams in the Augustinian Tradition Katherin A. Rogers Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Rogers, Katherin A. (2002) "The Abolition of Sin: A Response to Adams in the Augustinian Tradition," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 19 : Iss. 1 , Article 6. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol19/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. THE ABOLITION OF SIN: A RESPONSE TO ADAMS IN THE AUGUSTINIAN TRADITION Ka therin A. Rogers Augustine, Anselm, and Aquinas located the source of human misery in sin, freely choosing against God. Sin is permitted by God because the dig­ nity of the human creature requires that it be able to make free choices and live with their consequences. In Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God, Marilyn Adams critiques this view and offers an alternative explanation. I argue that Adams's criticisms do not connect with the traditional view and her proposed alternative entails conclusions which Christians should find insupportable, including the abolition of sin and the view that God is not good in any meaningful sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustinian Motifs in Mandeville's Theory of Society
    Journal of Markets & Morality Volume 19, Number 2 (Fall 2016): 317–338 Copyright © 2016 Augustinian Motifs Joost W. Hengstmengel in Mandeville’s Faculty of Philosophy Erasmus Institute for Philosophy Theory of Society and Economics In the eighteenth century, the Dutch-born satirist Bernard Mandeville was generally associated with deism and atheism. Nowadays scholarly opinions about his theo- logical outlook are strongly divided. Instead of reassessing what Mandeville really believed, this article focuses on three theological motifs that recur in Mandeville’s Fable of the Bees. These typically Augustinian ideas concerning the fall of man, the two faces of evil, and the distinction between worldly and real happiness deserves more attention than they have hitherto received. Even if E. G. Hundert is right that Mandeville “abandoned the Augustinian premises” of the Calvinists and the Jansenists, he clearly did not forsake all of them. I argue that the three motifs are part of a framework within which Mandeville develops his theory of man and society. Interestingly, Mandeville’s well-known thesis “private vices, public benefits” also seems to build on these Augustinian ideas. Introduction1 The physician and philosopher Bernard Mandeville (1660–1733) was undoubtedly one of the most controversial writers of the eighteenth century. His is one of only a few names that were mentioned in one and the same breath with Machiavelli, Spinoza, and Hobbes; in the early modern period, this certainly was no compli- ment. In the eyes of his contemporaries, Mandeville, like these other radical writers, had dared to undermine sacred religion, true virtue, and good order. The Anglo-Dutch writer proposed a plan for the establishment of public houses of prostitution, authored a book with liberal thoughts on religion and theology, and produced erotic dialogues and poems.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Evil As a Moral Objection to Theism
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Birmingham Research Archive, E-theses Repository THE PROBLEM OF EVIL AS A MORAL OBJECTION TO THEISM by TOBY GEORGE BETENSON A thesis submitted to the University of Birmingham for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY. Department of Philosophy School of Philosophy, Theology and Religion College of Arts and Law University of Birmingham September 2014 University of Birmingham Research Archive e-theses repository This unpublished thesis/dissertation is copyright of the author and/or third parties. The intellectual property rights of the author or third parties in respect of this work are as defined by The Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988 or as modified by any successor legislation. Any use made of information contained in this thesis/dissertation must be in accordance with that legislation and must be properly acknowledged. Further distribution or reproduction in any format is prohibited without the permission of the copyright holder. Abstract: I argue that the problem of evil can be a moral objection to theistic belief. The thesis has three broad sections, each establishing an element in this argument. Section one establishes the logically binding nature of the problem of evil: The problem of evil must be solved, if you are to believe in God. And yet, I borrow from J. L. Mackie’s criticisms of the moral argument for the existence of God, and argue that the fundamentally evaluative nature of the premises within the problem of evil entails that it cannot be used to argue for the non- existence of God.
    [Show full text]
  • Evil and the Ontological Disproof
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 9-2017 Evil and the Ontological Disproof Carl J. Brownson III The Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/2155 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] EVIL AND THE ONTOLOGICAL DISPROOF by CARL BROWNSON A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, City University of New York 2017 1 © 2017 CARL BROWNSON All Rights Reserved ii Evil and the Ontological Disproof by Carl Brownson This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Date Graham Priest Chair of Examining Committee Date Iakovos Vasiliou Executive Officer Supervisory Committee: Stephen Grover, advisor Graham Priest Peter Simpson Nickolas Pappas Robert Lovering THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii ABSTRACT Evil and the Ontological Disproof by Carl Brownson Advisor: Stephen Grover This dissertation is a revival of the ontological disproof, an ontological argument against the existence of God. The ontological disproof, in its original form, argues that God is impossible, because if God exists, he must exist necessarily, and necessary existence is impossible. The notion of necessary existence has been largely rehabilitated since this argument was first offered in 1948, and the argument has accordingly lost much of its force.
