3 Epistemology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

3 Epistemology 3Epistemology 3.1 Psychology 3.1.1 Cognition The ambiguity of aesthetics arisesfrom its combination of epistemology and media theory.The order of knowledge forms its epistemological basis, literature is its object,establishing its autonomyfrom logic is its goal, analogyits method, and etymologyits style. The eighteenth-century order of knowledge parcels cog- nition up into abright upperpart and adarklower part at the ground of the soul (fundus animae) – therebyrevisitingwhat Niklaus Largier analyzes as apromi- nent “trope of mystical discourse.”¹ As is well known, Baumgarten’s “science of everything that is sensate” contradictsthe topical order of the faculties of the soul, which was established by Leibniz and confirmed in Wolff’s Psychologia em- pirica (1732), by transposing the vertical spatial order into ahorizontal order in which sensation (sensatio/Empfindung) is the equal of reason. But in recon- structing the epistemology of Baumgarten’saesthetics, the scholarship often makes adecisive mistake: it attends to the cognitivefaculties (facultates cogno- scitivae) but neglects the appetitive faculties (facultates appetitivae). In the fol- lowing,Iwilldiscuss the lowercognitive faculty in relation to the appetitive fac- ulty.Incontrast to affect in the seventeenth century and feeling in the late eighteenthcentury,Baumgarten posits that both sensate cognition and sensate desire follow laws analogous to thoseofreason, making it possible to analyze the formal processes of both. His aesthetics thus does not give emphatic irratio- nality the role that it will later have in the eighteenth centuryintheorieslike Her- der’s. Baumgartendifferentiates between higher cognitive faculties (facultates cog- noscitivae superiores) and lower cognitive faculties (facultates cognoscitivae in- feriores). He articulates this distinctionindetail in the Metaphysica,but it is al- readypresent in the Meditationes,wherehedistinguishes between thingsknown (noeta) and thingsperceived(aistheta), and determines that “things known are to be known by the superior faculty as the object of logic; things perceived [are to be known by the inferior faculty,asthe object] of the science of perception, or Niklaus Largier, “The Plasticity of the Soul: Mystical Darkness,Touch, and Aesthetic Experi- ence,” MLN 125.3(2010): 537. See also Hans Adler, “Fundus Animae – der Grund der Seele: Zur Gnoseologie des Dunklen in der Aufklärung,” Deutsche Vierteljahrsschrift fürLiteraturwissen- schaft und Geistesgeschichte 62.2 (1988): 197–220. OpenAccess. ©2020Frauke Berndt, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the CreativeCommons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110624519-004 3.1 Psychology 29 aesthetic” (MED §116;Sint ergo νοητα cognoscenda facultatesuperioreobiec- tum logices, αισϑητα επιϛημης αισϑητιϰης sive AESTHETICAE).² He thus under- stands sensation “as an organ of cognition independent from reason” that rep- resents “the connections of thingsinits ownparticularway.”³ In this conception of sensation, the discipline of psychologyisresponsible for articulating the laws of “representing”⁴ or “appropriating the world sensate- ly.”⁵ In part 3ofthe Metaphysica on psychology(psychologia) – where Baum- garten treats both empirical and rational (speculative) psychology – he derives the following series of sensate faculties (facultates sentiendi) from the different characteristics of sensations: (1) the inferior faculty for knowingthe correspondences of things (§572, 279), to which per- tains asensitive wit (§575); (2) the inferior faculty for knowingthe differences of things (§572, 279), to which pertains sensitive acumen (§575); (3) sensitive memory (§579, 306); (4) the faculty of invention (§589); (5) the faculty of judging(§606,94), thus sensitive judg- ment (§607) and that of the senses (§608); (6) the expectation of similar cases (§610,612); and (7) the sensitive faculty of characterization (§619,347). All of these, insofar as they are similar to reasoninrepresentingthe nexus of things,constitutethe ANALOGUE OF REA- SON (§70), or the collection of the soul’sfaculties for representinganexus confusedly. 1) inferior facultas identitates rerumcognoscendi, §. 572, 279quo ingenium sensitivum, §. 575. 2) inferior facultas diversitates rerumcognoscendi, §. 572, 279. quo acumen sensiti- vum pertinet,§.575.3)memoria sensitiva, §. 579, 306.4)facultas fingendi, §. 589.5)facultas diiudicandi, §. 606,94. quo iudicium sensitivum, §. 607. &sensuum, §. 608. 6) exspectatio casuum similium,§.610,612. 7) facultas characteristica sensitiva, §. 