The Suprienie Court ®F Canada in the Age E Rule of Law and Fundaniental Ts Under Canada's Constitution

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Suprienie Court ®F Canada in the Age E Rule of Law and Fundaniental Ts Under Canada's Constitution THE SUPRIENIE COURT ®F CANADA IN THE AGE ° 9 E RULE OF LAW AND FUNDANIENTAL TS UNDER CANADA'S CONSTITUTION Lorraine E. Weinrib* Toronto In the aftermath ofthe SecondWorld War, democraticnations have embracedjudicial protection ofindividualautonomy, equalityandrespectfor human dignity. Whileeach nation's arrangements have distinctive features, there is a discernible model of postwar rightsprotection. This essay traces the roleofthe Supreme Courtin Canada's transformation into such apostwar, rightsprotectingpolity both before and after the adoptionofthe Charter in1982. Justafterthe war, the Supreme Court took the intiative toprotectrightsjustas Canada reachedpolitical independenceand the Court became Canada's highest appellate court. Facing challenges to themostbasic assumptions of liberal democracy, some ofthejudges inferredprotectionforfundamentalfreedoms from the structure of Canada's parliamentary democracy, the federal-provincial division ofpowers and the heritage of the flexible, unwritten British constitution. Although the Court ultimately abandoned this approach, it recently returned to this legacyinimportant reference casesthatdeliberatedupon theplace ofdirectdemocracy and the independence ofthe courts in our constitutional order. This essay compares the Court's understanding of its role in protecting rights tinder this traditional approach as well as under the Charter, to the postwar model ofrightsprotection. It notes that the Court has on occasion departedfrom this model to resolve aperceived tension between vigilant judicial protection of rights and the prerogatives of the executive and the legislature in our system ofgovernment. The author argues that Canada's adaptation of the postwar model to the Canadian context resolves that tension without prompting such departures. Support for this argument rests on a number of considerations. These include the conceptual substructure of unwritten constitutionalnorms, the institutionalstructureandremedialpurposes ofthe Charter, and the common law's affinity to the postwar model of rights-protection . Au lendemain de la Seconde Guerre Mondiale, les nations démocratiques ont embrassé les politiques de protection de l'autonomie individuelle, d'égalité et de respectde la dignitéhumaine. Bien que les dispositions de chaque nation comportent desparticularités, onpeutidentifierunmodèled'aprèsguerredeprotectiondes droits. Cet article retrace le rôle de la Coursuprême dans la transformation du Canadapar cette politiqué d'après guerre de protection des droits, aussi bien avant qu'après l'adoption de la Charte en 1982. Juste après la guerre la Cour suprême a pris l'initiative de protéger les droits au moment même où le Canada atteignait l'indépendance politique etque la Cour devenait laplus haute cour d'appel aupays. Faisant face à une remise en question des postulats les plus fondamentaux de la démocratie libérale, certainsjuges ontdéduit laprotection des libertésfondamentales de la structure de la démocratie parlementaire canadienne, dupartage despouvoirs entre leprovincial et lefédéral, et de l'héritage de la constitution britannique, souple * Lorraine E. Weinrib, ofthe Faculty of Law, University ofToronto, Toronto, Ontario. 700 THE CANADIAN BAR REVIEW [Vol.8O et non écrite. Bien que la Cour ait ultimementabandonné cette approche, elle est revenue à cethéritage dansdes affaires importantes de renvoiportant sur laplace de la démocratie directe et sur l'indépendance des tribunaux dans notre ordre constitutionnel. Cet essai compare la compréhension que la Cour a de son rôle dans la protection des droits, en vertu de cette approche traditionelle et en vertu de la Charte, avec le modèle d'après guerre deprotection des droits. Il relève qu'à l'occasion la Cour s'est écartée de ce modèle pour résoudre le problème de la tension qu'elle avait perçue entre une protection judiciaire des droitsfaite avec vigilance et les prérogatives de l'exécutif et du législatifdans notre système de gouvernement. L'auteur soutient que l'adaptation du modèle d'après guerre ail contexte canadien résout cette tension sanspour autantsacrifier laprotection des droits. Cette thèses'appuie sur un certain nombrede considérations. Parmi celles- ci ily a la sons-structure conceptuelle de normes constitutionnelles non écrites, la structure institutionnelle de la Charte etsesobjectifs de remédierà desproblèmes, ainsi que les affinités de la common law avec le modèle d'après guerre de protection des droits. I. The Age ofRights: Principles and Transitions ........ ... ........ ... .. .. ... 701 II. The Postwar Model of the Constitutional State .. ... ... ..... ..... ... ... ..... 704 III. The Supreme Court and the "Implied Bill ofRights" . ........ ... .. ... ... 710 IV. The Charter: Legal Structure and Institutional Roles ... ..... ... ... ..... 720 V. The Supreme Court and the Charter.. ........ ... ... ........ ... ..... ........ ... ... 734 VI. Conclusion ........ ... ... ........ ... ........ ... .. .. ........ .. ... ... ... .. ..... ... .. ... ... .. ... 743 "The development of the constitutional state can be understood as an open sequence ofexperience-guidedprecautionary measuresagainst the overpowering ofthe legalsystembyillegitimate power relations that contradictitsnormative self- understanding. "l ". ..'true' democracy recognizes the power of the constitution - fi-uit of the constituent authority - to entrench thefimdamental human rights and the basic values ofthe system against thepower ofthe majority. Such limitation ofmajority rule does not impairdemocracy but constitutes itsfull realization. "2 "That in thequestionsfacing courts wemustexcludetheory hasneverbeen the rule and never can be the rule: theory is simply the completion ofideas. "3 I J. Habermas, BetweenFacts andNorms (Cambridge, Mass: MITPress, 1996) at 39. UnitedMizrahi Bank Ltd. v. Migdal Cooperative Village (1995), P.D. 221 atpara. 47 per Justice Aharon Barak, President, Supreme Court ofIsrael. I.C. Rand, "The Role ofan Independent Judiciary in Preserving Freedom" (1951) 9 U.T.L.J.1 at 12. 2001] The Supreme Court ofCanada in the Age ofRights 70 1 I. The Age ofRights : Principles in Transition We' live in the age of rights.4 In the aftermath of the Second World War, commitment to theprinciples embodied in the modernidea ofhumanrights has intensified in the West, although the record of achievement is undeniably blemished. Liberty, equality and respect for human dignity have come to enjoy unprecedented support as abstract principles. Nonetheless, no single magic formula protects these principles in all contexts. It falls to each nation to make and re-make its own arrangements, either alone or in concert with other nation states: The fundamental problem concerning human rights today is not so much how to justify them, but how to protect them.5 These arrangements build upon several fundamental tenets of constitutional government. The first is an understanding of democracy as the sovereignty of the people, not of the legislature in the abstract or as a particular, temporarily elected, law-making body. It is this meaning ofdemocracy that legitimates the exercise of state power over all members of the postwar nation state.6 The second is that government power is not unlimited. It operates under the discipline of the rule oflaw, bolstering the idea that liberty prevails unless and until the law-making machinery has takenthe trouble to stipulate otherwise. To these, a third "experience guided precautionary measure" has been addedin the postwar period, that the constitutional state must directly protect fundamental rights andfreedoms? This third tenetreflects the painfully learnedlessonofthe twentieth century. Generally accepted practices of democratic government reliably secure neither the long-term continuity of democracy, nor the optimal operation oftherule of law, nor the entitlements to liberty, equality andrespect fordignitynow considered fundamental within thepostwar,pluralist,egalitarian, and often divided state. The postwar redesign of the democratic state has as its daunting aspiration the correction of these failings. The postwar agenda is an ambitious undertaking. It responds to dramatic changes in the nation state. The nation state is no longer the state of the nation: .. .today all ofus liveinpluralist societies . .. [in which] themajority culture must give up its historical prerogative to define the official terms of the generalized political culture that is to be shared by all citizens, regardless of whence they come andhow 4 C.N. Tate & T. Valinder, eds., The Global Expansion of Judicial Power (New York: New York University Press, 1995),, C.R. Epp, The Rights Revolution: Lawyers, Activists, and Supreme Courts in Comparative Perspective (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998), M. Shapiro and A. Stone, "The New Constitutional Politics of Europe" (1994) 26 Comparative Political Studies 397 . 5 N. Bobbio, The Age ofRights (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1996) at 10. 6 S. Freedman, "Constitutional Democracy and the Legitimacy ofJudicial Review" (1990-91) 9 Law and Philosophy 327 . See R:L. Brown, "Accountability, Liberty, and the Constitution (1998) 98 Colum. L. Rev. 531 for the origins of the counter-majoritarian dilemma in the U.S. context. Habemas, supra note 1. 702, LA REVUEDU BARREAU CANADIEN [VO1.80 they live. .Such generalized political cultures haveasreference national constitutions ; each ofthem contextualizes the same universalist principles, popular sovereignty and human rights, differently from the perspective oftheir own
Recommended publications
  • Building a Law of Human Rights: Roncarelli V. Duplessis in Canadian Constitutional Culture Eric M
    Document generated on 09/26/2021 12:09 p.m. McGill Law Journal Revue de droit de McGill Building a Law of Human Rights: Roncarelli v. Duplessis in Canadian Constitutional Culture Eric M. Adams The Legacy of Roncarelli v. Duplessis, 1959-2009 Article abstract L’héritage de l’affaire Roncarelli c. Duplessis, 1959-2009 This article reveals how audiences, especially in anglophone Canada, initially Volume 55, Number 3, September 2010 received and interpreted Roncarelli v. Duplessis as a case, above all, about human rights. Ignoring the judgment’s myriad complexities, commentators URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1000619ar eagerly situated the case within the Supreme Court of Canada’s “implied bill of DOI: https://doi.org/10.7202/1000619ar rights” jurisprudence then taking shape. Part of the reason for the emphasis on Roncarelli’s rights can be traced to the manner in which Frank Scott and Louis Stein argued the case, and the language of rights employed by Justice Ivan See table of contents Rand’s iconic judgment. But Roncarelli’s meaning also took shape in press accounts and editorials, radio broadcasts, case comments, and law school lectures. Exploring these Publisher(s) often-neglected sources, this article exposes the role of constitutional culture in McGill Law Journal / Revue de droit de McGill creating jurisprudential meaning. In turn, it also calls for greater recognition of the pre-Charter Supreme Court of Canada in contributing to Canada’s ISSN intellectual history of rights. 0024-9041 (print) 1920-6356 (digital) Explore this journal Cite this article Adams, E. M. (2010). Building a Law of Human Rights: Roncarelli v.
    [Show full text]
  • Romance, Realism, and the Legitimacy of Implied Rights Grant Huscroft
    ROMANCE, REALISM, AND THE LEGITIMACY OF IMPLIED RIGHTS GRANT HUSCROFT* Passage of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms in 1982 empowered Canadian judges not only to determine whether legislation infringed constitutionally protected rights, but also to declare legislation to be of no force or effect – to ‘strike it down’ – if they concluded that the infringement was not justified. This was a massive transfer of power from the elected branch of government to the judiciary and heady stuff for Canadian jurists. Prior to the Charter Canadian judges had no formal constitutional role in the protection of rights. The Canadian Bill of Rights, a statutory bill of rights that includes most of the rights enumerated in the Charter, had been in place since 1960, but it came to little despite its requirement that federal legislation should be rights-consistent.1 Indeed, the Canadian Bill of Rights is widely assumed to have failed because of judicial indifference to it, and the Chief Justice of the Supreme Court of Canada, Brian Dickson, was keen to ensure that this did not happen to the Charter. Dickson equated the success of the Charter with an activist role for the courts,2 and under his leadership the Court promoted and encouraged Charter litigation from the outset, easing standing rules and welcoming interventions by interested parties, among other things. Lawyers took their cue and a spate of Charter challenges to legislation was the result. The Court embraced its new lawmaking role under the Charter, making clear that the Charter was a break from the past and that its provisions would be interpreted generously and progressively.3 The impact of judicial review under the Charter is impossible to deny.
    [Show full text]
  • The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms
    Public Law II AK/POLS 3136 1 Agenda • Defining Civil Liberties • A Brief History of Civil Liberties in Canada • Implied Bill of Rights • Canadian Bill of Rights • Universal Declaration of Human Rights (handout) 1 Civil Liberties • Freedoms that protect the individual from the government. • Civil liberties set limits for government so that it cannot abuse its power. • The protection of civil liberties is a key feature of democratic states, as distinct from authoritarian states. • The Constitution of Canada includes the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms 3 Brief History of Civil Liberties in Canada 4 Brief History • No Bill of Rights ?? • Implied Bill of Rights • Bill of Rights • Charter of Rights & Freedoms 5 • In 1867, the British North American colonies after confederation did not include a bill of rights in their constitution. • English Common Law inherited by Canada included rules that are protective of civil liberties but does not provide any guarantee for their continued recognition. 6 Implications • In the absence of a bill of rights, when a law abridging a civil liberty is challenged, the issue is that of jurisdiction, not whether the injustice should be prohibited completely. • In other words, if the courts were faced with a law passed by a province that placed restrictions on civil liberties, the responsibility of the court was not to state whether or not the law violated a civil liberty or freedom but if the law fell under the province's jurisdiction under the constitution. 7 Implications • In other words, if the courts were faced with a law passed by a province that placed restrictions on civil liberties, the responsibility of the court was not to state whether or not the law violated a civil liberty or freedom but if the law fell under the province's jurisdiction under the constitution.
    [Show full text]
  • The Central Fallacy of Canadian Constitutional Law
    The Central Fallacy of Canadian Constitutional Law J. Noel Lyon* Legal theory is important because it shapes the questions we frame about the law and the way we respond to those questions in concrete cases. Constitutional theory is especially important because it determines the way we perceive the functions and relationships of the various institutions of government and hence the quality of our system of representative government under law. The purpose of this article is to consider how well Canadian constitutional theory reflects the law of the Canadian Constitution, and the conclusion offered will be that we claim the theoretical simplicity of the English doctrine of parliamentary supremacy by largely ignoring the written character of our basic constitutional law. The thesis is not that parliamentary supremacy is not a central principle of Canadian constitutional law, but rather that in its application to the Canadian system the doctrine must be qualified in the face of a limited legal separation of powers imposed by the British North America Act, 1867.1 The doctrine of parliamentary supremacy leads to the twin pro- positions that Parliament cannot bind its successors and that an Act of Parliament, duly passed, cannot be impeached in a court of law. We shall be concerned only with the second of these concepts, and with the extent to which the separation of powers between all three branches of government - the Legislature, Executive and Judiciary - is a matter of law for enforcement by the courts. English lawyers can assert with confidence that from the point of view of legal theory, the supremacy of Parliament is absolute and unqualified.
    [Show full text]
  • The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: Dawn of a New Era?
    THE CANADIAN CHARTER OF RIGHTS AND FREEDOMS: DAWN OF A NEW ERA? Chief Justice Brian Dickson (Retired)1 I am deeply honoured to have been asked to give this year's Merv Leitch Q.C. Memorial Lecture. It gives me particular pleasure to be associated with a lecture series that honours the life of a great Canadian who rose from humble beginnings to pursue a distinguished career of public service and in the law. Merv Leitch was born in Creelman, Saskatchewan in 1926. He grew up through the worst of the depression years, watching his family struggle to keep their farm intact. Eventually, his family moved to Alberta. Merv lived in Alderson and then Redcliff before joining the Navy in 1943 at the ripe old age of seventeen! Upon discharge, he found his way to law school at the University of Alberta, graduating with the gold medal. From 1952 to 1971 Merv practised law with Macleod Dixon, the firm to which he would return in 1982 when he left public life. But of course he is best known to many of us as a man who held a number of key cabinet positions in the Lougheed government: first as Attorney General, later as Treasurer responsible for the Heritage Fund and finally as Minister of Energy. Merv Leitch's accomplishments were truly remarkable and I am pleased to be with you to pay tribute to him this evening. Those who knew or worked with Merv Leitch are well aware that he had an abiding fascination for constitutional law. Indeed, it was his express wish that the Merv Leitch 1 I would like to acknowledge the research assistance of Robert Yalden, (Faculty of Law, McGill University) in the preparation of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Parliamentary Sovereignty Rests with the Courts:” the Constitutional Foundations of J
    Title Page “Parliamentary sovereignty rests with the courts:” The Constitutional Foundations of J. G. Diefenbaker’s Canadian Bill of Rights Jordan Birenbaum Thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the PhD degree in History Department of History Faculty of Arts University of Ottawa © Jordan Birenbaum, Ottawa, Canada, 2012 Abstract The 1980s witnessed a judicial “rights revolution” in Canada characterized by the Supreme Court of Canada striking down both federal and provincial legislation which violated the rights guaranteed by the 1982 Charter of Rights. The lack of a similar judicial “rights revolution” in the wake of the 1960 Canadian Bill of Rights has largely been attributed to the structural difference between the two instruments with the latter – as a “mere” statute of the federal parliament – providing little more than a canon of construction and (unlike the Charter) not empowering the courts to engage in judicial review of legislation. Yet this view contrasts starkly with how the Bill was portrayed by the Diefenbaker government, which argued that it provided for judicial review and would “prevail” over other federal legislation. Many modern scholars have dismissed the idea that the Bill could prevail over other federal statutes as being incompatible with the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty. That is, a bill of rights could only prevail over legislation if incorporated into the British North America Act. As such, they argue that the Diefenbaker government could not have intended the Bill of Rights to operate as anything more than a canon of construction. However, such a view ignores the turbulence in constitutional thinking on parliamentary sovereignty in the 1930s through 1960s provoked by the Statute of Westminster.
    [Show full text]
  • Meech Lake to the Contrary Notwithstanding (Part II)
    Osgoode Hall Law Journal Volume 29 Issue 3 Volume 29, Number 3 (Fall 1991) Article 3 7-1-1991 ...Meech Lake to the Contrary Notwithstanding (Part II) Roderick A. Macdonald Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/ohlj Part of the Constitutional Law Commons Article This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Citation Information Macdonald, Roderick A.. "...Meech Lake to the Contrary Notwithstanding (Part II)." Osgoode Hall Law Journal 29.3 (1991) : 483-571. https://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/ohlj/vol29/iss3/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Osgoode Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Osgoode Hall Law Journal by an authorized editor of Osgoode Digital Commons. ...Meech Lake to the Contrary Notwithstanding (Part II) Abstract In this essay, which has been published in two parts, the author argues that the Meech Lake Accord was more than a hastily cobbled together political deal between the Prime Minister and ten provincial premiers. Despite the unattractive process by which the Meech Lake Accord was struck, and especially defended, despite the disingenuous character of the arguments most often advanced for its adoption, and despite its close connection with other aspects of the federal government's political agenda which many Canadians found suspicious, the Meech Lake Accord did respond to an important issue in post- patriation constitutionalism. A review of Canadian constitutional history, the evolution of French and English linguistic minorities in Canada, and the complementary motifs of French-Canadian and English- Canadian survivance leads the author to conclude that the forces which generated the Meech Lake Accord have been perennial features of "British North American" political life since 1759.
    [Show full text]
  • Underlying Constitutional Principles
    UnderLying constitUtionaL principLes: the Legacy of JUstice rand David J. Mullan* So is it with freedom of speech. The Confederation Act recites the desire of the three provinces to be federally united into one Dominion “with a constitution similar in principle to that of the United Kingdom.” Under that constitution, government is by parliamentary institutions, including popular assemblies elected by the people at large in both provinces and Dominion; 2010 CanLIIDocs 230 government resting ultimately on public opinion reached by discussion and the interplay of ideas. If that discussion is placed under license, its basic condition is destroyed; the government, as licensor, becomes disjoined from the citizenry. The only security is steadily advancing enlightenment, for which the widest range of controversy is the sine qua non. Justice Rand in Saumur v. City of Quebec.1 INTRODUCTION Justice Ivan Cleveland Rand died in 1969, the year before I arrived in Canada from New Zealand as a graduate student. While his voice was influential among those who persuaded me to come to this country to undertake further studies, Justice Rand did not speak to me in person but rather through the power of his judgments. In particular, his seminal judgment in Roncarelli v. Duplessis2 (“Roncarelli”) struck a particularly harmonious chord at a time when I was concerned about the absence from New Zealand case law of any developed theory or conception of the role of the courts when faced by the spectre of abuse of executive powers. If Canada had judges as articulate and reflective as this, it was obviously a place in which graduate legal studies could be a stimulating experience.
    [Show full text]
  • A Bill of Rights for Australia?
    Discussion Paper: A Bill of Rights for Australia? Introduction In recent months, State and Federal judges1, politicians, academics2 and the press have commented on the desirability of a Bill of Rights for Australia. At a Federal level, the Australian Democrats have foreshadowed the introduction of a draft Bill into Federal Parliament. In December 1993, the Australian Capital Territory Attorney General's Department published a detailed issues paper entitledA Bill of Rights for the ACT? seeking community discussion on the subject. The debate about a Bill of Rights is at an embryonic stage. Whether it proceeds to mature is speculation. However, there is no doubt that the debate will continue in the wider community in some form. That being so, this paper attempts to identify some prominent issues to facilitate a discussion of them by Conference. Definitions 1.1 What is a Bill of Rights? A Bill of Rights is the formal enumeration and codification of specific rights which individuals of a community, and the community itself, uphold as basic. A Bill of Rights seeks to preserve and/or to extend rights of persons in civil society.3 According 1 See Mr. Justice Young of the Supreme Court of New South Wales, Editor of the Australian Law Journal, "Australian charter of rights," Australian Law Journal 67 (Nov.1993) 807-08. 2 E.g. R. Cullen, "Does Australia need a Bill of Rights?" Law Institute Journal 67 (Jan.1993) 71. 3 Ideally, particularly in the natural law tradition, a Bill of Rights is an attempt to define and to protect the conditions necessary for human flourishing.
    [Show full text]
  • SEPARATION, ENUMERATION, and the IMPLIED BILL of RIGHTS  Laurence Claus
    SEPARATION, ENUMERATION, AND THE IMPLIED BILL OF RIGHTS Laurence Claus The United States Constitution sets forth two strategies for distributing power within the system of government that it establishes. To distribute power horizontally within the national government, the Constitution seeks to separate power by kind – legislative, executive, and judicial. To distribute power vertically between the national and state governments, the Constitution seeks to enumerate power by subject. Neither strategy works. Separation by kind fails because governing actions are not of single kinds. Governing in all three branches necessarily involves both lawmaking and law-executing. Enumeration by subject fails because governing actions are not about single subjects. Governing actions can readily be characterized in more than one way, as about more than one subject. Consequently, those who must decide disputes about the distribution of power are obliged to create a law of institutional competence and a law of constitutional characterization with far less guidance from the Constitution than it purports to give them. How did these two unachievable strategies come to be adopted? What should guide courts in creating a law of institutional competence and a law of constitutional characterization to settle the actual horizontal and vertical distribution of power? Examining these questions illuminates a clearer path for courts to expound the Constitution’s meaning in ways that expand its protections. Deciding the distribution of power lets courts create an implied bill of rights. Professor of Law, University of San Diego. I am grateful for valuable comments from participants at the National Conference of Constitutional Law Scholars 2019, the Third International Biennial Public Law Conference, and a constitutional studies faculty colloquium at the University of Texas at Austin School of Law.
    [Show full text]
  • The Influence of US Jurisprudence on the Interpretation of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: an Initial Survey, 9 B.C
    Boston College International and Comparative Law Review Volume 9 | Issue 1 Article 4 12-1-1986 The nflueI nce of US Jurisprudence on the Interpretation of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: An Initial Survey Jordan D. Cooper Follow this and additional works at: http://lawdigitalcommons.bc.edu/iclr Part of the Jurisprudence Commons Recommended Citation Jordan D. Cooper, The Influence of US Jurisprudence on the Interpretation of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: An Initial Survey, 9 B.C. Int'l & Comp. L. Rev. 73 (1986), http://lawdigitalcommons.bc.edu/iclr/vol9/iss1/4 This Notes is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at Digital Commons @ Boston College Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Boston College International and Comparative Law Review by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ Boston College Law School. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Influence of U.S. Jurisprudence on the Interpretation of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms: An Initial Survey 1. INTRODUCTION In 1982 the Canadian government enacted several important amendments to its constitution. I These amendments include the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, which established constitutional protection for the civil rights of Canadian citizens.2 In addition, the Charter established the concept of judicial review giving the Canadian courts the authority to strike down any legislation inconsistent with provisions in the Charter.3 Although the Charter states which rights and freedoms are to receive consti­ tutional protection,4 the courts will ultimately have to determine the degree of I The Constitution Act, 1982 is the document which contains most of these amendments.
    [Show full text]
  • Regulatory Takings in Canada
    Washington University Global Studies Law Review Volume 5 Issue 3 Symposium on Regulatory Takings in Land-Use Law: A Comparative Perspective on Compensation Rights January 2006 Regulatory Takings in Canada Bryan P. Schwartz University of Manitoba Melanie R. Bueckert Manitoba Court of Appeal Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_globalstudies Part of the Comparative and Foreign Law Commons, and the Land Use Law Commons Recommended Citation Bryan P. Schwartz and Melanie R. Bueckert, Regulatory Takings in Canada, 5 WASH. U. GLOBAL STUD. L. REV. 477 (2006), https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_globalstudies/vol5/iss3/3 This Symposium is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School at Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Washington University Global Studies Law Review by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. REGULATORY TAKINGS IN CANADA DR. BRYAN P. SCHWARTZ∗ MELANIE R. BUECKERT∗∗ I. INTRODUCTION Canadian law lacks a robust “regulatory takings” doctrine, a phenomenon partially explained by Canada’s unique constitutional backdrop. Some Canadian provinces have statutes that provide greater protection for certain property rights. Canada also has international trade obligations that require it to protect foreign investors’ property rights. The only indirect recognition and remuneration of regulatory takings is encompassed in a longstanding interpretive presumption in favor of compensation in situations involving expropriation. Yet, despite all of these safeguards to protect property rights from regulatory takings and despite recent developments in regulatory takings jurisprudence, property rights receive minimal protection under Canadian law.
    [Show full text]