Implied Constitutional Rights and the Growth of Judicial Activism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Implied Constitutional Rights and the Growth of Judicial Activism University of Calgary PRISM: University of Calgary's Digital Repository Graduate Studies Legacy Theses 1997 Implied constitutional rights and the growth of judicial activism Bottomley, Samuel A. Bottomley, S. A. (1997). Implied constitutional rights and the growth of judicial activism (Unpublished master's thesis). University of Calgary, Calgary, AB. doi:10.11575/PRISM/22552 http://hdl.handle.net/1880/26943 master thesis University of Calgary graduate students retain copyright ownership and moral rights for their thesis. You may use this material in any way that is permitted by the Copyright Act or through licensing that has been assigned to the document. For uses that are not allowable under copyright legislation or licensing, you are required to seek permission. Downloaded from PRISM: https://prism.ucalgary.ca THE UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY Implied Constitutional Rights and the Growth of Judicial Activism by Samuel A Bottomley A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS DEPARTMENT OF POLITICAL SCIENCE CALGARY, ALBERTA AUGUST, 1997 Q Samuel A. Bottomley 1997 National Library Bibliothéque nationale 1*1 of Canada du Canada Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographie Services services bibliographiques 395 Wellington Street 395. rue Wellington Onawa ON K1A ON4 ûttawa ON KI A ON4 -da Canada The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive licence allowing the exclusive permettant à la National Library of Canada to Bibliothèque nationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distribute or sell reproduire, prêter, distribuer ou copies of this thesis in microfonn, vendre des copies de cette thèse sous paper or electronic formats. la forme de microfichelfilm, de reproduction sur papier ou sur format électronique. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conserve la propriété du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protège cette thèse. thesis nor substantial extracts fiom it Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels may be printed or othenvise de celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permission. autorisation. ABSTRACT What accounts for the giobal spread of judiciai activism? According to a legalist/institutional exphnation, judicial activism is mandated by entrenched constitutionai documents, and the spread of activism is thus explained by the spread of this kind of constitutionalism. A rival explanation, based on legal realism, holds that judicial activism is rnainly a fbnction of judicial inclination or judiciai culture, not constitutional documents. This study is grounded in the second perspective. In other words, it denies the legaiist explanation for judicial activism, at least in its more simplistic versions. Does it foilow fiom the obvious fact of judiçial discretion, howwer, that inclination and culture are the sole explanatory variables? Are the uisights of neoinstitutionalism of no relevance to the understanding of judiciai behaviour? Or, despite ttie great weight of judicial culture, does institutional context continue to exercise a si@cant infIuence? In short, in the area ofjudicial behaviour, 'do institutions matter'? The phenornenon of implied biiis of rights provides an interesting context in which to explore this question. Ifjudiciai inclination and culture is everything, one wouId expect judges to invent the grounds for constitutiondiy based activism where they do not explicitly exist. That such inventions exist - in the fonn of implied bill of rights - is itself eloquent testimony to the explanatory power of judicid incIination. But this knot the whole story. Having established an implied bill of rights, do judges use it as cornprehensively and aggressively as they would an explicitly entrenched constitutional document. If not, then claims that constitutional entrenchment explains judicid activism, while ofien used by judges in exaggerated ways, retain some force. 1 am indebted to many people for their help throughout the completion of this thesis. First, 1 wodd iike to thank the politicaI science office staff at the University of Calgary: Carolyn Andres, Judi Poweli, Valerie Snowdon, and espeçiaiiy Eiia Wensel were dl very helpfid and always full of encouragement. Further appreciation goes out to Drs. Archer, Gibbins, Harasymiw and Peri, who saw me through the coursework component of this degree. Thanks also to Dr. Morton for his insight and for aiiowing me to borrow numerous books and articles fiom his personal coiiection. I mus? also express my gratitude to a number of my feUow graduate students - Vince Lauerman, Butch Kamena, Nancy Bleses, Mebs Kanji, KeWi Muxlow, David Greener, Fred Wd, and especially Ian Brodie - t hanks for everything . Most of alI, 1 wodd like to thank Dr. Rainer Knopff 1 can say with cornplete sincerity that 1 codd not have had a better supervisor. This thesis benefited greatiy fiom his wisdom, guidance and patience. It was a pleasure working with hirn. To my parents, for al1 thezr encouragement. TABLE OF CONTENTS .. Approval Page........................................................................................................... .LI ..