619, 347. Hae omnes, quatenus in repraesentando rerum nexu rationi similes sunt,constituuntANALOGON RA- TIONIS,§.70. complexum facultatum animae nexum confuse repraesentantium. (MET §640;see also AE §§ 30 –37) Baumgartenthen organizes the third part of the Metaphysica,which is based on this list of faculties, as follows: See Hans Adler and Lynn L. Wolff, eds., Aisthesis und Noesis:ZweiErkenntnisformen vom 18. Jahrhundert bis zur Gegenwart (Munich: Wilhelm Fink,2013). See also TedKinnaman, “Aes- thetics beforeKant,” in ACompanion to Early Modern Philosophy,ed. Steven Nadler (Malden: Blackwell, 2002), 578–582. Ursula Franke, Kunstals Erkenntnis: Die Rolle der Sinnlichkeit in der Ästhetik des Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten (Wiesbaden: Franz Steiner,1972),37. See also Franke, “Sinnliche Erkenntnis – was sie ist und was sie soll: A. G. Baumgartens Ästhetik-Projekt zwischen Kunstphilosophie und Anthropologie,” in Aichele and Mirbach, “Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten,” 73– 99. Franke, Kunst als Erkenntnis,41. Friedhelm Solms, Disciplina aesthetica:Zur Frühgeschichte der ästhetischen Theorie bei Baum- garten und Herder (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1990), 21. 30 3Epistemology Section IIII: Imagination (phantasia) Section V: Perspicacity (perspicacia) Faculty of wit (ingenium) Faculty of acumen (acumen) Section VI: Memory (memoria) Section VII: Faculty of invention (facultas fingendi) Section VIII: Foresight (praevisio) Section VIIII: Judgment (iudicium) Section X: Anticipation (praesagitio) Section XI: Faculty of characterization (facultas characteristica) The science for analyzingthese sensate faculties requires, like anyscience,a method.Aswesaw in the last chapter,Baumgarten’s “science of everything that is sensate” is largely based on the rhetorical figureofanalogy, so it employs arhetorical method.⁶ He thus follows, as Herder astutelynotes,apath thatis more philologicallythan philosophicallygrounded: “Iamgetting closertothe heart of Baumgarten’sphilosophyand have noticed thatitissotied up with lan- guagethat his explanations, differentiations, and proofs oftenseem to work ety- mologically.”⁷ In other words, Baumgarten seems to shift the weight of his argu- ments onto the conceptsthat constitutethem. Herder becomes especiallyriled up with Baumgarten’suse of sensitivus,inEnglish “sensate,” which he seems to applytoeverything possible. In the context of the analogon of reason, the data (sense perceptions), organs (faculties), and products (representations, with regardtoboth quantity and quality) are all described with one and the same word: sensitivus. Herder bemoans this fact in his discussion of Friedrich Justus Riedel’s Theorie der schönen Künste (1767), which follows Baumgarten’s mold: We Germans disputewordsasother nations disputecauses; we areasblessed with defini- tions as others arewith inventions,and in his definition Baumgarten has moreover used a word that is rich and pregnant enough to conceal multiple meanings,thus leavingitself open to disputeand misuse: the word sensuous [sinnlich;Itranslateas“sensate,” F. B.]. Howmanyconcepts German philosophyassociates with this word! Sensuous leads us back to the source and medium of certain representations, and these arethe senses;itsig- nifies those faculties of the soul that form such representations, and these arethe so-called lower faculties of the soul; it characterizes the species of representation, confused and pleasant preciselyinthis rich, engagingconfusion; that is, sensuous;finally, it refers also to the intensity with which the representations enraptureusand excite sensuous pas- See 2.2Analogy. Johann Gottfried Herder, “VonBaumgartens Denkart in seinen Schriften,” in Werke,ed. Martin Bollacher et al., vol. 1, Frühe Schriften 1764–1772,ed. Ulrich Gaier (Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag, 1985), 653. 3.1 Psychology 31 sions – on all four conceptual paths the multifacetedwords sensuous, sensitive areinkeep- ing with the definition of Wolff, Baumgarten, and Mendelssohn.⁸ Baumgarten’sconceptual politics made more than asmall contribution to this inflation. Even the concept aesthetics itself is an argument based on words (ar- gumentum ex vi verbi). By deriving aesthetica from an etymological topos (locus ab etymologia) in the first paragraph of the Kollegium,Baumgarten traces the name for the “science of everything that is sensate” back to its original meaning and provides an etymological explanation for the analogybetween reason and sensation:⁹ It actuallycomes from aisthanomai [I sense]; this wordrefers to whatsentio refers to in Latin, namely, to all clear sensations.Sincesensations can be divided intoexternal and in- ternal ones – into those that Iamconscious of occurringinmybodyand that relatetoall the senses,and those that onlyoccur in my soul – this word, which referstoclear sensa- tions in general, applies to both. Since, furthermore, the word sentio refers to perceiving somethingwith the senses and the Greek is completely
