Life After Moral Error Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Life After Moral Error Theory What to do when the world doesn’t play along: Life after moral error theory JESSICA ISSEROW A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of The Australian National University August 2017 © Jessica Isserow 2017 Statement This thesis is solely the work of its author. No part of it has previously been submit- ted for any degree, or is currently being submitted for any other degree. To the best of my knowledge, any help received in preparing this thesis, and all sources used, have been duly acknowledged. JESSICA ISSEROW 15th August, 2017 Acknowledgements I had the pleasure and good fortune of writing my PhD at the philosophy depart- ment at the Australian National University, a graduate student’s paradise. I was also fortunate to have had an all-star supervisory panel, whose diversity helped me to see issues from different philosophical perspectives. I first want to thank the chair of my panel, Benjamin Fraser, for being incredibly supportive over the years, and for providing insightful comments, raising important challenges and making valuable suggestions. I am also immensely grateful to Daniel Nolan, who was incredibly gen- erous with his time, and whose feedback was always constructive and edifying. I would like to thank Kim Sterelny for his help, encouragement, and for making my time at the ANU so philosophically rewarding. I am grateful to Nic Southwood for providing straight and honest feedback, acknowledging when my work was up to scratch and having a laugh with me whenever it wasn’t. I am also thankful to those at the ANU who made my time there so enjoyable and philosophically stimulating. My work on this thesis has benefitted greatly from dis- cussions with Clare Due, Melissa Ebbers, Edward Elliott David Kalkman, Colin Klein, Christopher Lean, Leon Leontyev, Eric Llamas, Alexander Sandgren, and Lachlan Umbers. Special thanks is owed to Edward Elliott, who was the preview au- dience for all of the presentations I have given on this work. I also wish to thank au- diences at the ANU, at annual meetings of the Australasian Association of Philosophy, and many conferences at Kioloa. I spent most of the final year of my PhD at the University of Leeds, and I will be forever grateful to the philosophers there for their help and kindness. (And, of course, for the formidable karaoke sessions as well.) I am especially grateful to Daniel Elstein, Ulrike Heuer, Gerald Lang, Pekka Värynyen, and Jack Woods for meeting with me to discuss my research, as well as Richard Rowland, who met with me while visiting there. I should also register my appreciation for the funding that I received. This re- search was supported by an Australian Government Research Training Program (RTP) Scholarship. On a more personal note, I would like to thank (all four of) my parents, whose love and support has been unwavering throughout the years. They have always en- couraged me to pursue my dreams, and for that I am eternally grateful. Finally, I would like to thank Edward Elliott for his love, for believing in me, and for being the best friend that I’ve ever had. Abstract This work addresses the ‘what next?’ question for moral discourse, which concerns the best choice of action given the truth of the moral error theory. The moral error theory comprises two claims: (i) that moral discourse is used assertorically, and (ii) that moral assertions systematically fail to state truths. The upshot of the moral error theory is that nothing is really right or wrong—indeed, that the very idea of things being right or wrong is fundamentally mistaken. And yet, I argue, there are strong ar- guments in favour of moral error theory. With such far-reaching implications, we’d do well to have some guidance regarding what we ought to do upon coming to be- lieve that the moral error theory is true. In the first part of this work, I evaluate the answers to the ‘what next?’ question that have been proposed in the current literature. These include a systematic revision of our moral concepts (revisionism), preserving moral language in the spirit of a use- ful fiction (fictionalism), ridding ourselves of moral discourse entirely (abolitionism), and making do with our current erroneous moral discourse (conservationism). I ar- gue that none of the first three proposals offer us an entirely satisfactory answer to the ‘what next?’ question. Conservationism is the most promising