* Abstract .................................................................................................................... .III Achowiedgment ....................................................................................................... iv . - Dedication................................................................................................................. .v Table of Contents.................................................................................................... ..vi CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION.............................................................................. .1 CHAPTER 2: THE LEGALISTIINSTITUTIONAL EXPLANATION.................... .ll Explainhg Charter Activism: An Example of Legalist Justification............... -12 The U.S. Example........................................................................................ -16 The Swedish Example.................................................................................. .20 The Canadian Example................................................................................. -23 Judiciai Inclination or Institutionai Context?................................................. .27 CHAPTER 3: THE CANADIAN IMPLIED BILL OF RIGHTS.............................. .29 The Implied Bill of Rights in the Pre-war Era - 17ie Alberta Press Case.. ... .3O The Implied Bill of Rights and Judicial Activism in the 1950s........................ 38 Rex W. Hess. ...................................................................................... -39 The Quebec Cases.. .......................................................................... .4 1 Szmur v. Quebec................................................................. .42 Switnnan v. Elbling.............................................................. -46 A Period of Restra.int 1960-1982 ................................................................... 5( Oil Chernicd and Atmzc Workers v . Imperial Ozl ............................. 51 Dupond v. Mmesi.. ......................................................................... 53 Judiciai Inclination or Institutional Context?.................................................. 58 CHAPTER 4: THE ISR4ELI DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE.................. 61 A Bnef Period of Judiciai Restraint ............................................................... 65 A Period of Experimentation......................................................................... 68 Kol Ha 'am....................................................................................... -69 Ywdor............................................................................................... 74 The Recent Perioà of Judicial Activisrn......................................................... 77 Judicial Inclination or Institutional Context?................................................. -81 CHAPTER 5: WLYING RIGHTS IN THE FRENCH CONSTITUTION........... -84 The Constitutionai Council........................................................................... 85 Constitutionalking the PreambIe: The Decision of July 16, 197 1 ................... 88 Fundamental Principles Recognized by the Laws of the Republic .................. 93 The Decision of Juiy 16, 197 1 ........................................................... -93 The Decision of January 12, 1977 ...................................................... 95 The Decision of December 29, 1983 ..................................................96 The Decision of January 19-20, 198 1 ................................................. 98 The Dedaration of the Rights of Man .......................................................... 101 The Decision of December 1 8, 1973 ................................................ 101 The Decision of July 23. 1975 ........................................................... 102 The Nationaikations Case ................................................................. 102 The Collectivist Provisions of the 1946 Preamble .......................................... lû4 Judicial Inclination or Institutional Context?................................................. 107 CHAPTER 6: THE AUSTR4LIAN WLIED BILL OF RIGHTS ........................ 110 Implications in the Constitution Prior to The Free Speech Cases .................. 111 The Free Speech Cases
Recommended publications
  • Building a Law of Human Rights: Roncarelli V. Duplessis in Canadian Constitutional Culture Eric M
    Document generated on 09/26/2021 12:09 p.m. McGill Law Journal Revue de droit de McGill Building a Law of Human Rights: Roncarelli v. Duplessis in Canadian Constitutional Culture Eric M. Adams The Legacy of Roncarelli v. Duplessis, 1959-2009 Article abstract L’héritage de l’affaire Roncarelli c. Duplessis, 1959-2009 This article reveals how audiences, especially in anglophone Canada, initially Volume 55, Number 3, September 2010 received and interpreted Roncarelli v. Duplessis as a case, above all, about human rights. Ignoring the judgment’s myriad complexities, commentators URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1000619ar eagerly situated the case within the Supreme Court of Canada’s “implied bill of DOI: https://doi.org/10.7202/1000619ar rights” jurisprudence then taking shape. Part of the reason for the emphasis on Roncarelli’s rights can be traced to the manner in which Frank Scott and Louis Stein argued the case, and the language of rights employed by Justice Ivan See table of contents Rand’s iconic judgment. But Roncarelli’s meaning also took shape in press accounts and editorials, radio broadcasts, case comments, and law school lectures. Exploring these Publisher(s) often-neglected sources, this article exposes the role of constitutional culture in McGill Law Journal / Revue de droit de McGill creating jurisprudential meaning. In turn, it also calls for greater recognition of the pre-Charter Supreme Court of Canada in contributing to Canada’s ISSN intellectual history of rights. 0024-9041 (print) 1920-6356 (digital) Explore this journal Cite this article Adams, E. M. (2010). Building a Law of Human Rights: Roncarelli v.
    [Show full text]
  • Romance, Realism, and the Legitimacy of Implied Rights Grant Huscroft
    ROMANCE, REALISM, AND THE LEGITIMACY OF IMPLIED RIGHTS GRANT HUSCROFT* Passage of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms in 1982 empowered Canadian judges not only to determine whether legislation infringed constitutionally protected rights, but also to declare legislation to be of no force or effect – to ‘strike it down’ – if they concluded that the infringement was not justified. This was a massive transfer of power from the elected branch of government to the judiciary and heady stuff for Canadian jurists. Prior to the Charter Canadian judges had no formal constitutional role in the protection of rights. The Canadian Bill of Rights, a statutory bill of rights that includes most of the rights enumerated in the Charter, had been in place since 1960, but it came to little despite its requirement that federal legislation should be rights-consistent.1 Indeed, the Canadian Bill of Rights is widely assumed to have failed because of judicial indifference to it, and the Chief Justice of the Supreme Court of Canada, Brian Dickson, was keen to ensure that this did not happen to the Charter. Dickson equated the success of the Charter with an activist role for the courts,2 and under his leadership the Court promoted and encouraged Charter litigation from the outset, easing standing rules and welcoming interventions by interested parties, among other things. Lawyers took their cue and a spate of Charter challenges to legislation was the result. The Court embraced its new lawmaking role under the Charter, making clear that the Charter was a break from the past and that its provisions would be interpreted generously and progressively.3 The impact of judicial review under the Charter is impossible to deny.
    [Show full text]
  • The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms
    Public Law II AK/POLS 3136 1 Agenda • Defining Civil Liberties • A Brief History of Civil Liberties in Canada • Implied Bill of Rights • Canadian Bill of Rights • Universal Declaration of Human Rights (handout) 1 Civil Liberties • Freedoms that protect the individual from the government. • Civil liberties set limits for government so that it cannot abuse its power. • The protection of civil liberties is a key feature of democratic states, as distinct from authoritarian states. • The Constitution of Canada includes the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms 3 Brief History of Civil Liberties in Canada 4 Brief History • No Bill of Rights ?? • Implied Bill of Rights • Bill of Rights • Charter of Rights & Freedoms 5 • In 1867, the British North American colonies after confederation did not include a bill of rights in their constitution. • English Common Law inherited by Canada included rules that are protective of civil liberties but does not provide any guarantee for their continued recognition. 6 Implications • In the absence of a bill of rights, when a law abridging a civil liberty is challenged, the issue is that of jurisdiction, not whether the injustice should be prohibited completely. • In other words, if the courts were faced with a law passed by a province that placed restrictions on civil liberties, the responsibility of the court was not to state whether or not the law violated a civil liberty or freedom but if the law fell under the province's jurisdiction under the constitution. 7 Implications • In other words, if the courts were faced with a law passed by a province that placed restrictions on civil liberties, the responsibility of the court was not to state whether or not the law violated a civil liberty or freedom but if the law fell under the province's jurisdiction under the constitution.
