Perfection, History, and Harmonious Individuality: Herder's Ethical Thought, 1765-1791

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Perfection, History, and Harmonious Individuality: Herder's Ethical Thought, 1765-1791 Syracuse University SURFACE Dissertations - ALL SURFACE May 2015 Perfection, History, and Harmonious Individuality: Herder's Ethical Thought, 1765-1791 Charles Richard Booher Syracuse University Follow this and additional works at: https://surface.syr.edu/etd Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation Booher, Charles Richard, "Perfection, History, and Harmonious Individuality: Herder's Ethical Thought, 1765-1791" (2015). Dissertations - ALL. 203. https://surface.syr.edu/etd/203 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the SURFACE at SURFACE. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations - ALL by an authorized administrator of SURFACE. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Abstract This work is a study of the ethical thought of Johann Gottfried Herder. I examine the development of his ethics from 1765 through 1791. I contend that the earliest texts express a set of ideas that Herder modified and developed throughout the rest of his work. These are a perfectionist conception of the end of human life, a belief in the centrality of history for ethics, a form of naturalism, and a commitment to the idea that every individual ought to blend their characteristic powers into a harmonious whole. The study considers a set of texts in chronological order. I begin with an examination of the ideals espoused by Herder in two texts from the 1760s, “Wie die Philosophie zum Besten des Volks Allgemeiner und Nützlicher Werden Kann” and Journal meiner Reise im Jahr 1769. I then look at an exchange of letters between Herder and Moses Mendelssohn concerning the highest good, or vocation of man. I then look at how the ideas sketched in these earlier works were filled out in Abhandlung über den Ursprung der Sprache (1772), Auch eine Philosophie der Geschichte zur Bildung der Menschheit (1774), Vom Erkennen und Empfinden der menschlichen Seele (1774-8), and Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit (1784-91). Perfection, History, and Harmonious Individuality: Herder’s Ethical Thought, 1765-1791 by C. Richard Booher B.A., California State University Fullerton, 2003 M.A., The University of Chicago, 2004 Dissertation Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy Syracuse University May 2015 Copyright © 2015 C. Richard Booher All rights reserved Acknowledgements Fred Beiser provided me with judicious advice and criticism from the beginning of this project up to its completion. He was also encouraging at several crucial junctures when I needed it. This work would not have many of its better qualities, and would have taken much longer to bring to an end, had I not been fortunate to have such an excellent advisor. I also owe a debt to other members of the faculty at Syracuse University. Michael Stocker was a kind and wise guide. Traces of his influence have left their mark on my work, and the shape of my own philosophical views, even if they are not always immediately apparent. I also owe thanks to Ken Baynes, who has always been supportive, in addition to being a pleasure to converse with. I am thankful the members of my examination committee for their time, energy, and willingness to read my work: Nigel DeSouza, Michael Forster, Kristin Gjesdal, and Ahmed Abdel Meguid. Among my graduate student peers at Syracuse, I am thankful to Andrew Corsa, Jon Delmendo, Kienhow Goh, Aaron Koller, and John Monteleone for their camaraderie and intellectual support. I am also thankful for the love and encouragement of my family. My daughters, Caroline and Myra, are about as old as this project. Many challenging moments were allayed by their free and uplifting spirits. I also thank my parents, Chuck and Pam Booher, for their support. In working on the final stages of this project, I was carried on by the loving support of Erin Evans, for whose presence in my life I am enormously grateful. iv Table of Contents Acknowledgments………………………………………………………………………………iv Introduction………………………………………….……………………………….….………1 Chapter 1: Herder’s Early Ideals………………………………………..………………...…15 Chapter 2: The Vocation of Man Controversy….................…………………..………….46 Chapter 3: Abhandlung über den Ursprung der Sprache…………………..…….….…….92 Chapter 4: Herder’s Genealogy of Morals: Auch eine Philosophie der Geschichte………………………..………………117 Chapter 5: Vom Erkennen und Empfinden der menschlichen Seele…………..….……143 Chapter 6: Bonds of Love and the Chain of History: Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit……………….…......175 Conclusion…………………………………………………………….…………….…….….199 Note on Translations………………….…………………………………….……………….201 Abbreviations…………………….……………………………………………….…………..202 Bibliography………………….……………….……….……...………………………………202 Vita……………………………….………………………..…………………………………..211 v Introduction I T. Churchill, in the translator’s preface to the 1800 English language translation of Herder’s Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit, writes of his experience translating Herder: …many moments of bodily pain and mental anxiety has it sweetly beguiled; and while it has made my breast glow with the fervor of virtuous sentiment, I have almost felt myself the inhabitant of another world. May others feel from the perusal what I have done from the performance; and then no one, I hope, will lay down the book, without being able to say, that he is a happier and better man.1 This is not the only reference to the effect of reading Herder that strikes such a tone. Herder receives a significant mention in one of the greatest novels of the nineteenth- century, Tolstoy’s War and Peace. In a central moment of the novel, Pierre Bezukhov counsels the despondent Prince Andrei Bolkhonski: “You say you can’t see the kingdom of the good and the true on earth. I didn’t see it either; and it can’t be seen if you look at our life as the end of everything. On earth, I mean this earth” (Pierre pointed to the fields), “there is no truth – but in the universe, in the whole universe, there is the kingdom of the true, and we are now children of the earth, but eternally – children of the whole universe. Don’t I feel in my soul that I make up a part of that huge, harmonious whole? Don’t I feel that, among the countless number of beings in which the divinity – the higher power – whatever you like – is manifest, I make up one link, one step from lower beings to higher? If I see, see clearly, this ladder that leads from plant to man, then why should I suppose that this ladder, the lower end of which I do not see, is lost in the plants? Why should I suppose that this ladder stops with me and does not lead further and further to higher beings? I feel not only that I cannot 1 Translator’s preface to Johann Gottfried Herder, Outlines of a Philosophy of the History of Man, trans. T. Churchill (London: Luke Hansard, 1800), p. iv. 1 disappear, as nothing disappears in the world, but that I will always be and have always been. I feel that, besides me, above me, spirits live, and that in this world there is truth.” “Yes, that’s Herder’s teaching,” said Prince Andrei, “but that, dear heart, does not convince me; life and death are what convince me.”2 For the present moment, I wish to set aside the issue of the accuracy of these portrayals.3 What I want to draw attention to is that in both passages we can see that Herder was regarded as a thinker who had something to offer us in our ethical reflections, even for our improvement. This facet of his thought is foregrounded, and both writers suggest that Herder is a philosopher to be read for moral edification.4 This stands in stark contrast to the majority of Herder scholarship, which has not frequently made his ethical thought an object of detailed study. Admittedly, there are frequent passing references to Herder’s ethical views by scholars. However, these are almost always interjected as a background consideration in the midst of an account of his philosophy of history, language, social theory, or aesthetics.5 This is understandable, as 2 Leo Tolstoy, War and Peace, trans. Richard Pevear and Larissa Volokhonsky (New York: Knopf, 2007), p. 389. It is worth noting that Pierre achieves this transformation, in part, through an involvement in freemasonry, and that Herder was also a freemason from early in his adulthood. Tolstoy may have been aware of this. 3 The passage from Tolstoy comes closest to offering an actual interpretation of Herder, and I think that there are elements of it that are correct, but others that are wrong or misleading. Where I think it seems to go wrong, in brief, is that it intonates that the meaning of a human life is something transcendent and has to do with the existence of spirits or “higher beings”. As I will try to show in the present work, I think that Herder’s account of the highest good does not at all rely on such notions. 4 Throughout the rest of this text, I do not distinguish between the ‘ethical’, as an account of how one should live, and the ‘moral’, as concerned with duties and obligations. I admit the fruitfulness that such a distinction can have, as has been argued in Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), chapter 10. I believe nonetheless that imposing a distinction of this kind onto Herder, or forcing an inquiry into his works to conform to such a distinction, would be arduous and distortive. 5 The most noteworthy exceptions to this are Benjamin D. Crowe, "Herder’s Moral Philosophy: Perfectionism, Sentimentalism, and Theism," British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20, no. 6 (2012); Heiko Joosten, Selbst, Substanz und Subjekt: Die ethische und politische Relevanz der personalen Identität bei Descartes, Herder und Hegel (Würzburg: Königshausen und Neumann, 2005); Sonia Sikka, Herder on Humanity and Cultural Difference (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011).
Recommended publications
  • Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholarship@Western Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 9-23-2015 12:00 AM Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought Ben Woodard The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Tilottama Rajan The University of Western Ontario Joint Supervisor Joan Steigerwald The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Theory and Criticism A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Ben Woodard 2015 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Woodard, Ben, "Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought" (2015). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 3314. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/3314 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Schelling's Naturalism: Motion, Space, and the Volition of Thought (Thesis Format: Monograph) by Benjamin Graham Woodard A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctorate of Philosophy in Theory and Criticism The School of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies The University of Western Ontario London, Ontario, Canada © Ben Woodard 2015 Abstract: This dissertation examines F.W.J. von Schelling's Philosophy of Nature (or Naturphilosophie) as a form of early, and transcendentally expansive, naturalism that is, simultaneously, a naturalized transcendentalism.
    [Show full text]
  • HUMANISM Religious Practices
    HUMANISM Religious Practices . Required Daily Observances . Required Weekly Observances . Required Occasional Observances/Holy Days Religious Items . Personal Religious Items . Congregate Religious Items . Searches Requirements for Membership . Requirements (Includes Rites of Conversion) . Total Membership Medical Prohibitions Dietary Standards Burial Rituals . Death . Autopsies . Mourning Practices Sacred Writings Organizational Structure . Headquarters Location . Contact Office/Person History Theology 1 Religious Practices Required Daily Observance No required daily observances. Required Weekly Observance No required weekly observances, but many Humanists find fulfillment in congregating with other Humanists on a weekly basis (especially those who characterize themselves as Religious Humanists) or other regular basis for social and intellectual engagement, discussions, book talks, lectures, and similar activities. Required Occasional Observances No required occasional observances, but some Humanists (especially those who characterize themselves as Religious Humanists) celebrate life-cycle events with baby naming, coming of age, and marriage ceremonies as well as memorial services. Even though there are no required observances, there are several days throughout the calendar year that many Humanists consider holidays. They include (but are not limited to) the following: February 12. Darwin Day: This marks the birthday of Charles Darwin, whose research and findings in the field of biology, particularly his theory of evolution by natural selection, represent a breakthrough in human knowledge that Humanists celebrate. First Thursday in May. National Day of Reason: This day acknowledges the importance of reason, as opposed to blind faith, as the best method for determining valid conclusions. June 21 - Summer Solstice. This day is also known as World Humanist Day and is a celebration of the longest day of the year.
    [Show full text]
  • The Star of the Age of Reason. Voltaire 1694-1778
    Camilla Kolstad Danielsen The Star of The Age of Reason. Voltaire 1694-1778 During the 18th century, the French writers, philosophers and scientists were determined to improve the world through reason. Voltaire was the most famous of them all. No other writer was as frequently read and discussed. He was successful with his tragedies and poetry, he disseminated Newton’s philosophy to Europe and he was engaged in individual fates. For us, Voltaire is a symbolic figure, a socially engaged 2013 intellectual writer who fought for freedom of speech and other human rights. Such a Original title: Opplysningens stjerne. Voltaire notion is tinted by our modern viewpoint. But the important position Voltaire NORLA Selection acquired in his time was a result of the independent manner with which he handled his role as writer. FOREIGN RIGHTS This book provides an insight into Voltaire’s extensive and comprehensive authorship HAGEN AGENCY by Eirin Hagen within fiction, history, philosophy and various socially engaged essays. We meet Lindemans gate 3 D Voltaire as both controversial and moderate, radical and conservative, a contentious NO-0267 Oslo Tel: +47 22 46 52 54 man who won many battles, but far from all, and he did his best to fashion his star Mob: +47 93 41 10 56 status within his contemporaries and for future generations. [email protected] www.hagenagency.no English sample translation available Humanist Forlag 2014 231 Pages Praise: “This is a great book, scholastically solid and an exemplary dissemination of research. It is captivating and funny, and at the same time so convincing that I don’t think I have ever read anything better about Voltaire” Ellen Krefting, associate professor at the University of Oslo Camilla Kolstad Danielsen Camilla Kolstad Danielsenhas written articles on the French enlightenment and her PhD thesis about Voltaire’s philosophical narratives, potpourri, as a genre practice in Voltaire’s later philosophical works (2006).
    [Show full text]
  • Ferguson Diss
    PERMACULTURE AS FARMING PRACTICE AND INTERNATIONAL GRASSROOTS NETWORK: A MULTIDISCIPLINARY STUDY BY JEFFREY FERGUSON DISSERTATION Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Crop Sciences in the Graduate College of the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, 2015 Urbana, Illinois Doctoral Committee: Associate Professor Sarah Taylor Lovell, Chair Professor Michelle M. Wander Associate Professor Ashwini Chhatre Professor Thomas J. Bassett ABSTRACT Agroecology is a promising alternative to industrial agriculture, with the potential to avoid the negative social and ecological consequences of input-intensive production. Transitioning to agroecological production is, however, a complex project that requires action from all sectors of society – from producers and consumers, and from scientists and grassroots networks. Grassroots networks and movements are increasingly regarded as agents of change, with a critical role to play in agroecological transition as well as broader socio-environmental transformation. Permaculture is one such movement, with a provocative perspective on agriculture and human-environment relationships more broadly. Despite its relatively broad international distribution and high public profile, permaculture has remained relatively isolated from scientific research. This investigation helps to remedy that gap by assessing permaculture through three distinct projects. A systematic review offers a quantitative and qualitative assessment of the permaculture literature,
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant Was Born in 1724, and Published “Religion Within The
    CHAPTER FIVE THE PHENOMENOLOGY AND ‘FORMATIONS OF CONSCIOUSNESS’ It is this self-construing method alone which enables philosophy to be an objective, demonstrated science. (Hegel 1812) Immanuel Kant was born in 1724, and published “Religion within the limits of Reason” at the age of 70, at about the same time as the young Hegel was writing his speculations on building a folk religion at the seminary in Tübingen and Robespierre was engaged in his ultimately fatal practical experiment in a religion of Reason. Kant was a huge figure. Hegel and all his young philosopher friends were Kantians. But Kant’s system posed as many problems as it solved; to be a Kantian at that time was to be a participant in the project which Kant had initiated, the development of a philosophical system to fulfill the aims of the Enlightenment; and that generally meant critique of Kant. We need to look at just a couple of aspects of Kant’s philosophy which will help us understand Hegel’s approach. “I freely admit,” said Kant , “it was David Hume ’s remark [that Reason could not prove necessity or causality in Nature] that first, many years ago, interrupted my dogmatic slumber and gave a completely differ- ent direction to my enquiries in the field of speculative philosophy” (Kant 1997). Hume’s “Treatise on Human Nature” had been published while Kant was still very young, continuing a line of empiricists and their rationalist critics, whose concern was how knowledge and ideas originate from sensation. Hume was a skeptic; he demonstrated that causality could not be deduced from experience.
    [Show full text]
  • Averroes's Dialectic of Enlightenment
    59 AVERROES'S DIALECTIC OF ENLIGHTENMENT. SOME DIFFICULTIES IN THE CONCEPT OF REASON Hubert Dethier A. The Unity ofthe Intellect This theory of Averroes is to be combated during the Middle ages as one of the greatest heresies (cft. Thomas's De unitate intellectus contra Averroystas); it was active with the revolutionary Baptists and Thomas M"Unzer (as Pinkstergeest "hoch liber alIen Zerstreuungen der Geschlechter und des Glaubens" 64), but also in the "AufkHinmg". It remains unclear on quite a few points 65. As far as the different phases of the epistemological process is concerned, Averroes reputes Avicenna's innovation: the vis estimativa, as being unaristotelian, and returns to the traditional three levels: senses, imagination and cognition. As far as the actual abstraction process is concerned, one can distinguish the following elements with Avicenna. 1. The intelligible fonns (intentiones in the Latin translation) are present in aptitude and in imaginative capacity, that is, in the sensory images which are present there; 2. The fonns are actualised by the working of the Active Intellect (the lowest celestial sphere), that works in analogy to light ; 3. The intelligible fonns-in-act are "received" by the "possible" or the "material intellecf', which thereby changes into intellect-in-act, also called: habitual or acquired intellect: the. perfect form ofwhich - when all scientific knowledge that can be acquired, has been acquired -is called speculative intellect. 4. According to the Aristotelian principle that the epistemological process and knowing itselfcoincide, the state ofintellect-in-act implies - certainly as speculative intellect - the conjunction with the Active Intellect. 64 Cited by Ernst Bloch, Avicenna und die Aristotelische Linke, (1953), in Suhrkamp, Gesamtausgabe, 7, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Camora 1.Pdf
    The Function of the Rhetoric of Maternity in the Representation of Female Sexuality, Religion, Nationality, and Race in Early Modern English Literature and Culture by Cecilia Morales A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (English Language and Literature) in the University of Michigan 2020 Doctoral Committee: Professor Michael Schoenfeldt, Chair Dr. Neeraja Aravamudan, Edward Ginsberg Center, University of Michigan Professor Peggy McCracken Professor Catherine Sanok Professor Valerie Traub Cecilia Morales [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0001-7428-3777 © Cecilia Morales 2020 Acknowledgements Throughout my doctoral studies, I have been fortunate to have the love and support of countless individuals, to whom I owe a great deal of gratitude. I’d like to begin by thanking my committee members. Cathy and Peggy taught me valuable lessons not only about my work but about being a thoughtful and compassionate scholar and teacher. Valerie’s reminders to always be as generous as possible when discussing the work of other scholars has kept me sane and stable in this competitive world of academia. Mike helped me, a displaced Texan, to feel at home in Michigan from our first meeting, during which we chatted about both Shakespearean scholarship and Tex Mex. Finally, the most recent addition to my committee is Neeraja Aravamudan, who I consider my most active mentor and supporter. One of the best decisions I made during graduate school was accepting an internship at the Edward Ginsberg Center, where Neeraja became my supervisor. Neeraja and the other Ginsberg staff remind me it’s possible to take my work very seriously without taking myself too seriously.
    [Show full text]
  • From Witchcraft to Pseudoscience
    From Witchcraft to Pseudoscience Entertaining Satan: Witchcraft and the Culture of Early New England. By John Putnam Demos. Oxford University Press, New York, 1982. 543 pp. $29.95. Michael R. Dennett N SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY New England, in more cases than not, the I verdict in trials of individuals accused of being witches was "Not guilty."1 This is just one of the tidbits of information about the witch trials in early America found in John Demos's book, Entertaining Satan. It is rich in historic detail excavated from old court records at the cost of untold hours of research. Entertaining Satan is an important look into the past, and in particular it provides a view of how the paranormal was viewed three centuries ago. Demos gives the reader in-depth characterizations of some of the alleged witches (no light accom­ plishment in view of the incompleteness of available data). He also makes some effort to analyze the New England communities and their role in the events. It is is in the assessment of seventeenth-century New England and of witchcraft and how it relates to our day that this book fails. Discussing the idea of witchcraft and the trials, the author writes: "Our own culture accords a measure of tolerance to such conflicts; but in early New England the situation was probably quite different." He refers to the New England of this time as "premodern" and implies a connection between witchcraft and the premodern nature of the society. Although Demos never defines the premodern society, the implication is that it is different from a modern society.
    [Show full text]
  • Bringing Nature to Light: Schellingâ•Žs Naturphilosophie in the Early
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2013 Bringing Nature to Light: Schelling’s Naturphilosophie in the Early System of Identity Michael Vater Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Analecta Hermeneutica, Vol. 5 (2013). Permalink. © 2013 International Institute for Hermeneutics. Used with permission. ISSN 1918-7351 Volume 5 (2013) Bringing Nature to Light: Schelling’s Naturphilosophie in the Early System of Identity Michael Vater Light is already a completely ideal activity that deconstructs and reconstructs objects just as the light of idealism always does— and so Naturphilosophie provides a physical explanation of idealism, which proves that at the boundaries of nature there must break forth the intelligence we see break forth in the guise of humanity [Person des Menschen]. Schelling, General Deduction of Dynamic Process, § 631 In November of 1800 the issue of the reality of nature and its meaning for a transcendental philosophy interrupts, or rather heats up, the exchange of letters between Fichte in Berlin and Schelling in Jena. Fichte has faint praise for the latter‟s System of Transcendental Idealism and marks as problematic the way it sets nature alongside of consciousness as the subject of a genetic deduction. For transcendental philosophy, he insists, nature can only be something found, finished, perfect because lawful, but whose lawfulness is not its own, but that of the intelligence which beholds and explains.2 Schelling responds with a long recital of his philosophical development and poses several alternative ways that philosophy of nature might coincide with Wissenschaftslehre, the most radical of which suggests that philosophy of consciousness must be based on natural philosophy, not the reverse.
    [Show full text]
  • Albert Schweitzer: a Man Between Two Cultures
    , .' UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I LIBRARY ALBERT SCHWEITZER: A MAN BETWEEN TWO CULTURES A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN LANGUAGES AND LITERATURES OF • EUROPE AND THE AMERICAS (GERMAN) MAY 2007 By Marie-Therese, Lawen Thesis Committee: Niklaus Schweizer Maryann Overstreet David Stampe We certify that we have read this thesis and that, in our opinion, it is satisfactory in scope and quality as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts in Languages and Literatures of Europe and the Americas (German). THESIS COMMITIEE --~ \ Ii \ n\.llm~~~il\I~lmll:i~~~10 004226205 ~. , L U::;~F H~' _'\ CB5 .H3 II no. 3Y 35 -- ,. Copyright 2007 by Marie-Therese Lawen 1II "..-. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS T I would like to express my deepest gratitude to a great number of people, without whose assistance, advice, and friendship this thesis w0l!'d not have been completed: Prof. Niklaus Schweizer has been an invaluable mentor and his constant support have contributed to the completion of this work; Prof. Maryann Overstreet made important suggestions about the form of the text and gave constructive criticism; Prof. David Stampe read the manuscript at different stages of its development and provided corrective feedback. 'My sincere gratitude to Prof. Jean-Paul Sorg for the the most interesting • conversations and the warmest welcome each time I visited him in Strasbourg. His advice and encouragement were highly appreciated. Further, I am deeply grateful for the help and advice of all who were of assistance along the way: Miriam Rappolt lent her editorial talents to finalize the text; Lynne Johnson made helpful suggestions about the chapter on Bach; John Holzman suggested beneficial clarifications.
    [Show full text]
  • Religion Senior Seminar: Authority of Torah
    Religion Senior Seminar: Authority of Torah Religion 370 Professor: Jason Radine Classroom: 114 Comenius Hall Office: 108 Comenius Hall, x1314 Class times: TTh 2:35-3:45 Office Hours: Tuesdays 4:00-6:00pm E-mail: [email protected] and by appointment The Senior Seminar in Religion This course is the Senior Seminar in Religion, which is intended to form part of the “capstone” in your senior year as a Religion major or minor. The Senior Seminar is a research-based course, which emphasizes research methods and writing skills within the discipline of religious studies. For Religion majors, this course can serve as excellent preparation for Religion 385, the independent study program within the Religion Department. For Religion minors, this course can serve as an excellent stand-alone capstone to the minor. For both majors and minors, this course will utilize many of the skills that you have developed throughout your time with the Religion Department, including interpretation, close reading skills, research methods and academic writing. Four Views on the Authority of Torah Every year the Senior Seminar is different. This year, we will be studying a classic debate on the authority of the Bible, specifically of the Torah/Pentateuch (the first five books). We will be studying the writings on this topic by four key figures in the discussion; three Jews and one Christian. These will be the Dutch-Jewish philosopher Baruch Spinoza (1632-1677), the German-Jewish philosopher Moses Mendelssohn (1729-1786), the German Rabbi Samson Raphael Hirsch (1808-1888), and the German Protestant biblical scholar Julius Wellhausen (1844-1918).
    [Show full text]
  • Rabbi David Fränckel, Moses Mendelssohn, and the Beginning of the Berlin Haskalah
    RABBI DAVID FRÄNCKEL, MOSES MENDELSSOHN, AND THE BEGINNING OF THE BERLIN HASKALAH. REATTRIBUTING A PATRIOTIC SERMON (1757) Addenda Gad Freudenthal On December 10, 1757, R. David Fränckel (1707–1762), Chief Rabbi of Berlin Jewry, delivered in German a sermon on the occa- sion of Frederick the Great’s victory at Leuthen five days earlier (5 December). Volume 1 of EJJS carried my article describing the genesis of this so-called “Leuthen Sermon” and established that (contrary to previous consensus) it was written by David Fränckel and not by his former student Moses Mendelssohn (1729–1796).1 Rather, it was written in Hebrew by Fränckel and only translated into German by Mendelssohn. In an appendix, I described the very rich aftermath of the sermon: after having been very elegantly translated into English (we do not know by whom) and published by the ephemeral London publisher W. Reeve in 1758, the translation was reprinted no less than four times in New England. Mr. Shimon Steinmetz from Brooklyn (N.Y.) kindly drew my attention to three earlier relevant items that had escaped my atten- tion. He also supplied copies of them. I herewith thank him warmly for his generous and erudite help and share his findings with readers of EJJS: [1] As early as March 1758, The Scots Magazine, published in Edinburgh, carried the following entry in the section “New Books”: A thanksgiving-sermon from Psal xxii. 23.24 for the King of Prussia’s victory Dec. 5. Preached on the sabbath of the 10th, in the synagogue of the Jews in Berlin.
    [Show full text]