solution still on the table. However, conservationism is yet to be fully developed. In the second part of this work, I develop and motivate my own version of conservationism, and show that it is the most attractive response to the ‘what next?’ question; one that is capable of se- curing the many desirable practical goods that our moral practices provide. This page intentionally left blank Contents Introduction: error theories and the ‘what next?’ question 1 §I. Error Theories 4 §II. Error Theories in philosophy 10 §IIa. The conceptual stage 10 §IIb. The ontological stage 13 §IIc. Controversy 13 §III. Answering the WNQ 16 §IV. Game Plan 19 1. (Almost) Everything You’ve Ever Wanted to Know About Moral Error Theory 22 §1.1 Moral error theory in meta-ethics 23 §1.1.1 Cognitivism & Non-cognitivism, Success & Error 23 §1.1.2 The truth-conditions of moral judgments 25 §1.1.3 Moral error theory in meta-ethics: a summary 26 §1.2 Moral error theory: a general overview 27 §1.2.1 A selective history 28 §1.2.2 The many roads to error 29 §1.3 Moral facts: they’re not here, they’re queer 31 §1.3.1 Mackie’s many arguments for moral error theory 32 §1.3.2 Mackie’s metaphysical argument from queerness 34 §1.3.3 Olson’s development 39 §1.3.4 The queerness of the queerness charge 43 §1.4 The trouble with categorical reasons 45 §1.4.1 Reasons and rationality 45 §1.4.2 Joyce’s conceptual claim 49 §1.4.3 Joyce’s ontological claim 52 §1.5 Moral Error Theory: summing up 56 2. What is the ‘what next?’ question for moral discourse? 57 §2.1 Can the WNQ for moral discourse be a normative question? 58 §2.1.1 The over-generalisation problem for epistemic reasons 59 §2.1.2 The over-generalisation problem for all normative reasons 63 §2.1.3 The WNQ: summing up 66 §2.2 To whom is the WNQ for moral discourse addressed? 68 §2.3 Motivating the project 71 §2.3.1 The devastating result of the moral error theory 72 §2.3.2 Doom and gloom? 74 §2.3.3 Morality (huh): what is it good for? 77 §2.3.4 The tension: why we need to answer the WNQ 82 §2.4 Answers to the WNQ for moral discourse 84 §2.4.1 Abolitionism 84 §2.4.2 Revisionism 85 §2.4.3 Fictionalism 86 §2.4.4 Conservationism 86 §2.4.5 Why not propagandism? 87 §2.4.6 Evaluating answers to the WNQ 88 §2.5 Philosophical Dividends 89 §2.6 Take away 91 3. Moral Abolitionism 93 §3.1 What is moral Abolitionism? 94 §3.1.1 Motivation 94 §3.1.2 Scope 96 §3.1.3 A new hope? 97 §3.1.4 A caveat 97 §3.2 The argument from conflict 98 §3.2.1 Morality and interpersonal conflict 99 §3.2.2 The argument from conflict: an assessment 101 §3.3 The argument from history 105 §3.3.1 The role of morality 107 §3.3.2 Other culprits 109 §3.3.3 Minimising the misuse of morality 115 §3.4 A feasibility worry 121 §3.5 Where does moral abolitionism go wrong? 124 4. Revisionism 126 §4.1 How I’m going to go about things 127 §4.2 Concepts: what they are and how they change 128 §4.2.1 Concepts 129 §4.2.2 Conceptual change 133 §4.2.3 Some qualifications 137 §4.2.4 Reformists and Revisionists 139 §4.3 The case for revisionism 140 §4.3.1 The reformist strategy 140 §4.3.2 Grist for the revisionist’s mill 145 §4.4 Against schmorality 147 §4.4.1 Against the letter of schmorality 147 §4.4.2 Moral concepts and scientific concepts: some disanalogies 150 §4.4.3 Against the spirit of schmorality 157 §4.5 Revisionism: general lessons 160 5. Moral Fictionalism 162 §5.1 Fictionalism: a general overview 163 §5.1.1 What is fictionalism? 163 §5.1.2 Prefix fictionalism and preface fictionalism 166 §5.1.3 Hermeneutic fictionalism and revolutionary fictionalism 167 §5.2 Moral Fictionalism 169 §5.2.1 Joyce’s moral fictionalism 169 §5.2.2 Nolan, Restall, and West’s moral fictionalism 171 §5.3 The case against moral fictionalism 172 §5.3.1 An acceptance-transfer problem 173 §5.3.2 A validity problem 175 §5.3.3 A problem with preserving moral disagreement 177 §5.3.4 The case against moral fictionalism: summing up 180 §5.4 The real case against moral fictionalism 180 §5.4.1 Horn 1: the slip into belief 181 §5.4.2 Horn 2: the shortcomings of moral make-belief 190 §5.4.3 The shortcomings of fictional moral belief 196 §5.5 Moral Fictionalism: verdict and lessons 201 6. Conservationism: offense 204 §6.1 What is conservationism? 205 §6.1.1 Olson’s conservationism 207 §6.1.2 Some gaps in Olson’s proposal 209 §6.2 A new conservationism 210 §6.2.1 Believing that p and that ¬p 212 §6.2.2 Beliefs and contexts 217 §6.2.3 A justification for preserving our false moral beliefs 224 7.
Recommended publications
  • Towards a New Theory of Modal Fictionalism
    Dombrovszki, A.: Towards a New Theory of Modal Fictionalism. In: Ostium, roč. 13, 2017, č. 4. Abstract: In our everyday discourse, most of us use modal statements to express possibility, necessity, or contingency. Logicians, linguists, and philosophers of language tend to use the possible world discourse to analyse the semantics of this kind of sentences. There is a disadvantage of this method: in the usual Quinean meta-ontology it commits the users to the existence of possible worlds. Even though there are many theories on metaphysics of these possible worlds, I will focus on the fictionalist approach, which aims to suspend the undesired ontological commitment. Therefore it is an anti-realist theory. The fictionalist strategy is based on the idea that according to our common- sense ontology, fictions and fictional entities do not exist, and one can treat the possible world discourse as a fiction, and the possible worlds as fictional entities. However, in the last two decades, realist theories about fictions and fictional entities have arisen, especially the abstract artefact theory. In this paper I try to revise the fictionalist approach to modality by keeping the main idea that possible worlds are fictional entities, while accepting that fictional entities are abstract artefacts. The result is a new realist theory of modal fictionalism. Keywords: analytic philosophy, metaphysics, philosophy of language, fictionalism, modality, possible worlds The aim of this paper is to provide a revised version of the so-called fictionalist approach to modality.[1] Proponents of this view hold that realist theories about possible worlds, and therefore the whole possible world discourse is just a useful fiction, and – at least I suppose that – possible worlds are fictional entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Fictionalism and the Incompleteness Problem
    Synthese DOI 10.1007/s11229-015-1000-1 Fictionalism and the incompleteness problem Lukas Skiba1 Received: 27 April 2015 / Accepted: 18 December 2015 © The Author(s) 2016. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract Modal fictionalists face a problem that arises due to their possible-world story being incomplete in the sense that certain relevant claims are neither true nor false according to it. It has recently been suggested that this incompleteness prob- lem generalises to other brands of fictionalism, such as fictionalism about composite or mathematical objects. In this paper, I argue that these fictionalist positions are particularly threatened by a generalised incompleteness problem since they cannot emulate the modal fictionalists’ most attractive response. I then defend mathematical and compositional fictionalism by showing that the reasons for which the incomplete- ness problem has been thought to affect them are mistaken. This leads to the question of whether there are other fictionalist positions to which the problem does in fact generalise. I give a general account of the features of a fictionalist position that gen- erate the incompleteness problem and argue that whenever a fictionalist position does exemplify these features then the problem can be addressed in analogy to the modal fictionalists’ preferred response. Keywords Fictionalism · Possible worlds · Mathematical objects · Composite objects · Fictional incompleteness 1 Modal fictionalism and the incompleteness problem Modal realists endorse all instances of the following schema (R-Mod) φ ↔[φ]T where φ is an ordinary modal sentence and [φ]T is φ’s regimentation in the realists’ B Lukas Skiba [email protected] 1 Faculty of Philosophy, University of Cambridge, Sidgwick Avenue, Cambridge CB3 9DA, UK 123 Synthese possible-world language.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysical Accounts of Modality
    Metaphysical accounts of modality A comparative evaluation of Lewisian and neo-Aristotelian modal metaphysics David Chua Philosophy honours thesis Supervisor: Nicholas J.J. Smith The University of Sydney 12|10|2012 Metaphysical accounts of modality: An evaluation of Lewisian and neo-Aristotelian modal metaphysics ~Table of Contents ~ Introduction .................................................................................................. 3 1 Evaluating David Lewis’ genuine modal realism (GMR) ......................... 7 I. A plenitude of possibilities. ........................................................................................... 9 II. Not that ontologically crazy. ...................................................................................... 10 III. Genuine reduction. .................................................................................................... 10 1.1 GMR requires revision of moral beliefs ................................................... 12 I. Can egocentric desires ground morality? .................................................................... 13 II. GMR still generates moral dilemmas. ....................................................................... 14 III. Duplicate worlds to the rescue? ............................................................................... 20 IV. Conclusion .................................................................................................................. 22 1.2 GMR gives unsatisfactory truthmakers for de re modality ..................
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy in Practice Volume 12 — Spring 2018
    Philosophy in Practice Volume 12 — Spring 2018 California State uniVerSity, loS angeleS Department of philoSophy Philosophy in Practice VOLUME 12 – SPRING 2018 Cover Art: Photo of mural at Union Station, Los Angeles © Copyright 2018 by CSULA Philosophy Department. All rights reserved. Except for brief quotations in a review as permitted under the United States Copyright Act of 1976, no part of this publication may be reproduced or distributed in any form or by any means, or stored in a data base or retrieval system, without the prior written permission of the publisher. Individual copyright reverts to the authors upon further publication of their articles. CONTENTS Acknowledgments ..................................iv Faculty ...........................................v Professor Spotlight: Mark Balaguer ...................vii Articles: Persistent Beliefs Troy Polidori ............................... 1 Modal Fictionalism and the Problem of Incompleteness David Fonth ............................... 16 Logical Pluralism and its Collapse Problems Taylor A. Dunn ............................ 36 The Low-Entropy Past Still Requires Explanation Katelyn Rogers ............................ 46 Anarchy and Disclosure Bryan Knittle .............................. 59 Introspection and Cognitive Phenomenology Drew Patterson ............................ 81 An Aristotelian Approach to Quantum Mechanics Gil Sanders ................................94 Privacy: A Last Resort Fernando Cierra ...........................107 Simone de Beauvoir: Una Cuenta Para El
    [Show full text]
  • Fictionalism in Metaphysics Caddick Bourne Manuscript
    The University of Manchester Research Fictionalism in metaphysics DOI: 10.4324/9780415249126-N130-1 Document Version Accepted author manuscript Link to publication record in Manchester Research Explorer Citation for published version (APA): Caddick Bourne, E. (2018). Fictionalism in metaphysics. Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780415249126-N130- 1 Citing this paper Please note that where the full-text provided on Manchester Research Explorer is the Author Accepted Manuscript or Proof version this may differ from the final Published version. If citing, it is advised that you check and use the publisher's definitive version. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the Research Explorer are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Takedown policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please refer to the University of Manchester’s Takedown Procedures [http://man.ac.uk/04Y6Bo] or contact [email protected] providing relevant details, so we can investigate your claim. Download date:02. Oct. 2021 Fictionalism in Metaphysics Emily Caddick Bourne This is a draft of an entry published in the Fall/Winter 2018 update of the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy online, at https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/fictionalism-in- metaphysics/v-1. Keywords Fictionalism; Metaphysics; Fiction; Ontology; Pretence; Modality Article Summary Fictionalism proposes that a certain discourse – such as talk about possible worlds, or mathematical talk – is useful, perhaps even indispensable for theoretical purposes, but should not be taken as true.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Be an Intellectually Humble Philosopher?
    Why Be an Intellectually Humble Philosopher? Moti Mizrahi Florida Institute of Technology Abstract: In this paper, I sketch an answer to the question “Why be an intellectually humble philosopher?” I argue that, as far as philosophical argumentation is concerned, the historical record of Western Philosophy provides a straightforward answer to this question. That is, the historical record of philosophical argumentation, which is a track record that is marked by an abundance of alternative theories and serious problems for those theories, can teach us important lessons about the limits of philosophical argumentation. These lessons, in turn, show why philosophers should argue with humility. Keywords: intellectual humility; metaphilosophy; philosophical argumentation; virtue argumentation theory; virtue epistemology 1. Introduction In the introduction to Representation and Reality, Hilary Putnam writes: In this book I shall be arguing that the computer analogy, call it the “computational view of the mind,” or “functionalism,” or what you will, does not after all answer the question we philosophers (along with many cognitive scientists) want to answer, the question “What is the nature of mental states?” I am, thus, as I have done on more than one occasion, criticizing a view I myself earlier advanced. Strangely enough, there are philosophers who criticize me for doing this. The fact that I change my mind in philosophy has been viewed as a character defect (Putnam 1991, xi, emphasis added). Putnam (1991, xii) goes on to say that, for him, Rudolf “Carnap is still the outstanding example of a human being who puts the search for truth higher than personal vanity.” Contrary to what appears to be the view of Putnam’s critics, intellectual humility is usually considered, not a character defect, but rather a desirable character trait—a virtue—in introductory textbooks of logic and critical thinking.
    [Show full text]
  • Modal Fictionalism and Modal Instrumentalism
    ARTICLES STATE Organon F 22 (4) 2015: 439-460 Modal Fictionalism and Modal Instrumentalism ANTHONY DARDIS Department of Philosophy. Hofstra University Hempstead. NY – 11549-1150. USA [email protected] RECEIVED: 30-04-2015 ACCEPTED: 23-07-2015 1. Introduction The Author. Journal compilationInstitute of Philosophy SAS A NTHONY D ARDIS 2. The Brock-Rosen argument M ODAL F ICTIONALISM AND M ODAL I NSTRUMENTALISM xTxDx xTxDx A NTHONY D ARDIS 2.1. Reflexive fictionalism 2.2. Denying (1): no worlds at worlds M ODAL F ICTIONALISM AND M ODAL I NSTRUMENTALISM 2.2.1. The letter of fictionalism wxxw x in 2.2.2. Advanced modalizing A NTHONY D ARDIS non-trivial M ODAL F ICTIONALISM AND M ODAL I NSTRUMENTALISM 2.2.3. Plural evaluation not 2.3. “Strong” fictionalism A NTHONY D ARDIS MF pp* p p*p MF2 pp MF MF2 M ODAL F ICTIONALISM AND M ODAL I NSTRUMENTALISM Wrong meanings? A NTHONY D ARDIS Loss of problem? M ODAL F ICTIONALISM AND M ODAL I NSTRUMENTALISM MF 2.4.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Fictionalism
    Moral Fictionalism Daniel Nolan (Syracuse University) Greg Restall (University of Melbourne) Caroline West (University of Sydney) Draft only. Please do not cite without permission. Introduction What would morality have to be like in order to answer to our everyday moral concepts? What are we committed to when we make moral claims such as “female infibulation is wrong”; or “we ought give money to famine relief”; or “we have a duty to not to harm others”, and when we go on to argue about these sorts of claims? It has seemed to many—and it seems plausible to us— that when we assert and argue about things such as these we presuppose at least the following. First, that there is a realm of moral facts (in a non-technical sense of ‘facts’); facts in virtue of which claims like “female infibulation is wrong” are true and claims like “acts of senseless cruelty are right” are false. When we argue about whether female infibulation is wrong, for example, we seem to presuppose that that there is a fact of the matter about the rightness or wrongness of female infibulation about which we can form beliefs and which makes at most one of the disagreeing parties right. Furthermore, we suppose that the rightness or wrongness of female infibulation is something that we can discover. The assumption that there is a discoverable fact about the rightness or wrongness of female infibulation, for example, which our moral beliefs can get right or wrong, explains the purpose and nature of ordinary moral debate. Second, we take these facts to be objective facts—the rightness or wrongness of female infibulation, for example, doesn’t depend on what we happen to think or feel.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography on Modality and Possible Worlds
    Bibliography on Modality and Possible Worlds Karen Bennett and Ted Sider (Most abstracts taken from the Philosophers Index and PhilPapers) Spring, 2014 Adams, Robert Merrihew (1974). “Theories of Actuality.” Noûs 8: 211–31. Reprinted in Loux 1979: 190–209. — (1981). “Actualism and Thisness.” Synthese 49: 3–41. The thesis of this essay is that all possibilities are purely qualitative ex- cept insofar as they involve individuals that actually exist. This thesis is expounded and defended, and some of its implications for modality are developed; the chief implication is that what modal facts “de re” there are depends on what individuals actually exist. Armstrong, David M. (1989). A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility. New York: Cambridge University Press. Ayer, Alfred Jules (1936). Language, Truth and Logic. London: Victor Gollancz Ltd, 1946. 2nd edition. Bacon, Andrew (2013). “Quanti cational Logic and Empty Names.” Philoso- phers’ Imprint 13(24). The result of combining classical quanti cational logic with modal logic proves necessitism – the claim that necessarily everything is necessarily identical to something. This problem is reected in the purely quanti - cational theory by theorems such as $ exists xt = x$; it is a theorem, for example, that something is identical 1 to Timothy Williamson. The standard way to avoid these consequences is to weaken the theory of quanti cation to a certain kind of free logic. However, it has often been noted that in order to specify the truth con- ditions of certain sentences involving constants or variables that don’t denote, one has to apparently quantify over things that are not identi- cal to anything.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Metaphysics and Ontology
    Volume 1 (2021) Structure Journal of Metaphysics and Ontology Structure Journal of Metaphysics and Ontology Table of Contents Determining the Truth-Value of Mixed Predicates Under Composite Correspondence............................................... 1 By Michelle Yue Fictionalist Modal Expressivism: An Alternative Approach ................................................................................................... 9 By Xinran Jiang Being as Ground: On the Relevance of Paraconsistent Formal Answers to Heidegger’s Question of Being ..... 34 By Lucas Janz Sameness of Spell: Notation and Identity in the Ontology of Literature ........................................................................ 65 By Salvador Chinchilla Understanding Resistance to Racial Equality: The Role of Social Structures in Colorblind Racism ................... 76 By Jake Wasinger Note from the Editors Structure was launched this year, and we are very pleased to have received so many excellent submissions on such varied questions in metaphysics and ontology, which we loosely define as the study of reality and the study of being. Topics range from how we are to understand contemporary modal concepts metaphysically to assessing the relevance of answers to Heidegger’s question of being that use paraconsistent logic. The questions range from how and in which ways racism is present in our societies to how truth-values can be determined under Gila Sher’s composite correspondence theory of truth. We hope that this journal will continue to be a platform for the meeting of ideas from such diverse contexts. We are especially grateful to all those who participated in blind review for this journal. Thank you to Hank Blackburn, Nicko Boylan, Elisabeth Holmes, Neal Going, Ryan Leventhal, Bryce Liquerman, Mason Liddell, and Grace Rust for volunteering your time and effort to reading and evaluating submissions.
