Large Cardinals and Elementary Embeddings of V

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Large Cardinals and Elementary Embeddings of V Large cardinals and elementary embeddings of V Master thesis of: Marios Koulakis Supervisor: Athanassios Tzouvaras, Professor à¨å ¢¦¨å£à¤ ¡ §¦¢¦ ©£¦ç ¡ £ ¢∀ ¦ ¡ã - 1997 ©« ¨æ¨ «§«¬® ¡æ ££ To the memory of my parents, Ioannis Koulakis and Anastasia Chrysochoidou Contents 1 Preliminaries 1 1.1 Cumulative hierarchies . 1 1.2 TheMostowskicollapse ....................... 5 1.3 Absoluteness ............................. 6 1.4 Vα and Lα ............................... 12 1.5 Modeltheory ............................. 17 2 Some smaller large cardinals 21 2.1 Cardinalarithmetic.......................... 22 2.2 Inaccessiblecardinals. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 26 2.3 Mahlocardinals............................ 30 2.4 Weakly compact,Erd˝osand Ramsey cardinals. 33 3 Measurable cardinals and elementary embeddings of V 37 3.1 Aspectsofmeasurability. 37 3.2 Elementary embeddings of V .................... 42 3.3 Normal measures, indescribability . 48 4 0♯ and elementary embeddings of L 53 4.1 Indiscernibles ............................. 53 4.2 0♯ ................................... 54 4.3 The connection of 0♯ with L ..................... 60 4.4 Elementary embeddings of L .................... 62 5 Stronger embeddings of V 69 5.1 Strong,Woodinandsuperstrongcardinals . 69 5.2 Stronglycompactcardinals . 72 5.3 Supercompactcardinals . 73 5.4 Extendible cardinals and Vop˘enka’s principle . 75 5.5 HugecardinalsandI0-I3. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 76 5.6 Kunen’stheorem ........................... 78 5.7 Thewholenessaxiom......................... 79 i ii CONTENTS Introduction This thesis is a short survey of the theory of large cardinals. The notion of elementary embeddings is crucial in this study, since it is used to provide a quite general way of defining large cardinals. The survey concludes with a reference to Kunen’s theorem, which sets some limitations to the existence of specific elementary embeddings, and an attempt of P. Corazza to surmount those limitations. Most of the material used through the survey is defined in chapter 1, thus the text is accessible to all readers having knowledge of basic set theory and logic. Chapter 1 serves as an extensive introduction to some notions needed for the rest of the text. Mostowski’s collapsing theorem provides us with a way of transforming a lot of models of set theory, into standard transitive ones. Some results concerning L´evi’s hierarchy illuminate the notion of absoluteness, i.e. the case in which a formula or a term behaves the same way in V as in a standard transitive model. The important cumulative hierarchies Vα and Lα are introduced, along with some of their basic properties. Finally, there is a quick reference to some model theoretical constructions we will use later on. On chapter 2, the first large cardinals appear, though they are not strong enough to yield a connection with elementary embeddings. The first section of this chapter is somehow a continuation of the first chapter, as it provides some fundamental knowledge on cardinal arithmetic. Afterwards, we define in- accessible cardinals, then go on to Mahlo cardinals and finally introduce weakly compact and Erd˝os cardinals. There is an additional reference to Ramsey car- dinals, which have a combinatorial nature similar to that of Erd˝os cardinals, even though they are essentially stronger than the other large cardinals we have mentioned here. On chapter 3 things seem to get more interesting, as we introduce measur- able cardinals. They emerge in a very natural way from measure theory and their study moves from analysis to set theory. They are connected with the elementary embeddings of the form j : V ≺ M, and out of this connection we get the result, due to Scott, that if there is a measurable cardinal, then V 6= L. Concluding, we define normal measures, which become invaluable in the study of elementary embeddings. Chapter 4 goes a little bit backwards, since we study a weaker large cardinal hypothesis, the existence of 0♯. Some effort is needed in order to define 0♯ but it pays back, as 0♯ is very close to the critical question of whether L is a good iii iv CONTENTS approach of V . Silver’s theorem and Jensen’s covering theorem give a more than satisfactory answer to this question which had been roughly approached by measuble and Ramsey cardinals. We finally see, through a theorem of Kunen, that 0♯ is connected with the elementary embeddings of the form j : L ≺ L. Chapter 5 goes on from the point where chapter 3 ended, as it presents the use of elementary embeddings of the form j : V ≺ M, in order to obtain stronger large cardinals. This way, strong, Woodin, strongly compact, supercompact and extendible cardinals appear. We come up with even stronger hypotheses, such as Vop˘enka’s