A Choice of Illusions: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Choice of Illusions: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature A Choice of Illusions: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature Alastair Morrison Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Columbia University 2015 © 2015 Alastair Morrison All rights reserved ABSTRACT A Choice of Illusions: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature Alastair Morrison This dissertation considers how defenses of traditional faith in Britain have adapted to new frontiers of cultural relativism and religious difference. Its contention is that poetry has become central to such defenses. Relativistic thinking would seem to dispose against metaphysical belief; poetry, as a parallel claimant for cultural and expressive particularity, and as a sensuously non-empirical rhetorical medium, offers a way of muffling the dissonance that might otherwise arise from positioning difference and particularity as pretext for claims of universal truth. This study traces formal and rhetorical innovations from the Victorian crisis of faith forward to literary modernism, with a brief conclusion contemplating related developments in more contemporary poetry and religious thought in Britain. Table of Contents Acknowledgements ii 1. Introduction: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature 1 i. works cited 11 2. Unction on the Tightrope: Religion as Culture in Victorian Britain 12 ii. works cited 60 3. T.E. Hulme: What Choice in Illusion? 63 iii. works cited 94 4. To Do the Right Thing for the Wrong Reason: The Justification of T.S. Eliot 96 iv. works cited 131 5. David Jones: Cultures in Parenthesis 134 v. works cited 164 6. Conclusion: Poetry and Postsecularism 166 vi. works cited 173 i Acknowledgements It is chastening to think how different this study might be were it not for the generous contributions others have made to it. Feedback is always the starting point for new writing and revision, and it is tempting to think of the re-imaginations that result as substantially one's own. But what is probably always an illusion would be especially unpardonable here; too many blind spots have been pointed out, too many excesses trimmed, too many half-made arguments clarified. I have been fortunate, too, in forbearance, in so often having been given time to think again. My three outstanding advisors, Edward Mendelson, Michael Golston, and Bruce Robbins, read innumerable drafts, and provided me with advice that was always apt and generous. Jed Esty and Stathis Gourgouris were invaluable in the defense process, and Sarah Cole helped me with several pieces related to this project; all of their perceptive notes have helped me greatly. My friends at Columbia have contributed to my thinking on the issues discussed here with insight and good humor; my thanks especially to Deborah Aschkenes, Gania Barlow, Tim Donahue, Emily Hayman, Lucas Kwong, Sarah Minsloff, and Adam Spry. Here and everywhere, I owe my deepest gratitude to Jackie Weatherill, without whose kindness, wit, and sanity so little would be possible. ii For my Grandmother, Mary Sue McCarthy who knows more about this than I do iii Introduction: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature In a 2004 essay, Charles Taylor summarizes the epistemological model which he sees undergirding much of modern secularism in the West: this structure operates with a picture of knowing agents as individuals, who build up their understanding of the world through combining and relating, in more and more comprehensive theories, the information which they take in (49) This understanding of how humans acquire knowledge, "which is only partly consciously entertained, but which controls the way people think, argue, infer, and make sense of things" (49), makes the validity of a factual claim dependent on the extent to which it can be verified by an already-constituted, observing subject. In consequence, claims about the Unseen are extremely difficult to legitimate: "I must accede to the transcendent, if at all, by inference from the natural" (50). But for all its apparent naturalness, Taylor argues, this epistemological model is highly debatable, even flatly false. Human knowledge is not in fact acquired by neutrally observing individuals; observations acquire their meaning within a process of "working out," "an ongoing activity of coping with the world by bodily, social, and cultural beings" which is prior to any given instance (50). Taylor's is a powerful challenge to a certain kind of factualist atheism, of the positivist tradition which produces statements like Bertrand Russell's, that religious belief was unjustified due to "insufficient evidence." But it makes Taylor some curious bedfellows. The idea that an autonomous and rational self is precondition to subsequent knowledge comes from Enlightenment figures like Descartes; ideas like Taylor's, that knowledge is the result of anthropologically or societally variable processes, have achieved their recent influence through the work of Theodor Adorno and Michel Foucault. 