    [Show full text]
  • The Central Fallacy of Canadian Constitutional Law
    The Central Fallacy of Canadian Constitutional Law J. Noel Lyon* Legal theory is important because it shapes the questions we frame about the law and the way we respond to those questions in concrete cases. Constitutional theory is especially important because it determines the way we perceive the functions and relationships of the various institutions of government and hence the quality of our system of representative government under law. The purpose of this article is to consider how well Canadian constitutional theory reflects the law of the Canadian Constitution, and the conclusion offered will be that we claim the theoretical simplicity of the English doctrine of parliamentary supremacy by largely ignoring the written character of our basic constitutional law. The thesis is not that parliamentary supremacy is not a central principle of Canadian constitutional law, but rather that in its application to the Canadian system the doctrine must be qualified in the face of a limited legal separation of powers imposed by the British North America Act, 1867.1 The doctrine of parliamentary supremacy leads to the twin pro- positions that Parliament cannot bind its successors and that an Act of Parliament, duly passed, cannot be impeached in a court of law. We shall be concerned only with the second of these concepts, and with the extent to which the separation of powers between all three branches of government - the Legislature, Executive and Judiciary - is a matter of law for enforcement by the courts. English lawyers can assert with confidence that from the point of view of legal theory, the supremacy of Parliament is absolute and unqualified.
    [Show full text]
  • The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: Dawn of a New Era?
    THE CANADIAN CHARTER OF RIGHTS AND FREEDOMS: DAWN OF A NEW ERA? Chief Justice Brian Dickson (Retired)1 I am deeply honoured to have been asked to give this year's Merv Leitch Q.C. Memorial Lecture. It gives me particular pleasure to be associated with a lecture series that honours the life of a great Canadian who rose from humble beginnings to pursue a distinguished career of public service and in the law. Merv Leitch was born in Creelman, Saskatchewan in 1926. He grew up through the worst of the depression years, watching his family struggle to keep their farm intact. Eventually, his family moved to Alberta. Merv lived in Alderson and then Redcliff before joining the Navy in 1943 at the ripe old age of seventeen! Upon discharge, he found his way to law school at the University of Alberta, graduating with the gold medal. From 1952 to 1971 Merv practised law with Macleod Dixon, the firm to which he would return in 1982 when he left public life. But of course he is best known to many of us as a man who held a number of key cabinet positions in the Lougheed government: first as Attorney General, later as Treasurer responsible for the Heritage Fund and finally as Minister of Energy. Merv Leitch's accomplishments were truly remarkable and I am pleased to be with you to pay tribute to him this evening. Those who knew or worked with Merv Leitch are well aware that he had an abiding fascination for constitutional law. Indeed, it was his express wish that the Merv Leitch 1 I would like to acknowledge the research assistance of Robert Yalden, (Faculty of Law, McGill University) in the preparation of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Parliamentary Sovereignty Rests with the Courts:” the Constitutional Foundations of J
    Title Page “Parliamentary sovereignty rests with the courts:” The Constitutional Foundations of J. G. Diefenbaker’s Canadian Bill of Rights Jordan Birenbaum Thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the PhD degree in History Department of History Faculty of Arts University of Ottawa © Jordan Birenbaum, Ottawa, Canada, 2012 Abstract The 1980s witnessed a judicial “rights revolution” in Canada characterized by the Supreme Court of Canada striking down both federal and provincial legislation which violated the rights guaranteed by the 1982 Charter of Rights. The lack of a similar judicial “rights revolution” in the wake of the 1960 Canadian Bill of Rights has largely been attributed to the structural difference between the two instruments with the latter – as a “mere” statute of the federal parliament – providing little more than a canon of construction and (unlike the Charter) not empowering the courts to engage in judicial review of legislation. Yet this view contrasts starkly with how the Bill was portrayed by the Diefenbaker government, which argued that it provided for judicial review and would “prevail” over other federal legislation. Many modern scholars have dismissed the idea that the Bill could prevail over other federal statutes as being incompatible with the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty. That is, a bill of rights could only prevail over legislation if incorporated into the British North America Act. As such, they argue that the Diefenbaker government could not have intended the Bill of Rights to operate as anything more than a canon of construction. However, such a view ignores the turbulence in constitutional thinking on parliamentary sovereignty in the 1930s through 1960s provoked by the Statute of Westminster.