principle, the existence of huge cardinals and I0-I3. The latter, seem to lie near the existence of an embedding j : V ≺ V , which cannot exist due to Kunen’s result, thus there is a probability that they could be disproved from ZF C. Finally, we examine the case of an elementary embedding j : V ≺ V . Kunen’s theorem states that there is not such an embedding. In the process, we examine the consequences of the wholeness axiom, proposed by Corazza, which asserts the existence of an embedding j : V ≺ V that is not weakly definable. The wholeness axiom may weaken the hypotheses of Kunen’s result, but it implies the existence of a super-n-huge cardinal, thus it is very near inconsistency and it should be further investigated. Chapter 1 Preliminaries In this chapter, we present some basic notions of set theory and model theory which will be necessary for our study. On the same time, we try to give some motives for the introduction of large cardinals. Our first step is to present the well known axiomatic system ZF C. Most of the axioms are presented as the closure of V under certain operations, in order to provide a more vivid image of the structure of V . Afterwards, the most powerful of those operations, the powerset operation, is used in order to introduce the notion of cumulative hierarchies. Cumulative hierarchies are roughly sequences of levels Uα, which expand, by the addition of more complex sets, as α gets bigger. Two very common hierarchies are then introduced; von Newmann’s hierarchy Vα, and the hierarchy of the constructible sets Lα. Moving towards a model theoretical study of set theory, Mostowski’s collapsing theorem becomes very useful, as it gives us the opportunity to work, in almost all cases studied here, with standard transitive models. Since standard models share the same relation with V , we are interested in the cases where some formulas have the same truth value in a stander transitive model as in V . The notion that expresses those cases is absoluteness, and an easy way to study it is the introduction of L´evi’s hierarchy of formulas. Next, we meet again the hierarchies Vα, Lα and this time prove some of their basic properties. Finally, we state some model theoretic concepts, such as Skolem functions, ultraproducts and reflection principles. For a more extensive treatment of the material covered in this chapter, the reader is referred to [7], [11] and [21]. For an elementary introduction to set theory, he is referred to [15] and [12]. A classical book on model theory is [2] and much more information on ultraproducts can be found in [1]. 1.1 Cumulative hierarchies The axioms of ZFC The first two axioms describe the nature of sets: 1 2 CHAPTER 1. PRELIMINARIES • A1. Extensionality axiom ∀z (z ∈ x ↔ z ∈ y) → x = y • A2. Foundation axiom ∃y y ∈ x → ∃y ∈ x ∀z ∈ xz∈ / y The next 7 axioms express that the universe V is closed under certain oper- ations, and are written in the form x ∈ V → Q(x) ∈ V where Q denotes an operation. These are the following: • A3φ. Separation axiom x ∈ V →{y ∈ x : φ(y)} ∈ V • A4. Empty set axiom → ∅ ∈ V • A5. Pairing axiom x, y ∈ V →{x, y} ∈ V • A6. Power set axiom x ∈ V → P (x) ∈ V • A7. Union axiom x ∈ V → ∪x ∈ V • A8. Infinity axiom (inf) ∅ ∈ V → ω ∈ V • A9φ. Replacement axiom (F) ′′ x ∈ V → Fφ (x) ∈ V ′′ Where Fφ (x)= y ↔ ∀z (z ∈ y ↔ ∃w ∈ x φ(w,z)) for φ which define functions, i.e. ∀x ∃!y φ(x, y). Finally, the tenth axiom, the axiom of choice, demands the existence of a well-ordering for every set. • A10. Choice axiom (AC) ∀x ∃y y wellorders x 1.1. CUMULATIVE HIERARCHIES 3 An immediate consequence of the axiom of foundation is the fact that there can not exist infinite ∋ sequences. If we combine this with the axiom of ex- tensionality, which states that every set is defined exactly by its elements, we can imagine a construction of V , beginning with the empty set and recursively moving to new sets using axioms A4-A10. We could also add new sets which do not appear in this construction, but may be contained in sets we have already been constructed. We should note here that by ZF C − Ai we mean the axiom system ZF C without the axiom Ai, where 1 ≤ i ≤ 10. We also denote, ZF = ZF C − AC and Z = ZF − F . Cumulative hierarchies The above approach is quite vivid and reveals the structure that V should have, in order to satisfy ZFC. Unfortunately, it is quite complicated, especially when dealing with sets of infinite cardinality. What could be done to simplify it, is to begin with the empty set and produce an ⊂ sequence hUα : α ∈ Oni of sets with increasing complexity, relative to ∈. Using this method, we approach V by constructing bigger and bigger sets of its elements instead of adding them one by one. This idea is captured by the notion of cumulative hierarchies. Definition 1.1. A transfinite sequence hUα : α ∈ Oni is called a cumulative hierarchy if the following are true: (i) U0 = ∅; (ii) Uα ⊂ Uα+1 ⊂ P (Uα); (iii) Uα = β<α Uβ, limit(α).
Recommended publications
  • What Is Mathematics: Gödel's Theorem and Around. by Karlis
    1 Version released: January 25, 2015 What is Mathematics: Gödel's Theorem and Around Hyper-textbook for students by Karlis Podnieks, Professor University of Latvia Institute of Mathematics and Computer Science An extended translation of the 2nd edition of my book "Around Gödel's theorem" published in 1992 in Russian (online copy). Diploma, 2000 Diploma, 1999 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons License and is copyrighted © 1997-2015 by me, Karlis Podnieks. This hyper-textbook contains many links to: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia; MacTutor History of Mathematics archive of the University of St Andrews; MathWorld of Wolfram Research. Are you a platonist? Test yourself. Tuesday, August 26, 1930: Chronology of a turning point in the human intellectua l history... Visiting Gödel in Vienna... An explanation of “The Incomprehensible Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences" (as put by Eugene Wigner). 2 Table of Contents References..........................................................................................................4 1. Platonism, intuition and the nature of mathematics.......................................6 1.1. Platonism – the Philosophy of Working Mathematicians.......................6 1.2. Investigation of Stable Self-contained Models – the True Nature of the Mathematical Method..................................................................................15 1.3. Intuition and Axioms............................................................................20 1.4. Formal Theories....................................................................................27
    [Show full text]
  • Large Cardinals and the Continuum Hypothesis RADEK HONZIK Charles University, Department of Logic, Celetn´A20, Praha 1, 116 42, Czech Republic Radek.Honzik@ff.Cuni.Cz
    Large cardinals and the Continuum Hypothesis RADEK HONZIK Charles University, Department of Logic, Celetn´a20, Praha 1, 116 42, Czech Republic radek.honzik@ff.cuni.cz Abstract. This is a survey paper which discusses the impact of large cardinals on provability of the Continuum Hypothesis (CH). It was G¨odel who first suggested that perhaps \strong axioms of infinity" (large car- dinals) could decide interesting set-theoretical statements independent over ZFC, such as CH. This hope proved largely unfounded for CH { one can show that virtually all large cardinals defined so far do not affect the status of CH. It seems to be an inherent feature of large cardinals that they do not determine properties of sets low in the cumulative hierarchy if such properties can be forced to hold or fail by small forcings. The paper can also be used as an introductory text on large cardinals as it defines all relevant concepts. AMS subject code classification: 03E35,03E55. Keywords: Large cardinals, forcing. Acknowledgement: The author acknowledges the generous support of JTF grant Laboratory of the Infinite ID35216. 1 Introduction The question regarding the size of the continuum { i.e. the number of the reals { is probably the most famous question in set theory. Its appeal comes from the fact that, apparently, everyone knows what a real number is and so the question concerning their quantity seems easy to understand. While there is much to say about this apparent simplicity, we will not discuss this issue in this paper. We will content ourselves by stating that the usual axioms of set theory (ZFC) do not decide the size of the continuum, except for some rather trivial restrictions.1 Hence it is consistent, assuming the consistency of ZFC, that the number of reals is the least possible, i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Paul B. Larson a BRIEF HISTORY of DETERMINACY §1. Introduction
    Paul B. Larson A BRIEF HISTORY OF DETERMINACY x1. Introduction. Determinacy axioms are statements to the effect that certain games are determined, in that each player in the game has an optimal strategy. The commonly accepted axioms for mathematics, the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms with the Axiom of Choice (ZFC; see [??, ??]), im- ply the determinacy of many games that people actually play. This applies in particular to many games of perfect information, games in which the players alternate moves which are known to both players, and the out- come of the game depends only on this list of moves, and not on chance or other external factors. Games of perfect information which must end in finitely many moves are determined. This follows from the work of Ernst Zermelo [??], D´enesK}onig[??] and L´aszl´oK´almar[??], and also from the independent work of John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern (in their 1944 book, reprinted as [??]). As pointed out by Stanis law Ulam [??], determinacy for games of perfect information of a fixed finite length is essentially a theorem of logic. If we let x1,y1,x2,y2,::: ,xn,yn be variables standing for the moves made by players player I (who plays x1,::: ,xn) and player II (who plays y1,::: ,yn), and A (consisting of sequences of length 2n) is the set of runs of the game for which player I wins, the statement (1) 9x18y1 ::: 9xn8ynhx1; y1; : : : ; xn; yni 2 A essentially asserts that the first player has a winning strategy in the game, and its negation, (2) 8x19y1 ::: 8xn9ynhx1; y1; : : : ; xn; yni 62 A essentially asserts that the second player has a winning strategy.1 We let ! denote the set of natural numbers 0; 1; 2;::: ; for brevity we will often refer to the members of this set as \integers".
    [Show full text]
  • Ineffable Limits of Weakly Compact Cardinals and Similar Results
    DOI: https://doi.org/10.15446/recolma.v54n2.93846 Revista Colombiana de Matem´aticas Volumen 54(2020)2, p´aginas181-186 Ineffable limits of weakly compact cardinals and similar results L´ımitesinefables de cardinales d´ebilmente compactos Franqui Cardenas´ Universidad Nacional de Colombia, Bogot´a,Colombia Abstract. It is proved that if an uncountable cardinal κ has an ineffable subset of weakly compact cardinals, then κ is a weakly compact cardinal, and if κ has an ineffable subset of Ramsey (Rowbottom, J´onsson,ineffable or subtle) cardinals, then κ is a Ramsey (Rowbottom, J´onsson,ineffable or subtle) cardinal. Key words and phrases. Weakly compact cardinal, subtle cardinal, ineffable car- dinal, ineffable set, J´onssoncardinal, Rowbottom cardinal, Ramsey cardinal. 2020 Mathematics Subject Classification. 03E55, 03E05. Resumen. Se prueba que si un cardinal no contable κ tiene un subconjunto casi inefable de cardinales d´ebilmente compactos entonces κ es un cardinal d´ebilmente compacto. Y si κ tiene un conjunto inefable de cardinales de Ram- sey (Rowbottom, J´onsson,inefables o sutiles) entonces κ es cardinal de Ram- sey (Rowbottom, J´onsson,inefable o sutil). Palabras y frases clave. Cardinal d´ebilmente compacto, cardinal sutil, cardinal inefable, conjunto inefable, cardinal J´onsson,cardinal Rowbottom, cardinal Ramsey. Large cardinals imply the existence of stationary subsets of smaller large cardi- nals. For instance weakly compact cardinals have a stationary subset of Mahlo cardinals, measurable cardinals imply the set of Ramsey cardinals below the measurable cardinal κ has measure 1 and Ramsey cardinals imply the set of weakly compact cardinals below the Ramsey cardinal κ is a stationary subset of κ.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1801.09149V1 [Math.CA] 27 Jan 2018 .Byn H Osrcil Hierarchy Constructible the Beyond 5
    Set Theory and the Analyst by N. H. Bingham and A. J. Ostaszewski Then to the rolling heaven itself I cried, Asking what lamp had destiny to guide Her little children stumbling in the dark. And ‘A blind understanding’ heaven replied. – The Rubaiyat of Omar Khayyam Abstract. This survey is motivated by specific questions arising in the similarities and contrasts between (Baire) category and (Lebesgue) measure – category-measure duality and non-duality, as it were. The bulk of the text is devoted to a summary, intended for the working analyst, of the extensive background in set theory and logic needed to discuss such matters: to quote from the Preface of Kelley [Kel]: ”what every young analyst should know”. Table of Contents 1. Introduction 2. Early history 3. G¨odel Tarski and their legacy 4. Ramsey, Erd˝os and their legacy: infinite combinatorics 4a. Ramsey and Erd˝os 4b. Partition calculus and large cardinals 4c. Partitions from large cardinals 4d. Large cardinals continued arXiv:1801.09149v1 [math.CA] 27 Jan 2018 5. Beyond the constructible hierarchy L – I 5a. Expansions via ultrapowers 5b. Ehrenfeucht-Mostowski models: expansion via indiscernibles 6. Beyond the constructible hierarchy L – II 6a. Forcing and generic extensions 6b. Forcing Axioms 7. Suslin, Luzin, Sierpiński and their legacy: infinite games and large cardinals 7a. Analytic sets. 7b. Banach-Mazur games and the Luzin hierarchy 1 8. Shadows 9. The syntax of Analysis: Category/measure regularity versus practicality 10. Category-Measure duality Coda 1. Introduction An analyst, as Hardy said, is a mathematician habitually seen in the company of the real or complex number systems.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Choose New Axioms for Set Theory?
    HOW TO CHOOSE NEW AXIOMS FOR SET THEORY? LAURA FONTANELLA 1. Introduction The development of axiomatic set theory originated from the need for a rigorous investigation of the basic principles at the foundations of mathematics. The classical theory of sets ZFC offers a rich framework, nevertheless many important mathemati- cal problems (such as the famous continuum hypothesis) cannot be solved within this theory. Set theorists have been exploring new axioms that would allow one to answer such fundamental questions that are independent from ZFC. Research in this area has led to consider several candidates for a new axiomatisation such as Large Cardi- nal Axioms, Forcing Axioms, Projective Determinacy and others. The legitimacy of these new axioms is, however, heavily debated and gave rise to extensive discussions around an intriguing philosophical problem: what criteria should be satisfied by ax- ioms? What aspects would distinguish an axiom from a hypothesis, a conjecture and other mathematical statements? What is an axiom after all? The future of set theory very much depends on how we answer such questions. Self-evidence, intuitive appeal, fruitfulness are some of the many criteria that have been proposed. In the first part of this paper, we illustrate some classical views about the nature of axioms and the main challenges associated with these positions. In the second part, we outline a survey of the most promising candidates for a new axiomatization for set theory and we discuss to what extent those criteria are met. We assume basic knowledge of the theory ZFC. 2. Ordinary mathematics Before we start our analysis of the axioms of set theory and the discussion about what criteria can legitimate those axioms, we should address a quite radical view based on the belief that `ordinary mathematics needs much less than ZFC or ZF '.
    [Show full text]
  • Set Theory and the Analyst
    European Journal of Mathematics (2019) 5:2–48 https://doi.org/10.1007/s40879-018-0278-1 REVIEW ARTICLE Set theory and the analyst Nicholas H. Bingham1 · Adam J. Ostaszewski2 For Zbigniew Grande, on his 70th birthday, and in memoriam: Stanisław Saks (1897–1942), Cross of Valour, Paragon of Polish Analysis, Cousin-in-law Then to the rolling heaven itself I cried, Asking what lamp had destiny to guide Her little children stumbling in the dark. And ‘A blind understanding’ heaven replied. – The Rubaiyat of Omar Khayyam Received: 14 January 2018 / Revised: 15 June 2018 / Accepted: 12 July 2018 / Published online: 12 October 2018 © The Author(s) 2018 Abstract This survey is motivated by specific questions arising in the similarities and contrasts between (Baire) category and (Lebesgue) measure—category-measure duality and non-duality, as it were. The bulk of the text is devoted to a summary, intended for the working analyst, of the extensive background in set theory and logic needed to discuss such matters: to quote from the preface of Kelley (General Topology, Van Nostrand, Toronto, 1995): “what every young analyst should know”. Keywords Axiom of choice · Dependent choice · Model theory · Constructible hierarchy · Ultraproducts · Indiscernibles · Forcing · Martin’s axiom · Analytical hierarchy · Determinacy and large cardinals · Structure of the real line · Category and measure Mathematics Subject Classification 03E15 · 03E25 · 03E30 · 03E35 · 03E55 · 01A60 · 01A61 B Adam J. Ostaszewski [email protected] Nicholas H. Bingham [email protected] 1 Mathematics Department, Imperial College, London SW7 2AZ, UK 2 Mathematics Department, London School of Economics, Houghton Street, London WC2A 2AE, UK 123 Set theory and the analyst 3 Contents 1 Introduction ............................................
    [Show full text]
  • Some Challenges for the Philosophy of Set Theory
    Introduction A theorem of Shelah A theorem of Farah A theorem of Magidor and Shelah Conclusion Some challenges for the philosophy of set theory James Cummings CMU 21 March 2012 www.math.cmu.edu/users/jcumming/phil/efi_slides.pdf 1 / 51 Introduction A theorem of Shelah A theorem of Farah A theorem of Magidor and Shelah Conclusion Thesis I: (Really a general thesis about the philosophy of mathematics) A successful philosophy of set theory should be faithful to the mathematical practices of set theorists. In particular such a philosophy will require a close reading of the mathematics produced by set theorists, an understanding of the history of set theory, and an examination of the community of set theorists and its interactions with other mathematical communities. This talk represents an experiment in doing this kind of philosophy. 2 / 51 Introduction A theorem of Shelah A theorem of Farah A theorem of Magidor and Shelah Conclusion Thesis II: Set theory is a branch of mathematics. It happens to be a branch in which issues of independence and consistency lie close to the surface, and in which the tools of logic have proven very powerful, but it is not (or not only) about logic. As in any successful field of mathematics, progress in set theory comes from a dialectic between “internal” developments elaborating the central ideas, and “external” developments in which problems and ideas flow back and forth between set theory and other areas (for example topology, algebra, analysis, the theory of games). 3 / 51 Introduction A theorem of Shelah A theorem of Farah A theorem of Magidor and Shelah Conclusion Thesis III: Modern set theory uses a wide range of methods and discusses a wide range of objects.
    [Show full text]
  • A BRIEF HISTORY of DETERMINACY §1. Introduction
    0001 0002 0003 A BRIEF HISTORY OF DETERMINACY 0004 0005 0006 PAUL B. LARSON 0007 0008 0009 0010 x1. Introduction. Determinacy axioms are statements to the effect that 0011 certain games are determined, in that each player in the game has an optimal 0012 strategy. The commonly accepted axioms for mathematics, the Zermelo{ 0013 Fraenkel axioms with the Axiom of Choice (ZFC; see [Jec03, Kun83]), imply 0014 the determinacy of many games that people actually play. This applies in 0015 particular to many games of perfect information, games in which the 0016 players alternate moves which are known to both players, and the outcome 0017 of the game depends only on this list of moves, and not on chance or other 0018 external factors. Games of perfect information which must end in finitely 0019 many moves are determined. This follows from the work of Ernst Zermelo 0020 [Zer13], D´enesK}onig[K}on27]and L´aszl´oK´almar[Kal1928{29], and also 0021 from the independent work of John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern 0022 (in their 1944 book, reprinted as [vNM04]). 0023 As pointed out by Stanis law Ulam [Ula60], determinacy for games of 0024 perfect information of a fixed finite length is essentially a theorem of logic. 0025 If we let x1,y1,x2,y2,::: ,xn,yn be variables standing for the moves made by 0026 players player I (who plays x1,::: ,xn) and player II (who plays y1,::: ,yn), 0027 and A (consisting of sequences of length 2n) is the set of runs of the game 0028 for which player I wins, the statement 0029 0030 (1) 9x18y1 ::: 9xn8ynhx1; y1; : : : ; xn; yni 2 A 0031 essentially asserts that the first player has a winning strategy in the game, 0032 and its negation, 0033 0034 (2) 8x19y1 ::: 8xn9ynhx1; y1; : : : ; xn; yni 62 A 0035 essentially asserts that the second player has a winning strategy.1 0036 0037 The author is supported in part by NSF grant DMS-0801009.