Recommended publications
  • RN and Russell's Regress
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2001, 79 (3), pp. 395-408. RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM AND RUSSELL’S REGRESS Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra University of Edinburgh In a famous passage Bertrand Russell argued that any attempt, like that of Resemblance Nominalism, to get rid of universals in favour of resemblances fails [20, p. 48]. More precisely, Russell thought that no resemblance theory could avoid postulating a universal of resemblance without falling into a vicious infinite regress. And he added that admitting a universal of resemblance made it pointless to avoid other universals. In this paper I shall defend Resemblance Nominalism, a theory which gets rid of universals in terms of resemblances, from both of Russell’s points by arguing (a) Resemblance Nominalism can avoid the postulation of a universal of resemblance without falling into a vicious infinite regress (§V) and (b) even if Resemblance Nominalism had to admit a universal of resemblance, this would not make it pointless to avoid the postulation of other universals (§VI). But before doing so I shall briefly introduce Resemblance Nominalism (§I) and Russell’s regress (§II), and then I shall consider some failed arguments and strategies against the regress (§§III−IV). I. Resemblance Nominalism. Resemblance Nominalism is a solution to the Problem of Universals. I have argued elsewhere that the Problem of Universals, strictly understood, is what I call the Many over One, rather than the traditional One over Many [17, pp. 269-70]. The Many over One is the problem of explaining how a single particular can have a multiplicity of properties [17, pp. 269-70]. Thus solutions to the Problem of Universals account for what it is for any thing or particular a to have properties F, G, H etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Nuclear Bundles of Tropes and Ontological Dependence
    Nuclear Bundles of Tropes and Ontological Dependence JOSÉ TOMÁS ALVARADO OST DEFENDERS OF TROPE METAPHYSICS have maintained that particular objects should be reduced to bundles of tropes. Part of the attraction M of a trope metaphysic is the work that tropes can do for understanding the nature of both particulars and universals. On one hand, what we call ‘universals’ can be conceived as resemblance classes of tropes. On the other hand, particular objects are nothing but pluralities of tropes satisfying certain conditions (cf. for example, Williams 1953a, 1953b; Campbell 1981, 1990; Maurin 2002; Ehring 2011). But, what are exactly those conditions that make a plurality of tropes a particular object? It has not been easy to fill in the details of a trope theory of objects and, then, it is not surprising that a variety of different proposals have been put to the fore. Some have said that objects can be understood as mereological fusions of compresent tropes. Some have said that objects can be understood as pluralities of tropes that happen to be «co– instantiated». Some have said that «co–instantiation» is just a primitive fundamental ontological fact. Some have said that it is a relational trope, albeit an especial one. For example, a relational trope that is essentially a relation between the tropes that compose an object, although the related tropes are independent from each other (cf. Maurin 2002, pp. 164–166). For others the co–instantiation trope is a relational trope that happens to relate all the tropes composing an object, including itself (cf. Ehring 2011, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Trope Theory, Resemblance, and Russell's Regress
