Control Complexity of Schulze Voting

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Control Complexity of Schulze Voting Proceedings of the Twenty-Third International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence Control Complexity of Schulze Voting Curtis Menton1 and Preetjot Singh2 1Dept. of Comp. Sci., University of Rochester, Rochester, NY, USA 2EECS, Northwestern University, Evanston, IL, USA Abstract ther characterize the worst-case behavior of Schulze voting under control. We find that it possesses a good but not ex- Schulze voting is a recently introduced voting sys- ceptional number of control resistances, fewer than the best tem enjoying unusual popularity and a high degree known natural systems. Schulze voting currently is known of real-world use, with users including the Wiki- to posses the same control resistances as Copelandα with media foundation, several branches of the Pirate α 2 (0; 1), which was at one point the most resistant system Party, and MTV. It is a Condorcet voting system known that uses the standard linear vote model [Faliszewski that determines the winners of an election using in- et al., 2009b]. While it fails to stand among the most resistant formation about paths in a graph representation of systems, the popularity of the system increases the relevance the election. We resolve the complexity of many of these results, perhaps calling into question the use of the electoral control cases for Schulze voting. We find system in contexts where these control actions are of concern. that it falls short of the best known voting systems in terms of control resistance, demonstrating vul- 1.1 Preliminaries nerabilities of concern to some prospective users of the system. An election is a pair (C; V ) where C is a finite set of candi- dates and V is a finite collection of votes. The most common model is for a vote to be given as a strict linear ordering of 1 Introduction the candidates, though other models are sometimes used as Voting has a long history as a tool for collaborative deci- well. Most notably, approval voting uses binary vectors over sion making. It has classically been used for political and the candidates as votes. organizational elections, but it has become increasingly im- A voting system is a mapping from an election (C; V ) to a 0 portant through its use in artificial intelligence and multia- set C ⊆ C of winners. We do not require a voting system to gent systems. Some applications include recommender sys- select only a single winner: This would require us to build in tems [Ghosh et al., 1999; Pennock et al., 2000], consensus tiebreaking mechanisms while they are better left as separate mechanisms for planning [Ephrati and Rosenschein, 1991] procedures. We do not require a voting system even to always and search engine design [Lifantsev, 2000; Dwork et al., select any winners at all, as there are electoral contexts where 2001]. selecting no candidates is a reasonable outcome. For instance, A persistent worry with elections is that they may be ma- the voting system used to select entrants for the Baseball Hall nipulated, harming their integrity and often calling into ques- of Fame can select no players if none reach a certain threshold tion the authenticity of the results. The seminal work of Gib- of support. bard and Satterthwaite [Gibbard, 1973; Satterthwaite, 1975] (and the later extension of this result [Duggan and Schwartz, 1.2 Schulze Voting 2000]) showed that in fact no reasonable voting system is im- Schulze voting is a Condorcet voting system recently intro- mune to manipulation (i.e., strategic voting). Later, Bartholdi, duced by Marcus Schulze [Schulze, 2011]. It was designed Tovey, and Trick introduced computational complexity as a in part to effectively handle candidate cloning: In many vot- novel defense against this problem [Bartholdi et al., 1989].A ing systems, the inclusion of several similar candidates ends flood of research has subsequently investigated the complex- up diluting their support and lessening the influence of their ity of many voting systems under various manipulative action supporters. It has a somewhat more complex winner proce- problems. dure than other common voting systems, requiring the use of Here we study Schulze voting, a new and sophisticated vot- a graph best-path finding algorithm, but it is still solvable in ing system that has become fairly popular in recent years. We polynomial time, rendering Schulze a tractable voting system. investigate its complexity under control, a class of manipu- Schulze voting has garnered a high level of real-world use, lative action problems where the election chair changes the especially in the free software and free culture communities. structure of the election to affect the result. We build on ear- Users include several national branches of the Pirate Party, lier work by Parkes and Xia [Parkes and Xia, 2012] and fur- the Wikimedia foundation, many free-software projects such 286 as Ubuntu, Debian, Gentoo, and KDE, and even MTV. This 4 a level of real-world usage is unusual for a new, academically b proposed and studied voting system, but it makes Schulze 4 voting more compelling to analyze. 2 2 As a typical Condorcet system, the winners are determined by examining the pairwise contests between candidates. We 6 will thus introduce some useful functions and notation. The c d advantage function is a function on pairs of candidates where adv(a; b) is the number of voters in the given election that Figure 1: Election graph for the example Schulze election. prefer a to b (that is, rank a higher than b in their pref- erences). The net advantage function gives the net differ- ence in advantage for one candidate over another. We de- dates. Note that there are several Condorcet cycles and there fine the net advantage between a and b to be the following: is no clearly dominant candidate: Each of them loses to at netadv(a; b) = adv(a; b) − adv(b; a). least one other candidate, and each candidate has a path to It is easily possible to construct the net advantage function every other candidate. The following are the Schulze best given a collection of votes, but it is interesting to note that path scores. we can easily convert in the other direction as well. Given a b c d a net advantage function where either all the scores are even or all the scores are odd, we can construct an equivalent set a 4 4 4 of votes in time polynomial in the number of candidates and b 2 4 4 in the maximum magnitude of any score in the net advan- c 2 2 6 tage function. This method is due to McGarvey [McGarvey, d 2 2 2 1953]. We will use this method later to more easily construct a elections in the course of reductions, in order to avoid having The only winner of the election will be , as it has a to explicitly specify the votes. stronger path to every other candidate than those candidates have back to a. The winners in a Schulze election are determined as fol- lows. Generate the net advantage scores for the election, and 1.3 Election Manipulative Actions represent this data as a graph, with vertices for candidates and directed edges denoting net advantage scores. Deter- There are several classes of manipulative action problems mine the strongest paths in this graph between every pair of studied in computational social choice. The primary classes candidates by the following metric: The weight of a path is of these problems are manipulation, where a voter or voters the lowest weight edge in the path. This is the “bottleneck” strategically vote to affect the result of an election [Bartholdi metric. We can adapt the Floyd-Warshall dynamic program- et al., 1989], bribery, where an outside briber pays off voters ming algorithm to find the weight of such paths in polynomial to change their votes [Faliszewski et al., 2009a], and control, time [Schulze, 2011]. where an election organizer alters the structure of an election Once we have the best path weights, we build another to change the result [Bartholdi et al., 1992]. graph with the same vertices where there is a directed edge These problems are formalized as decision problems as is from a to b if the best path from a to b is stronger than the standard in computer science and we study their complexity best path from b to a. The winners of the election are the can- in various voting systems. There is some standard terminol- didates with no in-edges in this final graph. That is, they are ogy about the behavior of voting systems under manipulative the candidates that are not beaten by any other candidate in actions. A voting system is immune to a manipulative action relative best-path strength. if the action can never change the result of an election in the Note that a Condorcet winner, in the election graph, will voting system, and the system is susceptible otherwise. If a have positive weight edges to every other candidate, and so voting system is susceptible to some action and the decision they will clearly have the better paths to every other candidate problem is in P, then it is vulnerable to it, and the system and be the only winner of the election. is constructively vulnerable if additionally the corresponding search problem is in P. If the decision problem is NP-hard, the Example Election voting system is resistant to the action. The original versions Consider a Schulze election over candidates fa; b; c; dg with of these problems are the constructive cases, where the goal the following table expressing the net advantage function. is to make a particular candidate win, as opposed to destruc- tive cases, where the goal is to prevent a particular candidate a b c d from winning.
Recommended publications
  • Influences in Voting and Growing Networks
    UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Influences in Voting and Growing Networks Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/0fk1x7zx Author Racz, Miklos Zoltan Publication Date 2015 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Influences in Voting and Growing Networks by Mikl´osZolt´anR´acz A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Statistics in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Elchanan Mossel, Chair Professor James W. Pitman Professor Allan M. Sly Professor David S. Ahn Spring 2015 Influences in Voting and Growing Networks Copyright 2015 by Mikl´osZolt´anR´acz 1 Abstract Influences in Voting and Growing Networks by Mikl´osZolt´anR´acz Doctor of Philosophy in Statistics University of California, Berkeley Professor Elchanan Mossel, Chair This thesis studies problems in applied probability using combinatorial techniques. The first part of the thesis focuses on voting, and studies the average-case behavior of voting systems with respect to manipulation of their outcome by voters. Many results in the field of voting are negative; in particular, Gibbard and Satterthwaite showed that no reasonable voting system can be strategyproof (a.k.a. nonmanipulable). We prove a quantitative version of this result, showing that the probability of manipulation is nonnegligible, unless the voting system is close to being a dictatorship. We also study manipulation by a coalition of voters, and show that the transition from being powerless to having absolute power is smooth. These results suggest that manipulation is easy on average for reasonable voting systems, and thus computational complexity cannot hide manipulations completely.
