Mental Representation and the Subjectivity of Consciousness

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Mental Representation and the Subjectivity of Consciousness PHILOSOPHICALPSYCHOLOGY , VOL. 14, NO. 2, 2001 Mental representation and the subjectivity ofconsciousness * PETE MANDIK ABSTRACT Many haveurged that the biggest obstacles to a physicalistic understanding of consciousness arethe problems raised in connection withthe subjectivity ofconsciousness. These problemsare most acutely expressed in considerationof theknowledge argument against physicalism. Idevelopa novelaccount of the subjectivity of consciousness byexplicatingthe ways in whichmental representationsmay be perspectival. Crucial featuresof my accountinvolve analogies between the representationsinvolved in sensoryexperience and theways in which pictorialrepresentations exhibit perspectivesor points of view. Iarguethat the resultant account of subjectivity provides a basisfor thestrongest response physicalists can giveto the knowledge argument. Introduction Consciousness has beena real pain forphilosophers and cognitive scientists inter- estedin developing materialist theoriesof the mind. Particularly vexing is the subjectivity ofconsciousness: thesubjective characterof conscious experience. What subjectivity is and whyit posesproblems for physicalists emergesmost vividly in discussions focusing onthework of philosophers Thomas Nagel and Frank Jackson. Nagel (1974) famously asked “whatis it like tobe a bat?”and urged thathumans, notbeing bats, could never know. Mostimportantly in his criticism ofthe limits of physicalism, Nagel argued thatno amount ofknowledge ofthe objective physical factsabout bat brains could yield knowledge ofthe subjective characterof bat experience. Whatis known fromthe objective point of view cannot bridge thegulf toyield whatis known fromthe subjective pointof view: knowledge of what it is like . Drawing on similar intuitions, Jackson marshaled thesethemes in an attemptto falsify physicalism by way ofhis nowfamous knowledge argument .The gist ofthe knowledge argument is as follows.Mary has never seen red. She nonethelessknows all thephysical facts. Upon seeing red forthe rsttime, Mary learns something new: what it is like tosee red. Priorto seeing red, Mary knewall thephysical facts; thus *This paper was the winnerof the 2000William James Prize of the Societyfor Philosophy and Psychology, awarded for the best paper by agraduate student presentedat the Society’s annualmeeting. PeteMandik, Departmentof Philosophy, William Paterson University ofNew Jersey, 265Atrium Building, 300Pompton Road, Wayne, NJ07470,USA, email: [email protected] ISSN 0951-5089/print/ISSN 1465-394X/online/01/020179–24 Ó 2001Taylor &FrancisLtd DOI:10.1080/ 09515080120051553 180 P. MANDIK in learning anewfact upon having ared experience, Mary learns anon-physical fact. Thus thesubjective characterof experience is non-physical (Jackson, 1982). Therehave beenmany physicalist responsesto Nagel and Jackson overthe years. Mostare awed and only afewexplicitly address thetopic of subjectivity. In thispaper I develop atheoryof subjectivity and use it in adefenseof physicalism against theknowledge argument. Crucial aspectsof myaccount involve explications ofthe notions of perspective and point ofview .Icultivate an account ofperspective as it arises in pictorial representationsand apply theresultant account ofpictorial perspectiveto mental representations. Icontrastmy account against accounts that analyze perspectivesand pointsof view in termsof indexicals. Keyaspects in my arguments forthe superiority ofthe pictorial theoryof subjectivity overindexical theorieshinge on howthe respective theories are able todeal withthe issues raised in connection withthe knowledge argument. This paperis organized as follows.I begin withfurther discussion ofNagel and Jackson’s original arguments withspecial attention paid tothe role played by the notion ofsubjectivity. Ithenbrie y discuss themain kinds ofphysicalist responses toJackson’ s knowledge argument. Aftercanvassing themain kinds ofphysicalist responsesand their aws, Ilaunch into thearticulation ofmy pictorial theoryof subjectivity. Idiscuss crucial similarities and differencesbetween my pictorial theory and indexical theories,and address several possibleobjections to thepictorial theory. 1.The subjectivity of consciousness andthe knowledge argument against physicalism Nagel’s reections on objectivity and subjectivity have beendeveloped in several places, buthere I focuson his 1974 article “Whatis it like tobe a bat?”Nagel presumesthat bats are conscious, thatthere is something it is like tobe abat. Things thatlack conscious, like rocks,are things forwhich there is nothing it is like tobe. Notonly is Nagel condent thatthere is something it is like tobe a bat, heis condent thatit is radically unlike whatit is like tobe a human. This is plausible. Bats have sensory systemsquite unlike ours; mostnotably theyemploy sonar in their perceptual interaction withtheir environment. Given thedivergence betweenhu- mans and bats, humans are incapable ofknowing whatit is like tobe a bat. Imagination and extrapolation are oflittle help. Even imagining apping around and hearing ourown voices reected off of the surfaces of objects serves only totell us whatit would belike tobe us under altered circumstances—such imaginings bring us no closerto knowing whatit would belike for bats.Whatwe can knowabout bats are thedeliverances ofobjective physical sciences: factsand propertiesknowable frommultiple pointsof view— objective facts. The factsabout batsbeyond our purview are thesubjective facts:facts known, if at all, only fromthe point ofview of bats. Acrucial point tonote, and onethat I will return toseveral timesin thispaper, is thatNagel intends theseremarks about perspectivesand pointsof view tobe about types and not tokens.Nagel writes: Iam notadverting hereto thealleged privacy ofexperience toits possessor. The point ofview in question is notone accessible only toa single MENTAL REPRESENTATION 181 individual. Ratherit is a type. Itis oftenpossible to take up apoint ofview otherthan one’s own, sothe comprehension of such factsis notlimited to one’s owncase. Thereis asense in whichphenomenological factsare perfectlyobjective: one person can knowor say ofanotherwhat the quality ofthe other’ s experience is. They are subjective, however,in thesense that even thisobjective ascription ofexperience is possibleonly forsomeone sufciently similar tothe object of ascription tobe able toadopt his point ofview— to understand theascription in the rstperson as well as in the third, soto speak. The moredifferent from oneself the other experiencer is, theless successone can expectwith this enterprise. (1974, pp. 441–442) Nagel thusurges thatwhat we are cutoff from are factsabout certain properties— universals orrepeatables thatare instantiable by multiple individuals. Nagel’s arguments are nottargeting theepistemic problem of knowing theminds ofthose thatare merely numerically distinct fromyou, aproblemthat could arise between you and an otherwiseidentical twin. Nagel is instead concerned topoint outa problemthat arises in trying tocomprehend a quite qualitatively distinct kind of mind. Nagel castshis criticism as pointing outthe limits ofcurrent physicalistic understanding, buthe does not see it as falsifying physicalism. While hehas no doubt that physicalism about subjectivity is true, Nagel says thatwe cannot currently understand how it is true. Jackson, in contrast, cultivates Nagelian themesinto an argument against physicalism: theknowledge argument. Jackson’s knowledge argu- mentinvolves twothought experiments, onemore famous than theother. The famousthought experiment featuresMary, thephysically omniscient scientist who only comesto learn whatit is like tosee red late in life. Lessfamous is thethought experiment thatfeatures Fred. WhereMary spends mostof herlife restrictedto the black and whiteroom and thusseeing farfewer colors than theaverage human, Fred is gifted withan unusually sensitive visual systemand thussees more colors than the average human. Whereaverage humans might group asetof ripetomatoes together as all being thesame shade ofred, Fredsorts the tomatoes into twogroups thathe calls red1 and red2. Fredassures us thatred1 and red2 are as differentfrom each otheras yellow and blue. He sortsthe same objectsinto thesame groups trial after trial, giving evidence thatthe perceptual categories thathe is tapping into are quite salient and robust.Fred’ s reportsand behavior make us condent thatwhat it is like tobe Fred is differentfrom what it is like tobe a normal human. However, wedo notknow what it is like tobe Fred. Wemay acquire all ofthe physical information about howFred’ s nervous systemworks and whatphysical featuresof objects he is sensitive to,but this is insufcient togive us knowledge ofwhat it is like. According toJackson, however,there are otherconditions thatwill sufce to give us knowledge ofwhat it is like tobe Fred. Jackson invites us toimagine thathumans have their visual systemssurgically altered toresemble Fred’ s, orupon Fred’s death someone else receivesa transplant ofFred’ s visual system. Afterthese surgeries, peoplewould cometo learn something new—what it is like tobe Fred. Priorto the surgery, however,the regular humans knewall ofthephysical factsabout Fred. So in coming 182 P. MANDIK tolearn something new, theycome to learn something non-physical. Thus physical- ism is false since notall ofthe facts are physical facts. Like Nagel, Jackson urges thatthese remarks about thesubjective characterof experience target apointabout typesof minds, nottokens. Jackson writes: When Icomplained thatall
Recommended publications
  • Science, Subjectivity & Reality
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Science and Religion Dialogue Prints Journal of Consciousness Exploration & Research| April 2016 | Volume 7 | Issue 4 | pp. 333-336 333 Pereira, C. & Reddy, J. S. K., On Science & Phenomenology in Consciousness Studies Perspective Science, Subjectivity & Reality * Contzen Pereira & J. S. K. Reddy Abstract In this paper, we argue on the ability of science to capture the true subjective experience of life, blinded within the limits of its reductionist approaches. With this approach, even though science can explain well the physics behind the objective phenomenon, it fails fundamentally in understanding the various aspects associated with the biological entities. In this sense, we are skeptical to the present approach of science and calls out for a more fundamental theory of life that considers not only the objectivity aspect of a biological entity but also the subjective experience as well. It raises questions as to what does it takes to develop a new science from a subjective standpoint. Key Words: Science, subjectivity, reality, cosmos, peripersonal space. Modern science is based on the principle “Give us one free miracle and we’ll explain the rest.” The one free miracle is the appearance of all the matter and energy in the universe and all the laws that govern it from nothing, in a single instant - Terrence McKenna The Cosmos showers the experience of life graced by an enigmatic subject grounded in an objective fabric (or biological structure). The extent of the subjective experience is in a way bounded by the limitations of an objective fabric.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Habitus and the Power of the Embodied Self: Reflections on the Insights Gained from the Fakirs in Bangladesh
    23 Bangladesh e-Journal of Sociology. Volume 17, Number 2. July 2020. Aristotelian Habitus and the Power of the Embodied Self: Reflections on the Insights Gained from the Fakirs in Bangladesh Mohammad Golam Nabi Mozumder1, Abstract: This article traces back classical Greek and Medieval meanings of habitus to show that Bourdieu’s redefinition of habitus discarded a seminal feature of Aristotelian habitus—the power of radically transforming the self at will. I elaborate how the practices of purposefully training the embodied self remains marginalized in Pierre Bourdieu’s re-conceptualization of habitus. Examining Aristotle’s habitus, this paper brings back the focus on the long-neglected insight of the power of deliberately (re)training the self in constructing a heterodox but ethical way of being and socializing. As an example, I refer to the Fakirs in current Bangladesh, who cultivate antinomian life-practices. The main argument of the paper is that habitus in Bourdieu’s formulations is less suitable than Aristotle’s in analysing the praxis of the Fakirs. I suggest that instead of sticking to a universal conceptualization of habitus, sociologists should consider with equal importance both models of habitus articulated by Aristotle and Bourdieu. Doing that could benefit contemporary sociology in two ways: First, Aristotle’s conceptualization of habitus is an important tool in identifying the sociological importance of the praxis of marginalized groups, e.g., Fakirs in Bangladesh; and second, extending the focus of a key sociological concept, i.e., habitus, addresses the apparent disconnect between the wisdom of heterodox practitioners in the Global South and dominant social theories built upon the analyses of European and American social traditions.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel and Aristotle
    HEGEL AND ARISTOTLE ALFREDO FERRARIN Boston University published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, ny 10011-4211, usa 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, vic 3166, Australia Ruiz de Alarcón 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org © Alfredo Ferrarin 2001 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2001 Printed in the United States of America Typeface Baskerville 10.25/13 pt. System QuarkXPress™ 4.04 [AG] A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Ferrarin, Alfredo, 1960– