Evolutionism and Holism: Two Different Paradigms for the Phenomenon of Biological Evolution
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Foucault's Darwinian Genealogy
genealogy Article Foucault’s Darwinian Genealogy Marco Solinas Political Philosophy, University of Florence and Deutsches Institut Florenz, Via dei Pecori 1, 50123 Florence, Italy; [email protected] Academic Editor: Philip Kretsedemas Received: 10 March 2017; Accepted: 16 May 2017; Published: 23 May 2017 Abstract: This paper outlines Darwin’s theory of descent with modification in order to show that it is genealogical in a narrow sense, and that from this point of view, it can be understood as one of the basic models and sources—also indirectly via Nietzsche—of Foucault’s conception of genealogy. Therefore, this essay aims to overcome the impression of a strong opposition to Darwin that arises from Foucault’s critique of the “evolutionistic” research of “origin”—understood as Ursprung and not as Entstehung. By highlighting Darwin’s interpretation of the principles of extinction, divergence of character, and of the many complex contingencies and slight modifications in the becoming of species, this essay shows how his genealogical framework demonstrates an affinity, even if only partially, with Foucault’s genealogy. Keywords: Darwin; Foucault; genealogy; natural genealogies; teleology; evolution; extinction; origin; Entstehung; rudimentary organs “Our classifications will come to be, as far as they can be so made, genealogies; and will then truly give what may be called the plan of creation. The rules for classifying will no doubt become simpler when we have a definite object in view. We possess no pedigrees or armorial bearings; and we have to discover and trace the many diverging lines of descent in our natural genealogies, by characters of any kind which have long been inherited. -
Evolutionary Epistemology in James' Pragmatism J
35 THE ORIGIN OF AN INQUIRY: EVOLUTIONARY EPISTEMOLOGY IN JAMES' PRAGMATISM J. Ellis Perry IV University of Massachusetts at Dartmouth "Much struck." That was Darwin's way of saying that something he observed fascinated him, arrested his attention, surprised or puzzled him. The words "much struck" riddle the pages of bothhis Voyage ofthe Beagle and his The Origin of Species, and their appearance should alert the reader that Darwin was saying something important. Most of the time, the reader caninfer that something Darwin had observed was at variance with what he had expected, and that his fai th in some alleged law or general principle hadbeen shaken, and this happened repeat edly throughout his five year sojourn on the H.M.S. Beagle. The "irritation" of his doubting the theretofore necessary truths of natu ral history was Darwin's stimulus to inquiry, to creative and thor oughly original abductions. "The influence of Darwinupon philosophy resides inhis ha ving conquered the phenomena of life for the principle of transi tion, and thereby freed the new logic for application to mind and morals and life" (Dewey p. 1). While it would be an odd fellow who would disagree with the claim of Dewey and others that the American pragmatist philosophers were to no small extent influenced by the Darwinian corpus,! few have been willing to make the case for Darwin's influence on the pragmatic philosophy of William James. Philip Wiener, in his well known work, reports that Thanks to Professor Perry's remarks in his definitive work on James, "the influence of Darwin was both early and profound, and its effects crop up in unex pected quarters." Perry is a senior at the University of Massachusetts at Dartmoltth. -
Our Knowledge of the External World As a Field for Scientific Method In
Our Knowledge of the External World as a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy By Bertrand Russell 1 PREFACE The following lectures[1] are an attempt to show, by means of examples, the nature, capacity, and limitations of the logical-analytic method in philosophy. This method, of which the first complete example is to be found in the writings of Frege, has gradually, in the course of actual research, increasingly forced itself upon me as something perfectly definite, capable of embodiment in maxims, and adequate, in all branches of philosophy, to yield whatever objective scientific knowledge it is possible to obtain. Most of the methods hitherto practised have professed to lead to more ambitious results than any that logical analysis can claim to reach, but unfortunately these results have always been such as many competent philosophers considered inadmissible. Regarded merely as hypotheses and as aids to imagination, the great systems of the past serve a very useful purpose, and are abundantly worthy of study. But something different is required if philosophy is to become a science, and to aim at results independent of the tastes and temperament of the philosopher who advocates them. In what follows, I have endeavoured to show, however imperfectly, the way by which I believe that this desideratum is to be found. [1] Delivered as Lowell Lectures in Boston, in March and April 1914. The central problem by which I have sought to illustrate method is the problem of the relation between the crude data of sense and the space, 2 time, and matter of mathematical physics. -
PRAGMATISM AS a PHILOSOPHY of ACTION (Paper Presented at the First Nordic Pragmatism Conference, Helsinki, Finland, June 2008)
1 PRAGMATISM AS A PHILOSOPHY OF ACTION (Paper presented at the First Nordic Pragmatism Conference, Helsinki, Finland, June 2008) Erkki Kilpinen University of Helsinki When I gave the doctrine of pragmatism the name it bears, – and a doctrine of vital significance it is, – I derived the name by which I christened it from pragma, – behaviour – in order that it should be understood that the doctrine is that the only real significance of a general term lies in the general behaviour which it implies. Charles S. Peirce, May 1912 cited by Eisele (1987:95).1 Introduction: Action ahead of knowledge on pragmatism’s philosophical agenda Although the very founder of the pragmatic movement is adamant that this philosophy is inherently related to action – or behaviour as Peirce laconically says here – philosophers have been curiously reluctant to recognize this. Of course one finds in the literature comments about how pragmatists often talk about action, and some commentators feel that they talk about it too often, at the expense of traditional philosophical problems. To see this is not yet, however, to see the essential pragmatist point; in what sense they talk about action. Their usage of this term and the underlying idea differ from what is customary in other philosophical approaches. Pragmatism namely approaches all theoretical and philosophical problems as problems that in final analysis are related to action. In mainstream philosophy, both in its positivist-analytic and phenomenological versions, action is a contingent empirical phenomenon demanding an explanation. In pragmatism, action is a universal phenomenon which in itself begs no explanation but rather makes the starting point for explanations. -
Comment the Communication Strategies of Neocreationism Between the United States and Europe
SISSA – International School for Advanced Studies Journal of Science Communication ISSN 1824 – 2049 http://jcom.sissa.it/ Comment The communication strategies of neocreationism between the United States and Europe Astrid Pizzo In their essay which appeared in 1972 in Models in Paleobiology , Stephen Jay Gould and Niles Eldredge, introducing the theory of punctuated equilibrium, stressed the fact that no scientific theory develops as a simple and logical extension of facts and of patiently recorded observations, and that the particular vision of the world that the scientist adheres to is able to influence, even unconsciously, the way in which data are collected, selected and then interpreted. Scientists, being aware of the existence of an intrinsic problem of prejudice in their scientific research activity, know that, in order to produce original and innovative ideas, it is fundamental to try to revolutionise their research image, to look at reality in a new light, to read data with alternative viewpoints. According to the American philosopher Robert Pennock 1,2, creationists ignore this aspect completely: they look to the Sacred Scriptures to find answers on the origin of the world and of life, and then try to interpret the empirical evidence so that it fits the scriptures. However, American creationism has changed radically in recent decades. Unlike creationists in the strict sense of the word, who use what is said in the Bible explicitly, at times even literally, to attack the theory of evolution, the advocates of Intelligent Design, who opened their season in the Seventies with the publication of Scientific Creationism by Henry Morris 3, do not adopt a stance of direct opposition to evolutionism, but try to work alongside it and to make use of scientific method to find the evidence of the divine hand in nature. -
By Jacques Loeb [1]
Published on The Embryo Project Encyclopedia (https://embryo.asu.edu) The Mechanistic Conception of Life (1912), by Jacques Loeb [1] By: Elliott, Steve Keywords: Mechanism [2] Jacques Loeb [3] published The Mechanistic Conception of Life in 1912. Loeb’s goal for the book was to further disseminate his explanations of organic processes—such as embryonic development and organisms’ orientations to their environments—which relied on physics and chemistry. Loeb also wanted to provide an alternative explanatory framework to vitalism [4] and what he called romantic evolutionism [5], then both widespread. Loeb mined his work on tropisms [6] and artificial parthenogenesis [7], both of which he considered central to biology, to show that physicochemical explanations accounted for some of the most perplexing organic phenomena. Thus, for those processes, anyone who appealed to vitalism [4] or romantic evolutionism [5] offered only impotent explanations. The Mechanistic Conception of Life established Loeb’s widespread reputation as a mechanist, both to the public and to generations of biologists. In The Mechanistic Conception of Life ten popular lectures were presented, each originally published elsewhere beginning in 1893. The University of Chicago Press [8] published the first edition in 1912. In 1964 Donald Fleming [9] edited a second edition through the Harvard University Press [10]. Fleming’s edition included his biography of Loeb as well as notes appended to each essay relating its contents to contemporary biology. In the opening and closing essays, Loeb discussed what biologists studied and the nature of their explanations. In the first essay, the book’s title piece, Loeb promulgated two principles that ground biology, make it a rigorous discipline, and by which biologists explain phenomena. -
AR Wallace's Approach
View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Apollo Volume 5, No. 4 16 Evolutionism Combined with Spiritualism: A. R. Wallace’s Approach ∗ Li LIU Peking University Abstract: A. R. Wallace was the co-founder of the theory of natural selection and a solid supporter of Darwin, but he combined evolutionism with spiritualism, and tried to understand human evolution and evolutionary ethics with a spiritualistic teleology. This teleological version is a typical example of non-Darwinian evolutionism , which was rooted in the ideology of Victorian progressionism, and was used to avoid the materialism implicated in Darwinism. Through investigating Wallace's approach, we may realize how progressionism had worked as the bridge between science and religion in Victorian Age. Key Words: A. R. Wallace, evolutionism, spiritualism, Victorian progressionism ∗ Department of Philosophy, Peking University, Beijing, 100871, China. E-mail: [email protected] Journal of Cambridge Studies 17 1. INTRODUCTION Alfred Russel Wallace and Charles Robert Darwin independently discovered the principle of natural selection and their articles were announced to scientific community by a joint publication, on 1st July 1858. It’s the starting point of the Darwinian revolution or as Peter Bowler put in his book, “the non-Darwinian revolution”. Stimulated by Wallace, Darwin finally finished and then published his Origin of Species, and got “the whole credit for one of the most liberating advances in scientific thought”, as Wallace “agreed of his own free will to play moon to Darwin’s sun.”1 Considered as a Darwinist, Wallace positively defended Darwinism in his time, and published a book named Darwinism (1889). -
Essay on Robert Brandom, Making It Explicit Daniel Dennett July 31, 2006
Essay on Robert Brandom, Making it Explicit Daniel Dennett July 31, 2006 The Evolution of AWhy?@ 1. The descent of content. Which way is up? I have recently completed the bracingBand long overdueBexperience of reading Making it Explicit, and trying to superimpose my own views on it to see where the disagreements stand out. Mainly, there is agreement. Claim after claim, page after page, I find myself agreeing wholeheartedly with Brandom, and this is not just on matters about which philosophers in general agree. Brandom and I are on the same page about many issues that divide the profession. Moreover, on a few points where Brandom explicitly objects to positions I have maintained, I think he is, in the main, right, and I will acknowledge this in more detail below. What then is left to argue about? There is a fundamental difference of direction in our work. But I will try to show that our residual disagreementsBwhich at first make us appear poles apart on some very central thesesBmight quite easily be nudged into consonance if Brandom can take on what I view as a few friendly amendments. We both learned a lesson from Wilfrid Sellars that still hasn=t sunk in with many of our colleagues. I quote, not for the first time, what I consider to be the pithiest expression of it in Sellars: My solution is that A>. .= means - - -@ is the core of a unique mode of discourse which is as distinct from the description and explanation of empirical fact, as is the language of prescription and justification. -
Essentialism Story’’: a Case Study of German Idealistic Morphology
ARTICLE IN PRESS Theory in Biosciences 124 (2006) 281–307 www.elsevier.de/thbio The history of essentialism vs. Ernst Mayr’s ‘‘Essentialism Story’’: A case study of German idealistic morphology Georgy S. LevitÃ, Kay Meister Institut fu¨r Geschichte der Medizin, Naturwissenschaft und Technik, Ernst-Haeckel-Haus, Friedrich-Schiller-Universita¨t, Berggasse 7, D-07745 Jena, Germany Received 17 October 2005; accepted 18 November 2005 Abstract Idealistic morphology as perhaps the most important historical manifestation of typology is very suitable for a historical analysis of Ernst Mayr’s ‘‘Essentialism Story’’, which postulates an antagonism between ‘‘typological thinking’’ and ‘‘population thinking’’. We show that German- language idealistic-morphological theories consisted of two clearly distinguishable parts. The cornerstone of these theories was the concept of the type as an abstract pattern representing a certain class of phenomena and embodying the norm of this class. The primary objective of pure typology was to create a non-phylogenetic classification system for living organisms based on structurally explicable characters. Thus, typology, as a non-phylogenetic foundation of idealistic morphology, was conceptually neutral with respect to hypotheses of evolutionary mechanisms. Typology was often accompanied by concepts such as Lamarckism, orthogenesis, creationism, essentialism, etc. These peripheral (with respect to pure typology) concepts were autonomous constructions and did not represent a direct logical consequence of typology. In our view ‘‘population thinking’’, as part of the Darwinian theory of evolutionary mechanism, could not be directly opposed to ‘‘typological thinking’’. Rather, it was peripheral concepts such as essentialism or creationism that led to conflicts between the Modern Synthesis and idealistic morphology. -
History of Evolutionary Theory - Barbara Continenza
BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE FUNDAMENTALS AND SYSTEMATICS – Vol. I - History of Evolutionary Theory - Barbara Continenza HISTORY OF EVOLUTIONARY THEORY Barbara Continenza Dipartimento di Ricerche Filosofiche, Facoltà di Lettere e Filosofia, Università di Roma "Tor Vergata", Roma, Italia Keywords: Evolution, development, species, creationism, essentialism, fixism, transformism, scala naturae, systematics, natural history, biology, inheritance of acquired characters, use and disuse of the organs, organization plan, catastrophism, uniformism. Contents 1. Introduction 2. Scientific Historiography and the Analysis of the Theoretical Concepts 3. The Definition of "Species" 4. The Problem of Classification 5. Linneus, the "System" and the "Methods" 6. Buffon and the nuance of Nature 7. The Historical Dimension and the Re-orientation of Natural History 8. Lamarck and Transformism 9. Paleontology and Geology Glossary Bibliography Biographical Sketch Summary The term "evolution" is linked to the idea of development in the sciences of life, and only subsequently did it acquire the present meaning of diversification and origin of new species. The dominant image of the scala naturae, strictly related to the creationist, static and essentialistic positions, was substituted by the image of the tree that characterizes the transformist theories, and that represents the process of transformation over long periods of time. UNESCO – EOLSS 1. Introduction "Evolution" is a term rich in suggestions. It penetrates the current lexicon that we are accustomed to useSAMPLE in the most disparate occasions, CHAPTERS with meanings that are sometimes very distant from the scientific theory that decreed its success, or that are only vaguely allusive to the Darwinian theory of evolution. The term "evolution" has also historically assumed different meanings in specific studies of life. -
The Prodigal Genetics Returns: Integrating Gene Regulatory Net- Work Theory Into Evolutionary Theory
THE PRODIGAL GENETICS RETURNS: INTEGRATING GENE REGULATORY NET- WORK THEORY INTO EVOLUTIONARY THEORY by Aaron Michael Novick BA, The College of Wooster, 2012 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of PhD University of Pittsburgh 2018 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBRUGH DIETRICH SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Aaron Michael Novick It was defended on September 05, 2018 and approved by James Woodward, Distinguished Professor, History and Philosophy of Science Mark Wilson, Distinguished Professor, Philosophy Sandra Mitchell, Distinguished Professor, History and Philosophy of Science Mark Rebeiz, Associate Professor, Biological Sciences Dissertation Director: James Lennox, Emeritus Professor, History and Philosophy of Science ii THE PRODIGAL GENETICS RETURNS: INTEGRATING GENE REGULATORY NETWORK THEORY INTO EVOLUTIONARY THEORY Aaron Michael Novick, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2018 The aim of this dissertation is to show how gene regulatory network (GRN) theory can be integrated into evolutionary theory. GRN theory, which lies at the core of evolution- ary-developmental biology (evo-devo), concerns the role of gene regulation in driving developmental processes, covering both how these networks function and how they evolve. Evolutionary and developmental biology, however, have long had an uneasy re- lationship. Developmental biology played little role in the establishment of a genetic the- ory evolution during the modern synthesis of the early to mid 20th century. As a result, the body of evolutionary theory that descends from the synthesis period largely lacks obvious loci for integrating the information provided by GRN theory. Indeed, the rela- tionship between the two has commonly been perceived, by both scientists and philoso- phers, as one of conflict. -
European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy
European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy XI-2 | 2019 Pragmatism and Theories of Emergence Pragmatism and Emergentism In Chauncey Wright’s Evolutionary Philosophy Andrea Parravicini Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/1623 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.1623 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Andrea Parravicini, « Pragmatism and Emergentism », European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy [Online], XI-2 | 2019, Online since 24 December 2019, connection on 15 June 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/1623 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.1623 This text was automatically generated on 15 June 2020. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Pragmatism and Emergentism 1 Pragmatism and Emergentism In Chauncey Wright’s Evolutionary Philosophy Andrea Parravicini AUTHOR'S NOTE The author thanks the anonymous reviewers for valuable comments. 1. Introduction 1.1 Current Debates on the Notion of “Emergence” During the last twenty-five years, the notion of “emergence” has gained renewed attention in different fields, from evolutionary biology to cognitive sciences, from social sciences to philosophy of mind.1 This interest is connected to the possible application of the notion of emergence in the study of complex systems and to the possibility of developing a “non-reductive physicalism” (Crane 2001: 207). Emergence generally describes a new property or entity appearing when a system reaches a certain threshold of complexity. Although the emergent element must be connected to the system from which it emerges, it must also be novel (Bennett-Hunter 2015).