    [Show full text]
  • Possible Worlds and Ideology
    Possible Worlds and Ideology by Tom Constant A thesis submitted to Cardiff University in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy SCHOOL OF ENGLISH, COMMUNICATION AND PHILOSOPHY CARDIFF UNIVERSITY APRIL 2017 i Summary The broad aim of this thesis is to explore fruitful connections between ideology theory and the philosophy of possible worlds (PW). Ideologies are full of modal concepts, such as possibility, potential, necessity, essence, contingency and accident. Typically, PWs are articulated for the analysis and illumination of modal concepts. That naturally suggests a method for theorising ideologica l modality, utilising PW theory . The specific conclusions of the thesis proffer a number of original contributions t o knowledge: 1) PWs should only be used for explication and not as (intrinsic) 1 evidence or criteria o f assessment in ideology theory. The estimation of (e.g.) utopian possibilities, human essences and freedoms must be determined by extrinsic criteria. PWs can serve only as a window or means of expression but not as a set of evaluative premises . 2) For this purpose, a modified version of Lewisian genuine realism (GR), with its device of counterpart theory, is the best approach; the alternative theories risk constricting possibilities or smuggling in assumptions that ought to be object s of analysis in ideology theory . Th is is instructive, since ideology theorists are prone to pick and choose favoured aspects of modal philosophy without further argument. 3) Conclusions (1) and (2) suggest the adoption of GR or fictionalist GR . Overall, the actualist options are less adequate. Fictionalism, by contrast, is a worthwhile contender, but it too presents comparative weaknesses which reinforce GR’s standing as a potent challenger to the modal metaphysician.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics: Modal Objectivity
    Justin Clarke-Doane 712b Philosophy Hall Phone: 212-854-3246 [email protected] Modal Objectivity PHIL G9515 Spring 2015 Tuesday 12:10-2 Description: This is a course on meta-modality – the epistemology, metaphysics, and semantics of modal discourse. We will cover some familiar topics, including the relationship between conceivability and possibility, the prospects for reduction, and possible worlds semantics. However, we will also spend time in less charted waters – on the absoluteness, determinacy, and “metaphysical distinction” of metaphysical necessity and related notions. Attention will be paid to interactions between problems in meta-modality, and problems in the philosophies of logic and mathematics. Requirements: Regular attendance, class participation, and a term paper (≈ 20 pages), due May 4. Week Topic Literature Introduction to Modal Metaphysics 1/20 Background and Overview R: Kripke [1980] Lecture III, Melia [2003] Ch. I, Quine [1952], Soames [2005], Sec. VII O: Ballarin [2010], Carnap [1947], Garson [2014], Lewis [1914], Knuuttila [2013], Kment [2012] Realism 1/27 Cognitivism R: Blackburn [1986] O: Brandom [2008], Ch. IV, Craig [1985], Hale and Wright [1989], Price [2008], Sellars [1958], Ryle [1950/1971], Shalkowski [2008], Thomasson [2007], Wittgenstein [1998], Wright [1986]. 2/3 Independence R: Sidelle [1989] selections. O: Hale [2004], Sidelle [2009], Yablo [1992], Putnam [1986] & [1990] 2/10 Ideology R: Field [1989] selections. O: Fine [2003b], Forbes [1989], Melia [2003], Nolan [2011b], Rosen [1990] & [1993] 2/17 Ontology I: Reduction R: Lewis [1986], Ch. I O: Benacerraf [1965], Field [1989] selections, Melia, Ch. V, Menzel [2014], Sec. 2.1 2/24 Ontology II: Primitivism R: Melia [2003] VI & VII, Plantinga [1976] selections.
    [Show full text]