    [Show full text]
  • Meech Lake to the Contrary Notwithstanding (Part II)
    Osgoode Hall Law Journal Volume 29 Issue 3 Volume 29, Number 3 (Fall 1991) Article 3 7-1-1991 ...Meech Lake to the Contrary Notwithstanding (Part II) Roderick A. Macdonald Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/ohlj Part of the Constitutional Law Commons Article This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Citation Information Macdonald, Roderick A.. "...Meech Lake to the Contrary Notwithstanding (Part II)." Osgoode Hall Law Journal 29.3 (1991) : 483-571. https://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/ohlj/vol29/iss3/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Osgoode Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Osgoode Hall Law Journal by an authorized editor of Osgoode Digital Commons. ...Meech Lake to the Contrary Notwithstanding (Part II) Abstract In this essay, which has been published in two parts, the author argues that the Meech Lake Accord was more than a hastily cobbled together political deal between the Prime Minister and ten provincial premiers. Despite the unattractive process by which the Meech Lake Accord was struck, and especially defended, despite the disingenuous character of the arguments most often advanced for its adoption, and despite its close connection with other aspects of the federal government's political agenda which many Canadians found suspicious, the Meech Lake Accord did respond to an important issue in post- patriation constitutionalism. A review of Canadian constitutional history, the evolution of French and English linguistic minorities in Canada, and the complementary motifs of French-Canadian and English- Canadian survivance leads the author to conclude that the forces which generated the Meech Lake Accord have been perennial features of "British North American" political life since 1759.
    [Show full text]
  • Underlying Constitutional Principles
    UnderLying constitUtionaL principLes: the Legacy of JUstice rand David J. Mullan* So is it with freedom of speech. The Confederation Act recites the desire of the three provinces to be federally united into one Dominion “with a constitution similar in principle to that of the United Kingdom.” Under that constitution, government is by parliamentary institutions, including popular assemblies elected by the people at large in both provinces and Dominion; 2010 CanLIIDocs 230 government resting ultimately on public opinion reached by discussion and the interplay of ideas. If that discussion is placed under license, its basic condition is destroyed; the government, as licensor, becomes disjoined from the citizenry. The only security is steadily advancing enlightenment, for which the widest range of controversy is the sine qua non. Justice Rand in Saumur v. City of Quebec.1 INTRODUCTION Justice Ivan Cleveland Rand died in 1969, the year before I arrived in Canada from New Zealand as a graduate student. While his voice was influential among those who persuaded me to come to this country to undertake further studies, Justice Rand did not speak to me in person but rather through the power of his judgments. In particular, his seminal judgment in Roncarelli v. Duplessis2 (“Roncarelli”) struck a particularly harmonious chord at a time when I was concerned about the absence from New Zealand case law of any developed theory or conception of the role of the courts when faced by the spectre of abuse of executive powers. If Canada had judges as articulate and reflective as this, it was obviously a place in which graduate legal studies could be a stimulating experience.
    [Show full text]
  • A Bill of Rights for Australia?
    Discussion Paper: A Bill of Rights for Australia? Introduction In recent months, State and Federal judges1, politicians, academics2 and the press have commented on the desirability of a Bill of Rights for Australia. At a Federal level, the Australian Democrats have foreshadowed the introduction of a draft Bill into Federal Parliament. In December 1993, the Australian Capital Territory Attorney General's Department published a detailed issues paper entitledA Bill of Rights for the ACT? seeking community discussion on the subject. The debate about a Bill of Rights is at an embryonic stage. Whether it proceeds to mature is speculation. However, there is no doubt that the debate will continue in the wider community in some form. That being so, this paper attempts to identify some prominent issues to facilitate a discussion of them by Conference. Definitions 1.1 What is a Bill of Rights? A Bill of Rights is the formal enumeration and codification of specific rights which individuals of a community, and the community itself, uphold as basic. A Bill of Rights seeks to preserve and/or to extend rights of persons in civil society.3 According 1 See Mr. Justice Young of the Supreme Court of New South Wales, Editor of the Australian Law Journal, "Australian charter of rights," Australian Law Journal 67 (Nov.1993) 807-08. 2 E.g. R. Cullen, "Does Australia need a Bill of Rights?" Law Institute Journal 67 (Jan.1993) 71. 3 Ideally, particularly in the natural law tradition, a Bill of Rights is an attempt to define and to protect the conditions necessary for human flourishing.