1 These are, to be fair, two of the figures most troubled by the processes of thought- formation they report. There is also the venerable position that the deep backdrops to the rational and empirical intellectual agency of the individual are positive, even precious bequeathments. This position can be materialist; in the view Raymond Williams and the tradition of cultural studies, the constitution of individual subjectivities is a social, dynamic, and interactive process, in a way which implies democracy and community. The position can also be metaphysical, as it was when Samuel Taylor Coleridge expressed it in Aids to Reflection (1825). Drawing on Kantian concepts of a priori knowledge, and on Schiller's emphasis of aesthetics as a mechanism for reaching the transcendent, Coleridge proposed Understanding, and essential human faculty triggered by sensory experience, but pointing to ultimate truths far surpassing that experience. Understanding existed alongside Reason, which processed experience empirically, and reached abstract conclusions only by induction. Understanding, the faculty which allowed one to look at the mountains around Chamounix and see God, was always privileged. Reason depended on Understanding for confidence in its own observations.1 Williams admired Coleridge, and gave him a prominent role in the tradition of resistance to bourgeois rationalism to which Williams himself subscribed. This being said, their approaches are quite different, especially in terms of the ground they leave open to religious faith. The gap between these two sorts of positions - between foundational claims of non-empirical revelation and relativistic assertions of material contingency in perception - poses a considerable obstacle for Taylor's defense of faith. And not only Taylor's. I choose him as a convenient metonym for the diverse range of scholars who have disputed secularism on relativist grounds in recent 1 For an instance of the cultural studies position, see Williams' "Dominant, Residual, and Emergent" in Marxism and Literature (121). For the reference to Chamounix, see Coleridge's poem “Chamouny, the Hour Before Sunrise.” 2 years, from William Connolly in political science to Talal Asad, Saba Mahmood, and Charles Hirschkind in anthropology. On the one hand, many people are no longer likely to be moved by an intuitionist argument like Coleridge's. Paradigms of cultural diffusion, like Williams', show us how such intuitions could in fact be culturally produced, while, at the same time, we have become increasingly aware of the fact that no consensus of intuitions actually exists. Relativism supplies a much more actionable reply to the idea of naked reason "disproving" religious beliefs. Such relativism may save religion from dismissal as false consciousness by incorporating it into the contingent but continuous process of human meaning-making. If the relativism is not the sort that sees violence in normalization (if, in other words, the theorist is Williams rather than Foucault), it may even allow for an appreciation of religious practice as a cultural and conceptual flowering. What it would seem to disallow is the kind of metaphysical truth claim that is traditionally understood to accompany these practices. Relativism can be used to protect religion from certain kinds of attack, but it is not a position from which one can espouse religion, at least not on the terms whereby religion is defined by most people. I could mention some impressively acrobatic attempts to escape this difficulty. Saba Mahmood, for instance, offers an approach to religion as an "embodied practice," so as to deemphasize the potentially troubling matter of conviction.2 But I want to return to Coleridge. The categories of Reason and Understanding were predicted in the more explicitly literary 2 See Mahmood's The Politics of Piety. It could be argued (indeed it is a favourite point of scholars including Mahmood, Talal Asad, and Mark C. Taylor) that hard divisions between religious activity and other activity are only possible in an atmosphere of modern secularism which arises out of deracinated Western Protestantism. Charles Taylor begins the split in the high middle ages. The distinctiveness of the metaphysical knowledge claim from other kinds of knowledge claim is indeed deeply culture-bound, as is the idea that some actions fall into the range of "religion" while others do not. At least in the Abrahamic religions, however, it would probably be uncontroversial to say that subscription to a set of factual positions is a necessary part of religious life. 3 binary Coleridge had formulated in Biographia Literaria (1817), that of Fancy and Imagination. Fancy was the merely "mechanical" aspect of artistic endeavour, the manipulation of already- existing sense data into aesthetically pleasing configuration. Imagination, by contrast, was a "repetition in the finite mind of the eternal action of creation in the infinite I AM" (691-2). Just as it was Understanding that gave us faith, it is Imagination that gives us poetry, which by this gesture is made part of the access to the divine, and part of the check against the tyrannies of upstart reason. Poetry, however, is able to withstand its own relativization.
Recommended publications
  • Objective Hope: Assessing the Effectiveness of Faith-Based Organizations: a Review of the Literature
    Objective Hope: Assessing the Effectiveness of Faith-Based Organizations: A Review of the Literature by Byron R. Johnson with Ralph Brett Tompkins and Derek Webb ISR exists to initiate, support, and conduct research on religion, involving scholars and projects spanning the intellectual spectrum: history, psychology, sociology, economics, anthropology, political science, theology, and religious studies. Our mandate extends to all religions, everywhere, and throughout history. It also embraces the study of religious effects on such things as prosocial behavior, family life, economic development, and social conflict. While always striving for appropriate scientific objectivity, our scholars treat religion with the respect that sacred matters require and deserve. This research was released in 2002 as a CRRUCS Report at the University of Pennsylvania and is being re-issued as a Baylor ISR Report at Baylor University in 2008. Objective Hope: Assessing the Effectiveness of Faith-Based Organizations: A Review of the Literature Byron R. Johnson, Ph.D. Co-Director, Baylor Institute for Studies of Religion Professor of Sociology, Baylor University Senior Fellow, The Witherspoon Institute Ralph Brett Tompkins and Derek Webb in memoriam This report is dedicated to the memory of Dr. David B. Larson, the pioneering leader of faith factor research. His legacy will not know an end. objective hope 3 table of contents 5 Foreword 7 Executive Summary 8 Introduction 10 Research Examining the Relationship Between Religion and Health Outcomes Hypertension Mortality
    [Show full text]
  • London Calling: BBC External Services, Whitehall and the Cold War 1944- 57
    London calling: BBC external services, Whitehall and the cold war 1944- 57. Webb, Alban The copyright of this thesis rests with the author and no quotation from it or information derived from it may be published without the prior written consent of the author For additional information about this publication click this link. http://qmro.qmul.ac.uk/jspui/handle/123456789/1577 Information about this research object was correct at the time of download; we occasionally make corrections to records, please therefore check the published record when citing. For more information contact [email protected] LONDON CALLING: SSC EXTERNAL SERVICES, WHITEHALL AND THE COLD WAR, 1944-57 ALBAN WEBB Queen Mary College, University of London A thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the University of London for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Ph.D) 1 Declaration: The work presented in this thesis is my own. Signed: '~"\ ~~Ue6b Alban Webb Declaration: The work presented in this thesis is my own. Signed: Alban Webb ABSTRACT The Second World War had radically changed the focus of the BBC's overseas operation from providing an imperial service in English only, to that of a global broadcaster speaking to the world in over forty different languages. The end of that conflict saw the BBC's External Services, as they became known, re-engineered for a world at peace, but it was not long before splits in the international community caused the postwar geopolitical landscape to shift, plunging the world into a cold war. At the British government's insistence a re-calibration of the External Services' broadcasting remit was undertaken, particularly in its broadcasts to Central and Eastern Europe, to adapt its output to this new and emerging world order.
    [Show full text]
  • RN and Russell's Regress
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2001, 79 (3), pp. 395-408. RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM AND RUSSELL’S REGRESS Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra University of Edinburgh In a famous passage Bertrand Russell argued that any attempt, like that of Resemblance Nominalism, to get rid of universals in favour of resemblances fails [20, p. 48]. More precisely, Russell thought that no resemblance theory could avoid postulating a universal of resemblance without falling into a vicious infinite regress. And he added that admitting a universal of resemblance made it pointless to avoid other universals. In this paper I shall defend Resemblance Nominalism, a theory which gets rid of universals in terms of resemblances, from both of Russell’s points by arguing (a) Resemblance Nominalism can avoid the postulation of a universal of resemblance without falling into a vicious infinite regress (§V) and (b) even if Resemblance Nominalism had to admit a universal of resemblance, this would not make it pointless to avoid the postulation of other universals (§VI). But before doing so I shall briefly introduce Resemblance Nominalism (§I) and Russell’s regress (§II), and then I shall consider some failed arguments and strategies against the regress (§§III−IV). I. Resemblance Nominalism. Resemblance Nominalism is a solution to the Problem of Universals. I have argued elsewhere that the Problem of Universals, strictly understood, is what I call the Many over One, rather than the traditional One over Many [17, pp. 269-70]. The Many over One is the problem of explaining how a single particular can have a multiplicity of properties [17, pp. 269-70]. Thus solutions to the Problem of Universals account for what it is for any thing or particular a to have properties F, G, H etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Nuclear Bundles of Tropes and Ontological Dependence
    Nuclear Bundles of Tropes and Ontological Dependence JOSÉ TOMÁS ALVARADO OST DEFENDERS OF TROPE METAPHYSICS have maintained that particular objects should be reduced to bundles of tropes. Part of the attraction M of a trope metaphysic is the work that tropes can do for understanding the nature of both particulars and universals. On one hand, what we call ‘universals’ can be conceived as resemblance classes of tropes. On the other hand, particular objects are nothing but pluralities of tropes satisfying certain conditions (cf. for example, Williams 1953a, 1953b; Campbell 1981, 1990; Maurin 2002; Ehring 2011). But, what are exactly those conditions that make a plurality of tropes a particular object? It has not been easy to fill in the details of a trope theory of objects and, then, it is not surprising that a variety of different proposals have been put to the fore. Some have said that objects can be understood as mereological fusions of compresent tropes. Some have said that objects can be understood as pluralities of tropes that happen to be «co– instantiated». Some have said that «co–instantiation» is just a primitive fundamental ontological fact. Some have said that it is a relational trope, albeit an especial one. For example, a relational trope that is essentially a relation between the tropes that compose an object, although the related tropes are independent from each other (cf. Maurin 2002, pp. 164–166). For others the co–instantiation trope is a relational trope that happens to relate all the tropes composing an object, including itself (cf. Ehring 2011, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Master List
    Code Title Poem Poet Read by Does Note the CD Contain AIK Conrad Aiken Reading s N The Blues of Ruby Matrix Conrad Aiken Conrad Aiken Time in the Rock (selections) Conrad Aiken Conrad Aiken A Letter from Li Po Conrad Aiken Conrad Aiken BEA(1) The Beat Generation (Vol. 1) Y San Francisco Scene (The Beat Generation) Jack Kerouac Jack Kerouac The Beat Generation (McFadden & Dor) Bob McFadden Bob McFadden Footloose in Greenwich Village Blues Montage Langston Hughes Langston Hughes / Leonard Feather Manhattan Fable Babs Gonzales Babs Gonzales Reaching Into it Ken Nordine Ken Nordine Parker's Mood King Pleasure King Pleasure Route 66 Theme Nelson Riddle Nelson Riddle Diamonds on My Windshield Tom Waits Tom Waits Naked Lunch (Excerpt) William Burroughs William Burroughs Bernie's Tune Lee Konitz Lee Konitz Like Rumpelstiltskin Don Morrow Don Morrow OOP-POP-A-DA Dizzy Gillespie Dizzy Gillespie Basic Hip (01:13) Del Close and John Del Close / John Brent Brent Christopher Columbus Digs the Jive John Drew Barrymore John Drew Barrymore The Clown (with Jean Shepherd) Charles Mingus Charles Mingus The Murder of the Two Men… Kenneth Patchen Kenneth Patchen BEA(2) The Beat Generation (Vol.2) Y The Hip Gahn (06:11) Lord Buckley Lord Buckley Twisted (02:16) Lambert, Hendricks & Lambert, Hendricks & Ross Ross Yip Roc Heresy (02:31) Slim Gaillard & His Slim Gaillard & His Middle Middle Europeans Europeans HA (02:48) Charlie Ventura & His Charlie Ventura & His Orchestra Orchestra Pull My Daisy (04:31) David Amram Quintet David Amram Quintet with with Lynn Sheffield Lynn Sheffield October in the Railroad Earth (07:08) Jack Kerouac Jack Kerouac / Steve Allen The Cool Rebellion (20:15) Howard K.
    [Show full text]
  • Religious Factors Associated with Alcohol Involvement: Results From
    Drug and Alcohol Dependence 135 (2014) 37–44 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Drug and Alcohol Dependence jo urnal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/drugalcdep Religious factors associated with alcohol involvement: Results from the Mauritian Joint Child Health Project a,b,∗ a c d,e,f Susan E. Luczak , Carol A. Prescott , Cyril Dalais , Adrian Raine , g a Peter H. Venables , Sarnoff A. Mednick a Department of Psychology, SGM 501, University of Southern California, Los Angeles, CA 90089-1061, USA b Department of Psychiatry, 3350 La Jolla Village Drive, University of California, San Diego, La Jolla, CA 92161-2002, USA c Joint Child Health Project, 75 Celicourt Antelme, Quatre Bornes, Mauritius d Department of Criminology, University of Pennsylvania, 3718 Locust Walk, Philadelphia, PA 19104-6286, USA e Department of Psychology, University of Pennsylvania, 3720 Walnut Street, Philadelphia, PA 19104-6241, USA f Department of Psychiatry, University of Pennsylvania, 423 Guardian Drive, Philadelphia, PA 19104-6021, USA g Department of Psychology, University of York, Heslington, York YO10 5DD, UK a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t Article history: Background: The purpose of this study was to examine religious factors associated with alcohol involve- Received 10 August 2013 ment in Mauritius. The three main religions on the island, Hinduism, Catholicism, and Islam, promote Received in revised form different views of the appropriate use of alcohol. Based on reference group theory, we hypothesized that 23 September 2013 both the content of a religion’s alcohol norms and an individual’s religious commitment would relate to Accepted 18 October 2013 alcohol use behavior.