    [Show full text]
  • Stable Voting
    Stable Voting Wesley H. Hollidayy and Eric Pacuitz y University of California, Berkeley ([email protected]) z University of Maryland ([email protected]) September 12, 2021 Abstract In this paper, we propose a new single-winner voting system using ranked ballots: Stable Voting. The motivating principle of Stable Voting is that if a candidate A would win without another candidate B in the election, and A beats B in a head-to-head majority comparison, then A should still win in the election with B included (unless there is another candidate A0 who has the same kind of claim to winning, in which case a tiebreaker may choose between A and A0). We call this principle Stability for Winners (with Tiebreaking). Stable Voting satisfies this principle while also having a remarkable ability to avoid tied outcomes in elections even with small numbers of voters. 1 Introduction Voting reform efforts in the United States have achieved significant recent successes in replacing Plurality Voting with Instant Runoff Voting (IRV) for major political elections, including the 2018 San Francisco Mayoral Election and the 2021 New York City Mayoral Election. It is striking, by contrast, that Condorcet voting methods are not currently used in any political elections.1 Condorcet methods use the same ranked ballots as IRV but replace the counting of first-place votes with head- to-head comparisons of candidates: do more voters prefer candidate A to candidate B or prefer B to A? If there is a candidate A who beats every other candidate in such a head-to-head majority comparison, this so-called Condorcet winner wins the election.
    [Show full text]
  • Single-Winner Voting Method Comparison Chart
    Single-winner Voting Method Comparison Chart This chart compares the most widely discussed voting methods for electing a single winner (and thus does not deal with multi-seat or proportional representation methods). There are countless possible evaluation criteria. The Criteria at the top of the list are those we believe are most important to U.S. voters. Plurality Two- Instant Approval4 Range5 Condorcet Borda (FPTP)1 Round Runoff methods6 Count7 Runoff2 (IRV)3 resistance to low9 medium high11 medium12 medium high14 low15 spoilers8 10 13 later-no-harm yes17 yes18 yes19 no20 no21 no22 no23 criterion16 resistance to low25 high26 high27 low28 low29 high30 low31 strategic voting24 majority-favorite yes33 yes34 yes35 no36 no37 yes38 no39 criterion32 mutual-majority no41 no42 yes43 no44 no45 yes/no 46 no47 criterion40 prospects for high49 high50 high51 medium52 low53 low54 low55 U.S. adoption48 Condorcet-loser no57 yes58 yes59 no60 no61 yes/no 62 yes63 criterion56 Condorcet- no65 no66 no67 no68 no69 yes70 no71 winner criterion64 independence of no73 no74 yes75 yes/no 76 yes/no 77 yes/no 78 no79 clones criterion72 81 82 83 84 85 86 87 monotonicity yes no no yes yes yes/no yes criterion80 prepared by FairVote: The Center for voting and Democracy (April 2009). References Austen-Smith, David, and Jeffrey Banks (1991). “Monotonicity in Electoral Systems”. American Political Science Review, Vol. 85, No. 2 (June): 531-537. Brewer, Albert P. (1993). “First- and Secon-Choice Votes in Alabama”. The Alabama Review, A Quarterly Review of Alabama History, Vol. ?? (April): ?? - ?? Burgin, Maggie (1931). The Direct Primary System in Alabama.
    [Show full text]
  • A Brief Introductory T T I L C T Ti L Tutorial on Computational Social Choice
    A Brief Introductory TtTutori ilal on Compu ttitationa l Social Choice Vincent Conitzer Outline • 1. Introduction to votinggy theory • 2. Hard-to-compute rules • 3. Using computational hardness to prevent manipulation and other undesirable behavior in elections • 4. Selected topics (time permitting) Introduction to voting theory Voting over alternatives voting rule > > (mechanism) determines winner based on votes > > • Can vote over other things too – Where to ggg,jp,o for dinner tonight, other joint plans, … Voting (rank aggregation) • Set of m candidates (aka. alternatives, outcomes) •n voters; each voter ranks all the candidates – E.g., for set of candidates {a, b, c, d}, one possible vote is b > a > d > c – Submitted ranking is called a vote • AvotingA voting rule takes as input a vector of votes (submitted by the voters), and as output produces either: – the winning candidate, or – an aggregate ranking of all candidates • Can vote over just about anything – pppolitical representatives, award nominees, where to go for dinner tonight, joint plans, allocations of tasks/resources, … – Also can consider other applications: e.g., aggregating search engines’ rankinggggs into a single ranking Example voting rules • Scoring rules are defined by a vector (a1, a2, …, am); being ranked ith in a vote gives the candidate ai points – Plurality is defined by (1, 0, 0, …, 0) (winner is candidate that is ranked first most often) – Veto (or anti-plurality) is defined by (1, 1, …, 1, 0) (winner is candidate that is ranked last the least often) – Borda is defined by (m-1, m-2, …, 0) • Plurality with (2-candidate) runoff: top two candidates in terms of plurality score proceed to runoff; whichever is ranked higher than the other by more voters, wins • Single Transferable Vote (STV, aka.
    [Show full text]
  • Generalized Scoring Rules: a Framework That Reconciles Borda and Condorcet
    Generalized Scoring Rules: A Framework That Reconciles Borda and Condorcet Lirong Xia Harvard University Generalized scoring rules [Xia and Conitzer 08] are a relatively new class of social choice mech- anisms. In this paper, we survey developments in generalized scoring rules, showing that they provide a fruitful framework to obtain general results, and also reconcile the Borda approach and Condorcet approach via a new social choice axiom. We comment on some high-level ideas behind GSRs and their connection to Machine Learning, and point out some ongoing work and future directions. Categories and Subject Descriptors: J.4 [Computer Applications]: Social and Behavioral Sci- ences|Economics; I.2.11 [Distributed Artificial Intelligence]: Multiagent Systems General Terms: Algorithms, Economics, Theory Additional Key Words and Phrases: Computational social choice, generalized scoring rules 1. INTRODUCTION Social choice theory focuses on developing principles and methods for representation and aggregation of individual ordinal preferences. Perhaps the most well-known application of social choice theory is political elections. Over centuries, many social choice mechanisms have been proposed and analyzed in the context of elections, where each agent (voter) uses a linear order over the alternatives (candidates) to represent her preferences (her vote). For historical reasons, we will use voting rules to denote social choice mechanisms, though we need to keep in mind that the application is not limited to political elections.1 Most existing voting rules fall into one of the following two categories.2 Positional scoring rules: Each alternative gets some points from each agent according to its position in the agent's vote. The alternative with the highest total points wins.
    [Show full text]
  • Approval-Based Elections and Distortion of Voting Rules
    Proceedings of the Twenty-Eighth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI-19) Approval-Based Elections and Distortion of Voting Rules Grzegorz Pierczynski , Piotr Skowron University of Warsaw, Warsaw, Poland [email protected], [email protected] Abstract voters and the candidates are represented by points in a metric space M called the issue space. The optimal candidate is the We consider elections where both voters and can- one that minimizes the sum of the distances to all the voters. didates can be associated with points in a metric However, the election rules do not have access to the met- space and voters prefer candidates that are closer to ric space M itself but they only see the ranking-based profile those that are farther away. It is often assumed that induced by M: in this profile the voters rank the candidates the optimal candidate is the one that minimizes the by their distance to themselves, preferring the ones that are total distance to the voters. Yet, the voting rules of- closer to those that are farther. Since the rules do not have ten do not have access to the metric space M and full information about the metric space they cannot always only see preference rankings induced by M. Con- find optimal candidates. The distortion quantifies the worst- sequently, they often are incapable of selecting the case loss of the utility being effect of having only access to optimal candidate. The distortion of a voting rule rankings. Formally, the distortion of a voting rule is the max- measures the worst-case loss of the quality being imum, over all metric spaces, of the following ratio: the sum the result of having access only to preference rank- of the distances between the elected candidate and the vot- ings.
    [Show full text]
  • Ranked-Choice Voting from a Partisan Perspective
    Ranked-Choice Voting From a Partisan Perspective Jack Santucci December 21, 2020 Revised December 22, 2020 Abstract Ranked-choice voting (RCV) has come to mean a range of electoral systems. Broadly, they can facilitate (a) majority winners in single-seat districts, (b) majority rule with minority representation in multi-seat districts, or (c) majority sweeps in multi-seat districts. Such systems can be combined with other rules that encourage/discourage slate voting. This paper describes five major versions used in U.S. public elections: Al- ternative Vote (AV), single transferable vote (STV), block-preferential voting (BPV), the bottoms-up system, and AV with numbered posts. It then considers each from the perspective of a `political operative.' Simple models of voting (one with two parties, another with three) draw attention to real-world strategic issues: effects on minority representation, importance of party cues, and reasons for the political operative to care about how voters rank choices. Unsurprisingly, different rules produce different outcomes with the same votes. Specific problems from the operative's perspective are: majority reversal, serving two masters, and undisciplined third-party voters (e.g., `pure' independents). Some of these stem from well-known phenomena, e.g., ballot exhaus- tion/ranking truncation and inter-coalition \vote leakage." The paper also alludes to vote-management tactics, i.e., rationing nominations and ensuring even distributions of first-choice votes. Illustrative examples come from American history and comparative politics. (209 words.) Keywords: Alternative Vote, ballot exhaustion, block-preferential voting, bottoms- up system, exhaustive-preferential system, instant runoff voting, ranked-choice voting, sequential ranked-choice voting, single transferable vote, strategic coordination (10 keywords).
    [Show full text]
  • Präferenzaggregation Durch Wählen: Algorithmik Und Komplexität
    Pr¨aferenzaggregationdurch W¨ahlen: Algorithmik und Komplexit¨at Folien zur Vorlesung Wintersemester 2017/2018 Dozent: Prof. Dr. J. Rothe J. Rothe (HHU D¨usseldorf) Pr¨aferenzaggregation durch W¨ahlen 1 / 57 Preliminary Remarks Websites Websites Vorlesungswebsite: http:==ccc:cs:uni-duesseldorf:de=~rothe=wahlen Anmeldung im LSF J. Rothe (HHU D¨usseldorf) Pr¨aferenzaggregation durch W¨ahlen 2 / 57 Preliminary Remarks Literature Literature J. Rothe (Herausgeber): Economics and Computation: An Introduction to Algorithmic Game Theory, Computational Social Choice, and Fair Division. Springer-Verlag, 2015 with a preface by Matt O. Jackson und Yoav Shoham (Stanford) Buchblock 155 x 235 mm Abstand 6 mm Springer Texts in Business and Economics Rothe Springer Texts in Business and Economics Jörg Rothe Editor Economics and Computation Ed. An Introduction to Algorithmic Game Theory, Computational Social Choice, and Fair Division J. Rothe D. Baumeister C. Lindner I. Rothe This textbook connects three vibrant areas at the interface between economics and computer science: algorithmic game theory, computational social choice, and fair divi- sion. It thus offers an interdisciplinary treatment of collective decision making from an economic and computational perspective. Part I introduces to algorithmic game theory, focusing on both noncooperative and cooperative game theory. Part II introduces to Jörg Rothe Einführung in computational social choice, focusing on both preference aggregation (voting) and judgment aggregation. Part III introduces to fair division, focusing on the division of Editor Computational Social Choice both a single divisible resource ("cake-cutting") and multiple indivisible and unshare- able resources ("multiagent resource allocation"). In all these parts, much weight is Individuelle Strategien und kollektive given to the algorithmic and complexity-theoretic aspects of problems arising in these areas, and the interconnections between the three parts are of central interest.
    [Show full text]
  • Computational Perspectives on Democracy
    Computational Perspectives on Democracy Anson Kahng CMU-CS-21-126 August 2021 Computer Science Department School of Computer Science Carnegie Mellon University Pittsburgh, PA 15213 Thesis Committee: Ariel Procaccia (Chair) Chinmay Kulkarni Nihar Shah Vincent Conitzer (Duke University) David Pennock (Rutgers University) Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Copyright c 2021 Anson Kahng This research was sponsored by the National Science Foundation under grant numbers IIS-1350598, CCF- 1525932, and IIS-1714140, the Department of Defense under grant number W911NF1320045, the Office of Naval Research under grant number N000141712428, and the JP Morgan Research grant. The views and conclusions contained in this document are those of the author and should not be interpreted as representing the official policies, either expressed or implied, of any sponsoring institution, the U.S. government or any other entity. Keywords: Computational Social Choice, Theoretical Computer Science, Artificial Intelligence For Grandpa and Harabeoji. iv Abstract Democracy is a natural approach to large-scale decision-making that allows people affected by a potential decision to provide input about the outcome. However, modern implementations of democracy are based on outdated infor- mation technology and must adapt to the changing technological landscape. This thesis explores the relationship between computer science and democracy, which is, crucially, a two-way street—just as principles from computer science can be used to analyze and design democratic paradigms, ideas from democracy can be used to solve hard problems in computer science. Question 1: What can computer science do for democracy? To explore this first question, we examine the theoretical foundations of three democratic paradigms: liquid democracy, participatory budgeting, and multiwinner elections.