    [Show full text]
  • SOME WEAK VERSIONS of LARGE CARDINAL AXIOMS Introduction
    ANNALS OF MATttEMATICAL LOGIC 5 (1973) 291- 325. North-Holland Publishing Company SOME WEAK VERSIONS OF LARGE CARDINAL AXIOMS Keith J. DEVLIN* Unive,'sity of Manchester~ Manchester, UK. Received 4 February 1972 Introduction This paper is partly a survey article, collecting together results which have ltitherto only appeared in a very scattered form, and partly a presentation of new results. Verious natural ,veakenings of the familiar large cardinal axioms ': ~, (X)~ ~ are defined and discussed. For com- pleteness and easy reference, a brief discussion of large cardinals of this size is included. Otherwise, the titles of the various sections serve as an adequate description of the paper. We wish to express our gratitude to Dr. F. Rowbottom for supervising tiffs research, and to Dr. R. Laver for several interesting conversations concerning the problems here discussed. * The results in this paper were contained in the author's Doctoral Dissertation submitted to the Univerfity of Bristol in 1971. The author wishes to acknowledg~ the financial support given him by the S¢.ienee Re.~ateh Council for the entire preparation of this paper. 292 /(.,,'./3ev//n, ,Some week vcr~ra o]'/arge mrd/,,m/axiom~ O. Preliminaries We work in ZFC throughout, ano use the usual notation and conven- tions. In particular, cardinals are i~it~al ordinals, K, X, la, ... denote cardinals, and a, 8, "r, ... denote ordinals. If X is a set IXI denotes its cardinality. "not-~" is denoted by '"-~". By a filter D on a set X is meant a filter in the field of all subsets of X. D is uniform if U~ D -~ IUI - IXI.
    [Show full text]
  • July 16, 2010 RAMSEY-LIKE CARDINALS II 1. Introduction The
    July 16, 2010 RAMSEY-LIKE CARDINALS II VICTORIA GITMAN AND P.D. WELCH Abstract. This paper continues the study of the Ramsey-like large cardi- nals introduced in [Git09] and [WS10]. Ramsey-like cardinals are defined by generalizing the characterization of Ramsey cardinals via the existence of el- ementary embeddings. Ultrafilters derived from such embeddings are fully iterable and so it is natural to ask about large cardinal notions asserting the existence of ultrafilters allowing only α-many iterations for some countable or- dinal α. Here we study such α-iterable cardinals. We show that the α-iterable cardinals form a strict hierarchy for α ≤ ω1, that they are downward absolute L to L for α < ω1 , and that the consistency strength of Schindler’s remarkable cardinals is strictly between 1-iterable and 2-iterable cardinals. We show that the strongly Ramsey and super Ramsey cardinals from [Git09] are downward absolute to the core model K. Finally, we use a forcing argument from a strongly Ramsey cardinal to separate the notions of Ramsey and virtually Ramsey cardinals. These were introduced in [WS10] as an upper bound on the consistency strength of the Intermediate Chang’s Conjecture. 1. Introduction The definitions of measurable cardinals and stronger large cardinal notions follow the template of asserting the existence of elementary embeddings j : V → M from the universe of sets to a transitive subclass with that cardinal as the critical point. Many large cardinal notions below a measurable cardinal can be characterized by the existence of elementary embeddings as well. The characterizations of these smaller large cardinals κ follow the template of asserting the existence of elementary embeddings j : M → N with critical point κ from a weak κ-model or κ-model M of set theory to a transitive set.1 A weak κ-model M of set theory is a transitive set of size κ satisfying ZFC− (ZFC without the Powerset Axiom) and having κ ∈ M.
    [Show full text]
  • Measurable Cardinal Wikipedia Contents
    Measurable cardinal Wikipedia Contents 1 Atom (measure theory) 1 1.1 Definition ............................................... 1 1.2 Examples ............................................... 1 1.3 Non-atomic measures ......................................... 1 1.4 See also ................................................ 2 1.5 Notes ................................................. 2 1.6 References ............................................... 2 2 Axiom of determinacy 3 2.1 Types of game that are determined .................................. 3 2.2 Incompatibility of the axiom of determinacy with the axiom of choice ................ 3 2.3 Infinite logic and the axiom of determinacy .............................. 4 2.4 Large cardinals and the axiom of determinacy ............................ 4 2.5 See also ................................................ 4 2.6 References ............................................... 5 2.7 Further reading ............................................ 5 3 Cardinal number 6 3.1 History ................................................. 6 3.2 Motivation .............................................. 8 3.3 Formal definition ........................................... 9 3.4 Cardinal arithmetic .......................................... 10 3.4.1 Successor cardinal ...................................... 10 3.4.2 Cardinal addition ....................................... 10 3.4.3 Cardinal multiplication .................................... 11 3.4.4 Cardinal exponentiation ................................... 11 3.5
    [Show full text]