    [Show full text]
  • Trope Theory, Resemblance, and Russell's Regress
    Trope Theory, Resemblance, and Russell's Regress Florian Boge 12.07.2012 Structure • Introduction – what are tropes? – Nominalism about universals – Bundle theory – A refinement: nucleus theory • Similarity relations – A trope theoretical measure for relative resemblance • The resemblance regress – a fundamental problem for trope theory – Is it vicious? – Similarity as internal – A cognitivist approach as a possible solution • Perfect resemblance defined What are tropes? • Definition: Tropes are the particular properties (property instances) of a given concrete entity (cf. Campbell 1990, 18). They are abstract particulars. – Relatons = polyadic tropes – Qualitons = monadic tropes (cf. Bacon 2008, 2) • An entity is called abstract (in this context) iff. it is a part of some other entity, which can only be separated in thought (cf. Rojek 2008, 361). • Particulars (indviduals) = entities which only exist in one place at one time (interval) Spacio-temproal location as an important criterion for individuality according to trope theory: “[O]ur abstract particulars are particulars because they have a local habitation, even if no name. They exist as individuals at unique place- times.” (Campbell 1990, 3) What are tropes? • Examples: – The particular shape of a given chair – Bill Clinton‟s eloquence – „This redness‟, in contrast to „redness‟ in general • Supposed to provide an alternative to realism about universals Trope theory is a form of nominalism about universals Needs to explain our use of general terms Should be able to explain every day life‟s entities such as things, their appearance, their relations etc. Nominalism about universals • Nominalism about universals = attempt to provide an explanation of general terms (i.e. terms for types, properties, relations etc.) without appeal to universals • Universals = entities that are multiply exemplified i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Religiousness and Post-Release Community Adjustment Graduate Research Fellowship – Final Report
    The author(s) shown below used Federal funds provided by the U.S. Department of Justice and prepared the following final report: Document Title: Religiousness and Post-Release Community Adjustment Graduate Research Fellowship – Final Report Author(s): Melvina T. Sumter Document No.: 184508 Date Received: September 25, 2000 Award Number: 99-IJ-CX-0001 This report has not been published by the U.S. Department of Justice. To provide better customer service, NCJRS has made this Federally- funded grant final report available electronically in addition to traditional paper copies. Opinions or points of view expressed are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the official position or policies of the U.S. Department of Justice. “Religiousness and Post-Release Community Adjustment” Graduate Research Fellowship - Final Report Melvina T. Sumter This document is a research report submitted to the U.S. Department of Justice. This report has not been published by the Department. Opinions or points of view expressed are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the official position or policies of the U.S. Department of Justice. THE FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF CRIMINOLOGY AND CRIMINAL JUSTICE RELIGIOUSNESS AND POST-RELEASE COMMUNITY ADJUSTMENT BY MELVINA T. SUMTER A Dissertation submitted to the School of Criminology and Criminal Justice in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctorate of Philosophy Degree Awarded: . Fall Semester, 1999 Copyright 0 1999 Melvina T. Sumter All Rights Reserved This document is a research report submitted to the U.S. Department of Justice. This report has not been published by the Department.
    [Show full text]
  • Armstrong and Tropes Proof.Pdf
    Peter Simons Armstrong and Tropes “So the philosophy of tropes is riding high.” David Armstrong, U 125.¹ Appreciation 5 In 1974, while a graduate student at the University of Manchester, I rst heard David Armstrong give a talk. It was on various regress arguments against nominalism, later published in NR. At that time I was not a nominalist and the arguments seemed sound. What impressed me much more forcibly however was Armstrong’s refreshing direct- ness in addressing metaphysical issues. At that time, metaphysics was largely still 10 under the domination of the philosophy of language, and arguments about the na- ture of universals tended to go via consideration of predicates, semantics and so on. Armstrong’s rejection of bad old arguments from meaning cut through that tangle like Alexander’s sword through the Gordian knot, and we were left face to face with the metaphysical question itself: are there universals, or are there not? Just as in the phe- 15 nomenological tradition Roman Ingarden had broken away from Husserl’s transcen- dental anxietizing, so in the analytical tradition Armstrong broke away from Straw- son’s Aristotelian-Kantian linguistic metaphysics-lite and Quine’s Carnapian insou- ciance as to ultimates. The idea that metaphysics might regain her status as the Queen of Philosophy was implanted, and has stayed with me ever since. I owe David a great 20 intellectual debt for making this clear by living example. The next time I saw David was in 1990 at Zinal, by which time we and things had both moved on, and this essay is about some of those things.
    [Show full text]
  • The Approach of Quakers to Substance Use and Gambling Helena Chambers Quaker Action on Alcohol and Drugs, [email protected]
    Quaker Studies Volume 14 | Issue 1 Article 5 2010 Modern Testimonies: The Approach of Quakers to Substance use and Gambling Helena Chambers Quaker Action on Alcohol and Drugs, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.georgefox.edu/quakerstudies Part of the Christian Denominations and Sects Commons, and the Social and Behavioral Sciences Commons Recommended Citation Chambers, Helena (2010) "Modern Testimonies: The Approach of Quakers to Substance use and Gambling," Quaker Studies: Vol. 14: Iss. 1, Article 5. Available at: http://digitalcommons.georgefox.edu/quakerstudies/vol14/iss1/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ George Fox University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Quaker Studies by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ George Fox University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. QUAKER STUDIES QUAKER STUDIES 14/1 (2009) [93-107] ISSN 1363-013X �TAILS Department of Economic and Social published widely on various aspects of �ss history. He is the author of Social 2003), Thejoseph Rowntree Charitable tit Education 1904-1954 (2004) and St g with Robin Pearson (University of MODERN TESTIMONIES: THE APPROACH OF r) on a study of early British and Irish QUAKERS TO SUBSTANCE USE AND GAMBLING and Social History, Lilybank House, Helena Chambers Glasgow G12 8RT, Scotland. Gloucester, England ABSTRACT This article outlines a study into Quaker attitudes and behaviours in relation to the testimony of abstinence and moderation and that regarding gambling and speculation. The background to the Quaker testimonies is summarised, and relevant research in the substances/gambling fields about denominational influences on personal behaviours is briefly outlined.
    [Show full text]
  • Religiousness and Alcohol Use: Exploring the Role of Descriptive Drinking Norms
    University of Kentucky UKnowledge University of Kentucky Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 2007 RELIGIOUSNESS AND ALCOHOL USE: EXPLORING THE ROLE OF DESCRIPTIVE DRINKING NORMS Emily H. Brechting University of Kentucky, [email protected] Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Brechting, Emily H., "RELIGIOUSNESS AND ALCOHOL USE: EXPLORING THE ROLE OF DESCRIPTIVE DRINKING NORMS" (2007). University of Kentucky Doctoral Dissertations. 516. https://uknowledge.uky.edu/gradschool_diss/516 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Kentucky Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ABSTRACT OF DISSERTATION Emily H. Brechting The Graduate School University of Kentucky 2007 RELIGIOUSNESS AND ALCOHOL USE: EXPLORING THE ROLE OF DESCRIPTIVE DRINKING NORMS _____________________________________________ ABSTRACT OF DISSERTATION _____________________________________________ A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the College of Arts and Sciences at the University of Kentucky By Emily H. Brechting Lexington, Kentucky Director: Dr. Charles R. Carlson, Professor of Psychology Lexington, Kentucky 2007 Copyright © Emily H. Brechting 2007 ABSTRACT OF DISSERTATION RELIGIOUSNESS AND ALCOHOL USE: EXPLORING THE ROLE
    [Show full text]
  • William Ockham and Trope Nominalism
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department Classics and Religious Studies 1998 William Ockham and Trope Nominalism Stephen E. Lahey University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/classicsfacpub Part of the Classics Commons Lahey, Stephen E., "William Ockham and Trope Nominalism" (1998). Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department. 85. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/classicsfacpub/85 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Classics and Religious Studies at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. William Ockhsun and Trope Nominalism Can we take a medieval metaphysician out of his scholastic robes and force him into a metaphysical apparatus as seemingly foreign to him as a tuxedo might be? I believe that the terminological and conceptual differences that appear to prevent this can be overcome in many cases, and that one case most amenable to this project is the medieval problem of universals. After all, the problem for the medieval is, at base, the same as it is for contemporary philosophers, as for Plato: How do we account, ontologically, for many tokens of the same type? If one object has the property x and another, distinct object has the "same" property x, how to explain the apparent "samenessw of the property x? Is x one property or two? I will argue that William Ockharn's ontology, when considered in light of some contemporary philosophical thought, is remarkably fresh and vital, able seriously to be con- sidered as a tenable position, so long as we are clear about what Ockham is saying.
    [Show full text]