    [Show full text]
  • SEPARATION, ENUMERATION, and the IMPLIED BILL of RIGHTS  Laurence Claus
    SEPARATION, ENUMERATION, AND THE IMPLIED BILL OF RIGHTS Laurence Claus The United States Constitution sets forth two strategies for distributing power within the system of government that it establishes. To distribute power horizontally within the national government, the Constitution seeks to separate power by kind – legislative, executive, and judicial. To distribute power vertically between the national and state governments, the Constitution seeks to enumerate power by subject. Neither strategy works. Separation by kind fails because governing actions are not of single kinds. Governing in all three branches necessarily involves both lawmaking and law-executing. Enumeration by subject fails because governing actions are not about single subjects. Governing actions can readily be characterized in more than one way, as about more than one subject. Consequently, those who must decide disputes about the distribution of power are obliged to create a law of institutional competence and a law of constitutional characterization with far less guidance from the Constitution than it purports to give them. How did these two unachievable strategies come to be adopted? What should guide courts in creating a law of institutional competence and a law of constitutional characterization to settle the actual horizontal and vertical distribution of power? Examining these questions illuminates a clearer path for courts to expound the Constitution’s meaning in ways that expand its protections. Deciding the distribution of power lets courts create an implied bill of rights. Professor of Law, University of San Diego. I am grateful for valuable comments from participants at the National Conference of Constitutional Law Scholars 2019, the Third International Biennial Public Law Conference, and a constitutional studies faculty colloquium at the University of Texas at Austin School of Law.
    [Show full text]
  • The Influence of US Jurisprudence on the Interpretation of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: an Initial Survey, 9 B.C
    Boston College International and Comparative Law Review Volume 9 | Issue 1 Article 4 12-1-1986 The nflueI nce of US Jurisprudence on the Interpretation of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: An Initial Survey Jordan D. Cooper Follow this and additional works at: http://lawdigitalcommons.bc.edu/iclr Part of the Jurisprudence Commons Recommended Citation Jordan D. Cooper, The Influence of US Jurisprudence on the Interpretation of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: An Initial Survey, 9 B.C. Int'l & Comp. L. Rev. 73 (1986), http://lawdigitalcommons.bc.edu/iclr/vol9/iss1/4 This Notes is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at Digital Commons @ Boston College Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Boston College International and Comparative Law Review by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ Boston College Law School. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Influence of U.S. Jurisprudence on the Interpretation of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: An Initial Survey 1. INTRODUCTION In 1982 the Canadian government enacted several important amendments to its constitution. I These amendments include the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, which established constitutional protection for the civil rights of Canadian citizens.2 In addition, the Charter established the concept of judicial review giving the Canadian courts the authority to strike down any legislation inconsistent with provisions in the Charter.3 Although the Charter states which rights and freedoms are to receive consti­ tutional protection,4 the courts will ultimately have to determine the degree of I The Constitution Act, 1982 is the document which contains most of these amendments.
    [Show full text]
  • Regulatory Takings in Canada
    Washington University Global Studies Law Review Volume 5 Issue 3 Symposium on Regulatory Takings in Land-Use Law: A Comparative Perspective on Compensation Rights January 2006 Regulatory Takings in Canada Bryan P. Schwartz University of Manitoba Melanie R. Bueckert Manitoba Court of Appeal Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_globalstudies Part of the Comparative and Foreign Law Commons, and the Land Use Law Commons Recommended Citation Bryan P. Schwartz and Melanie R. Bueckert, Regulatory Takings in Canada, 5 WASH. U. GLOBAL STUD. L. REV. 477 (2006), https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_globalstudies/vol5/iss3/3 This Symposium is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School at Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Washington University Global Studies Law Review by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. REGULATORY TAKINGS IN CANADA DR. BRYAN P. SCHWARTZ∗ MELANIE R. BUECKERT∗∗ I. INTRODUCTION Canadian law lacks a robust “regulatory takings” doctrine, a phenomenon partially explained by Canada’s unique constitutional backdrop. Some Canadian provinces have statutes that provide greater protection for certain property rights. Canada also has international trade obligations that require it to protect foreign investors’ property rights. The only indirect recognition and remuneration of regulatory takings is encompassed in a longstanding interpretive presumption in favor of compensation in situations involving expropriation. Yet, despite all of these safeguards to protect property rights from regulatory takings and despite recent developments in regulatory takings jurisprudence, property rights receive minimal protection under Canadian law.
    [Show full text]