    Trope Theory, Resemblance, and Russell's Regress Florian Boge 12.07.2012 Structure • Introduction – what are tropes? – Nominalism about universals – Bundle theory – A refinement: nucleus theory • Similarity relations – A trope theoretical measure for relative resemblance • The resemblance regress – a fundamental problem for trope theory – Is it vicious? – Similarity as internal – A cognitivist approach as a possible solution • Perfect resemblance defined What are tropes? • Definition: Tropes are the particular properties (property instances) of a given concrete entity (cf. Campbell 1990, 18). They are abstract particulars. – Relatons = polyadic tropes – Qualitons = monadic tropes (cf. Bacon 2008, 2) • An entity is called abstract (in this context) iff. it is a part of some other entity, which can only be separated in thought (cf. Rojek 2008, 361). • Particulars (indviduals) = entities which only exist in one place at one time (interval) Spacio-temproal location as an important criterion for individuality according to trope theory: “[O]ur abstract particulars are particulars because they have a local habitation, even if no name. They exist as individuals at unique place- times.” (Campbell 1990, 3) What are tropes? • Examples: – The particular shape of a given chair – Bill Clinton‟s eloquence – „This redness‟, in contrast to „redness‟ in general • Supposed to provide an alternative to realism about universals Trope theory is a form of nominalism about universals Needs to explain our use of general terms Should be able to explain every day life‟s entities such as things, their appearance, their relations etc. Nominalism about universals • Nominalism about universals = attempt to provide an explanation of general terms (i.e. terms for types, properties, relations etc.) without appeal to universals • Universals = entities that are multiply exemplified i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Armstrong and Tropes Proof.Pdf
    Peter Simons Armstrong and Tropes “So the philosophy of tropes is riding high.” David Armstrong, U 125.¹ Appreciation 5 In 1974, while a graduate student at the University of Manchester, I rst heard David Armstrong give a talk. It was on various regress arguments against nominalism, later published in NR. At that time I was not a nominalist and the arguments seemed sound. What impressed me much more forcibly however was Armstrong’s refreshing direct- ness in addressing metaphysical issues. At that time, metaphysics was largely still 10 under the domination of the philosophy of language, and arguments about the na- ture of universals tended to go via consideration of predicates, semantics and so on. Armstrong’s rejection of bad old arguments from meaning cut through that tangle like Alexander’s sword through the Gordian knot, and we were left face to face with the metaphysical question itself: are there universals, or are there not? Just as in the phe- 15 nomenological tradition Roman Ingarden had broken away from Husserl’s transcen- dental anxietizing, so in the analytical tradition Armstrong broke away from Straw- son’s Aristotelian-Kantian linguistic metaphysics-lite and Quine’s Carnapian insou- ciance as to ultimates. The idea that metaphysics might regain her status as the Queen of Philosophy was implanted, and has stayed with me ever since. I owe David a great 20 intellectual debt for making this clear by living example. The next time I saw David was in 1990 at Zinal, by which time we and things had both moved on, and this essay is about some of those things.
    [Show full text]
  • William Ockham and Trope Nominalism
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department Classics and Religious Studies 1998 William Ockham and Trope Nominalism Stephen E. Lahey University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/classicsfacpub Part of the Classics Commons Lahey, Stephen E., "William Ockham and Trope Nominalism" (1998). Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department. 85. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/classicsfacpub/85 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Classics and Religious Studies at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. William Ockhsun and Trope Nominalism Can we take a medieval metaphysician out of his scholastic robes and force him into a metaphysical apparatus as seemingly foreign to him as a tuxedo might be? I believe that the terminological and conceptual differences that appear to prevent this can be overcome in many cases, and that one case most amenable to this project is the medieval problem of universals. After all, the problem for the medieval is, at base, the same as it is for contemporary philosophers, as for Plato: How do we account, ontologically, for many tokens of the same type? If one object has the property x and another, distinct object has the "same" property x, how to explain the apparent "samenessw of the property x? Is x one property or two? I will argue that William Ockharn's ontology, when considered in light of some contemporary philosophical thought, is remarkably fresh and vital, able seriously to be con- sidered as a tenable position, so long as we are clear about what Ockham is saying.