    [Show full text]
  • Listen to the Song
    Listen to the song. Use the song to help you re-cap the unit so far: • What is evil and suffering? Then think about… • How can evil and suffering be a problem to Christians? http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=WpYeekQkAdc Oracy focus RE Skills focus Peer teaching Evaluation How do Christians respond to the PoE? EVALUATE the Augustinian and Irenaean responses to evil and suffering. EXPLAIN Christian responses to the problem of evil and suffering. Show UNDERSTANDING of how evil and suffering can be a problem to Christians. Title: How do Christians explain evil and suffering? The Problem of Evil: A God who is benevolent will have a motive to get rid of evil. A God who is omnipotent will have the ability to get rid of evil. Evil exists in the world. Therefore, either God does not exist or he is not omnipotent and omnibenevolent. The The Augustinian Irenaean Theodicy Theodicy What does the word ‘theodicy’ mean? A theodicy is an attempt to answer how a good, all- loving God allows evil and suffering in the world. Similarities Differences Use the information on the next few slides to answer the questions on the work sheet on the next slide. Make a Be careful spider how you diagram on spell these your words! theory Augustine information: The Augustinian Theodicy • Many people believe that evil and suffering in the world is proof that God does not exist. If God exists, and was all powerful (omnipotent), all loving (benevolent) and all knowing (omniscient), surely he wouldn’t let evil and suffering take place? • In response to this problem of evil, Saint Augustine of Hippo (a 4th century Christian) used the first story in the Bible, the story of Genesis, to explain that it is not God’s fault there is evil in the world.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Evil and the Probity of Theodicy from William Rowe's
    Liberty University Department of Philosophy The Problem of Evil and the Probity of Doing Theodicy from William Rowe’s Evidential Argument from Evil ------------------------------------------- A Thesis Presented to the Faculty of Philosophy Department of Liberty University In Partial Fulfilment Of the Requirement for the Degree Master of Arts in Philosophical Studies -------------------------------------------- By Olaoluwa Apata -------------------------------------------- Lynchburg, VA May 2016 Abstract In this research, we discussed the types of evil: moral and natural, which are cited by atheistic philosophers as evidence against the existence of God. The so-called evidence from evil has been used by the atheistic and other non-theistic scholars to raise hypothesis on evaluating the possibility or likelihood that an omnipotent, omniscient, and wholly good God exists in a world that is littered with evil. Moral evil is evil that arise from the misuse of free will by moral agents, while natural evils are natural disasters such as: earthquakes, famine, floods, hurricanes, tornadoes etc. We discussed moral evil and Plantinga’s free will defense. We also discussed the natural evil and how it poses threat to theism. The logical and the evidential arguments from evil are the forms of arguments developed from moral and natural evils. While many scholars have agreed that Plantinga’s free will defense adequately responds to the problem of logical evil, the same consensus does not necessarily apply to the evidential argument from evil. We also examined William Rowe’s evidential argument which he developed from cases of intense animal and human sufferings considered by him to be pointless or gratuitous with no known reasons or goods for which God should have allowed the visceral experience of such sufferings.
    [Show full text]
  • The Liberal Doctrine of Hell and Universalism: a Transcendental Approach
    1 The Liberal Doctrine of Hell and Universalism: A Transcendental Approach By Daniel L. Broadstock BA (Hons), B.Ed A thesis submitted in fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Philosophy University of Divinity 2017 2 Abstract In this thesis I have applied a Kantian methodology to present a new approach to the problem of Hell. I have engaged with two leading perspectives in this debate, the ‘liberal doctrine of Hell’ and the doctrine of Universalism, and pursued dialogue with leading theologians of each view; Jerry Walls and Jurgen Moltmann respectively. The liberal model of Hell is a modern attempt to revitalise the doctrine by recasting its nature and purpose. Rather than an instrument for the punishment of sin, the liberal model interprets Hell as God’s response to human freedom. This theory holds that God has constituted human beings with free volition of the will and desires a free relationship with them. As it is possible to resist this invitation, he has also created Hell as a place of eternal separation for those who reject him. While the invitation of grace is never withdrawn, some will remain there forever. Universalism is the view that all human beings will be saved. I have sketched a general outline of these views, illustrating them with reference to arguments proposed by key thinkers in their respective fields. I conclude that they constitute an antinomy; an a priori dilemma abstract from experience and therefore unresolvable by philosophical reasoning. I suggest that the problem of Hell can be resolved by employing a theological adaptation of Kant’s transcendental idealism: eternal separation and universal salvation can both be true, if understood as compatible manifestations of different levels of reality and perception.
    [Show full text]