    [Show full text]
  • Group Decision Making with Partial Preferences
    Group Decision Making with Partial Preferences by Tyler Lu A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Department of Computer Science University of Toronto c Copyright 2015 by Tyler Lu Abstract Group Decision Making with Partial Preferences Tyler Lu Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Department of Computer Science University of Toronto 2015 Group decision making is of fundamental importance in all aspects of a modern society. Many commonly studied decision procedures require that agents provide full preference information. This requirement imposes significant cognitive and time burdens on agents, increases communication overhead, and infringes agent privacy. As a result, specifying full preferences is one of the contributing factors for the limited real-world adoption of some commonly studied voting rules. In this dissertation, we introduce a framework consisting of new concepts, algorithms, and theoretical results to provide a sound foundation on which we can address these problems by being able to make group decisions with only partial preference information. In particular, we focus on single and multi-winner voting. We introduce minimax regret (MMR), a group decision-criterion for partial preferences, which quantifies the loss in social welfare of chosen alternative(s) compared to the unknown, but true winning alternative(s). We develop polynomial-time algorithms for the computation of MMR for a number of common of voting rules, and prove intractability results for other rules. We address preference elicitation, the second part of our framework, which concerns the extraction of only the relevant agent preferences that reduce MMR. We develop a few elicitation strategies, based on common ideas, for different voting rules and query types.
    [Show full text]
  • Measuring Violations of Positive Involvement in Voting*
    Measuring Violations of Positive Involvement in Voting* Wesley H. Holliday Eric Pacuit University of California, Berkeley University of Maryland [email protected] [email protected] In the context of computational social choice, we study voting methods that assign a set of winners to each profile of voter preferences. A voting method satisfies the property of positive involvement (PI) if for any election in which a candidate x would be among the winners, adding another voter to the election who ranks x first does not cause x to lose. Surprisingly, a number of standard voting methods violate this natural property. In this paper, we investigate different ways of measuring the extent to which a voting method violates PI, using computer simulations. We consider the probability (under different probability models for preferences) of PI violations in randomly drawn profiles vs. profile- coalition pairs (involving coalitions of different sizes). We argue that in order to choose between a voting method that satisfies PI and one that does not, we should consider the probability of PI violation conditional on the voting methods choosing different winners. We should also relativize the probability of PI violation to what we call voter potency, the probability that a voter causes a candidate to lose. Although absolute frequencies of PI violations may be low, after this conditioning and relativization, we see that under certain voting methods that violate PI, much of a voter’s potency is turned against them—in particular, against their desire to see their favorite candidate elected. 1 Introduction Voting provides a mechanism for resolving conflicts between the preferences of multiple agents in order to arrive at a group choice.
    [Show full text]
  • Voting with Rank Dependent Scoring Rules
    Voting with Rank Dependent Scoring Rules Judy Goldsmith, Jer´ omeˆ Lang, Nicholas Mattei, and Patrice Perny Abstract Positional scoring rules in voting compute the score of an alternative by summing the scores for the alternative induced by every vote. This summation principle ensures that all votes con- tribute equally to the score of an alternative. We relax this assumption and, instead, aggregate scores by taking into account the rank of a score in the ordered list of scores obtained from the votes. This defines a new family of voting rules, rank-dependent scoring rules (RDSRs), based on ordered weighted average (OWA) operators, which include all scoring rules, and many oth- ers, most of which of new. We study some properties of these rules, and show, empirically, that certain RDSRs are less manipulable than Borda voting, across a variety of statistical cultures and on real world data from skating competitions. 1 Introduction Voting rules aim at aggregating the ordinal preferences of a set of individuals in order to produce a commonly chosen alternative. Many voting rules are defined in the following way: given a vot- ing profile P, a collection of votes, where a vote is a linear ranking over alternatives, each vote contributes to the score of an alternative. The global score of the alternative is then computed by summing up all these contributed (“local”) scores, and finally, the alternative(s) with the highest score win(s). The most common subclass of these scoring rules is that of positional scoring rules: the local score of x with respect to vote v depends only on the rank of x in v, and the global score of x is the sum, over all votes, of its local scores.
    [Show full text]