    [Show full text]
  • The Racism of Philosophy's Fear of Cultural Relativism
    Journal of World Philosophies Articles/99 The Racism of Philosophy’s Fear of Cultural Relativism∗ _________________________________________ SHUCHEN XIANG Institute of Foreign Philosophy, Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies, Peking University, China ([email protected]) By looking at a canonical article representing academic philosophy’s orthodox view against cultural relativism, James Rachels’ “The Challenge of Cultural Relativism,” this paper argues that current mainstream western academic philosophy’s fear of cultural relativism is premised on a fear of the racial Other. The examples that Rachels marshals against cultural relativism default to the persistent, ubiquitous, and age-old stereotypes about the savage/barbarian Other that have dominated the history of western engagement with the non-western world. What academic philosophy fears about cultural relativism, it is argued, is the barbarians of the western imagination and not fellow human beings. The same structure that informs fears of cultural relativism, whereby people with different customs are reduced to the barbarian/savage of the western imagination, can be seen in the genesis of international law which arose as a justification for the domination of the Amerindian (parsed as “barbarians”). It is argued that implicit in arguments against cultural relativism is the preservation of the same right to dominate the Other. Finally, it is argued that the appeal of the fear of cultural relativism is that, in directing moral outrage at others, one can avoid reflecting on the failures of one’s own cultural tradition. Key words: racism; barbarian; moral universalism; cultural relativism; James Rachels; Amerindian; international law 1 Introduction This paper will illustrate how the structure of mainstream western philosophy’s fear of cultural relativism can be understood as a continuation of the pervasive racist beliefs that have dominated much of western history.
    [Show full text]
  • A Choice of Illusions: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature
    A Choice of Illusions: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature Alastair Morrison Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Columbia University 2015 © 2015 Alastair Morrison All rights reserved ABSTRACT A Choice of Illusions: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature Alastair Morrison This dissertation considers how defenses of traditional faith in Britain have adapted to new frontiers of cultural relativism and religious difference. Its contention is that poetry has become central to such defenses. Relativistic thinking would seem to dispose against metaphysical belief; poetry, as a parallel claimant for cultural and expressive particularity, and as a sensuously non-empirical rhetorical medium, offers a way of muffling the dissonance that might otherwise arise from positioning difference and particularity as pretext for claims of universal truth. This study traces formal and rhetorical innovations from the Victorian crisis of faith forward to literary modernism, with a brief conclusion contemplating related developments in more contemporary poetry and religious thought in Britain. Table of Contents Acknowledgements ii 1. Introduction: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature 1 i. works cited 11 2. Unction on the Tightrope: Religion as Culture in Victorian Britain 12 ii. works cited 60 3. T.E. Hulme: What Choice in Illusion? 63 iii. works cited 94 4. To Do the Right Thing for the Wrong Reason: The Justification of T.S. Eliot 96 iv. works cited 131 5. David Jones: Cultures in Parenthesis 134 v. works cited 164 6. Conclusion: Poetry and Postsecularism 166 vi. works cited 173 i Acknowledgements It is chastening to think how different this study might be were it not for the generous contributions others have made to it.
    [Show full text]
  • Herbert Hochberg • Kevin Mulligan (Eds.) Relations and Predicates
    Herbert Hochberg • Kevin Mulligan (Eds.) Relations and Predicates P h i l o s o p h i s c h e A n a l y s e P h i l o s o p h i c a l A n a l y s i s Herausgegeben von / Edited by Herbert Hochberg • Rafael Hüntelmann • Christian Kanzian Richard Schantz • Erwin Tegtmeier Band 11 / Volume 11 Herbert Hochberg • Kevin Mulligan (Eds.) Relations and Predicates ontos verlag Frankfurt . Lancaster Bibliographic information published by Die Deutsche Bibliothek Die Deutsche Bibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliographie; detailed bibliographic data is available in the Internet at http://dnb.ddb.de North and South America by Transaction Books Rutgers University Piscataway, NJ 08854-8042 [email protected] United Kingdom, Ire Iceland, Turkey, Malta, Portugal by Gazelle Books Services Limited White Cross Mills Hightown LANCASTER, LA1 4XS [email protected] 2004 ontos verlag P.O. Box 15 41, D-63133 Heusenstamm www.ontosverlag.com ISBN 3-937202-51-X 2004 No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in retrieval systems or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use of the purchaser of the work Printed on acid-free paper ISO-Norm 970-6 Printed in Germany. Contents Introduction 7 Herbert Hochberg / Kevin Mulligan Absurd Claims 11 Lars Gustafsson Relations, Properties and Particulars 17 Herbert Hochberg (University of Texas at Austin, USA) Predication Theory: Classical vs Modern 55 Ignacio Angelelli (University of Texas at Austin, USA) Bareness, as in ‘“Bare” Particulars’: Its Ubiquity 81 Fred Wilson (University of Toronto, Canada) Objects as Hierarchical Structures: A Comprehensive Ontology 113 Donald W.
    [Show full text]
  • Hellwig.Pdf (350.8Kb)
    WHY TROPES CANNOT BE METAPHYSICALLY SIMPLE A Thesis by HEINRIK ZIEHM HELLWIG Submitted to the Office of Graduate Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS May 2008 Major Subject: Philosophy WHY TROPES CANNOT BE METAPHYSICALLY SIMPLE A Thesis by HEINRIK ZIEHM HELLWIG Submitted to the Office of Graduate Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS Approved by: Chair of Committee, Christopher Menzel Committee Members, Michael LeBuffe Hugh McCann Harold Boas Head of Department, Daniel Conway May 2008 Major Subject: Philosophy iii ABSTRACT Why Tropes Cannot Be Metaphysically Simple. (May 2008) Heinrik Ziehm Hellwig, B.A., John Carroll University Chair of Advisory Committee: Dr. Christopher Menzel A popular concept in contemporary metaphysics is that of metaphysical simplicity—the idea that an existent can have no parts. One reason for this is that the notion of a simple is crucial to discussions of the composition of single objects. Simples, if real, are the basic units that, when combined in various ways, make up all other objects. Keith Campbell claims that tropes—particularized properties—can be simple. In this essay I argue, against Campbell, that tropes cannot be simple. They are made up of at least two parts—a bare particular and a universal. In Section 1 I give an exhaustive account of what it is to be a simple. Then in Section 2 I discuss basic particulars and what conditions must hold for a simple to be basic.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defense of a Trope-Based Ontology for Conceptual Modeling: an Example with the Foundations of Attributes, Weak Entities and Datatypes
    In Defense of a Trope-Based Ontology for Conceptual Modeling: An example with the foundations of Attributes, Weak Entities and Datatypes Giancarlo Guizzardi 1,2 , Claudio Masolo 1, Stefano Borgo 1 1Laboratory for Applied Ontology (ISTC-CNR), Trento, Italy {guizzardi,masolo,borgo}@loa-cnr.it 2 Computer Science Department, Federal University of Espirito Santo, Vitoria-ES, Brazil Abstract. In recent years, there has been a growing interest in approaches that employ foundational ontologies as theoretical tools for analyzing and improv- ing conceptual modeling languages . However, some of these approaches do not always make explicit their ontological commitments. This leads to situations where criticisms resulting from the specific ontological choices made by a par- ticular approach are generalized to the enterprise of ontology as a whole. In this paper we discuss an example of such a case involving the BWW approach. First, we make explicit the ontological commitments underlying that approach by relating it to other possible philosophical alternatives. Second, we construct an ontological theory which commits to a different philosophical position. Third, we show how the ontology proposed here can be used to provide real- world semantics and sound modeling guidelines for the modeling constructs of Attributes, Weak Entities and Datatypes. Finally, we compare the ontology pro- posed here with BWW, thus demonstrating its benefits. 1 Introduction In recent years, there has been a growing interest in the use of foundational ontologies for: (i) evaluating conceptual modeling languages; (ii) developing guidelines for their use; (iii) providing real-world semantics for their modeling constructs (e.g., [5,7,18]). A well-known example of a foundational ontology in the conceptual model- ing/information systems area is the Bunge-Wand-Weber (BWW) ontology proposed by Wand and Weber in a series of articles (e.g., [5,20]) on the basis of the original meta- physical theory developed by Bunge in [2].
    [Show full text]
  • Plato Journal
    DEZ 2013 ISSN 2079-7567 I3 eISSN 2183-4105 Established 1989 http://platosociety.org/ Papers William H.F. Altman “The Missing Speech of the Absent Fourth: Reader Response and Plato’s Timaeus-Critias” David Levy, “Socrates vs. Callicles: Examination and Ridicule in Plato’s Gorgias.” Nathalie Nercam, “En tout et pour tout (Théétète 204a-210b)” Matthew Robinson, “Competition, Imagery, and Pleasure in Plato’s Republic, 1-91” Scott J. Senn, “Ignorance or Irony in Plato’s Socrates?: A Look Beyond Avowals and Disavowals of Knowledge” INTERNATIONAL PLATO SOCIETY PLATO INTERNATIONAL PL ATO Société Platonicienne JOURNALInternationale Associazione Internazionale dei Platonisti Sociedad Internacional de Platonistas Internationale Platon-Gesellschaft Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra Coimbra Universiy Press 2 | Enicaper ficaed susta nondin is es nonim et dolore CREDITS EditOriAL BOARD INterNAtiONAL PLATO Francisco Gonzalez SOcietY EXecutiVE University of Ottawa COmmittee (2013-16) Irmgard Männlein-Robert President: Francisco Bravo Universität Tübingen Universidad Central de Venezuela Angela Ulacco President: Gabriele Cornelli Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg Universidade de Brasília Vice President: Tom Robinson ScieNtific BOArd University of Toronto Luc Brisson Ex-President: Mauro Tulli CNRS – UPR76 Centre Jean-Pépin, Paris Università degli Studi di Pisa Tomás Calvo Next President: Luc Brisson Universidad Complutense, Madrid CNRS – UPR76 Centre Jean-Pépin, Paris John Dillon Next President: Olivier Renaut Trinity College, Dublin Université Paris
    [Show full text]
  • Two Ways to Particularize a Property
    Two Ways to Particularize a Property Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 2015, 1(4), 635-652. Robert K. Garcia Texas A&M University [email protected] www.robertkgarcia.com Request from the author: If you would be so kind, please send me a quick email if … • you are reading this for a university or college course, or • you are citing this in your own work. It is rewarding to know how my work is being used, especially if it has been adopted as required or recommended reading. Thank you. Citation Information: • Garcia, Robert K. (2015) “Two Ways to Particularize a Property” Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 2015, 1(4), 635-652. Journal of the American Philosophical Association http://journals.cambridge.org/APA Additional services for Journal of the American Philosophical Association: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Two Ways to Particularize a Property ROBERT K. GARCIA Journal of the American Philosophical Association / Volume 1 / Issue 04 / December 2015, pp 635 - 652 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2015.21, Published online: 29 December 2015 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S2053447715000214 How to cite this article: ROBERT K. GARCIA (2015). Two Ways to Particularize a Property. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1, pp 635-652 doi:10.1017/apa.2015.21 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/APA, IP address: 50.24.68.155 on 31 Dec 2015 Journal of the American Philosophical Association (2015) 635–652 C American Philosophical ⃝ Association doi: 10.1017/apa.2015.21 Two Ways to Particularize a Property abstract: Trope theory is an increasingly prominent contender in contemporary debates about the existence and nature of properties.
    [Show full text]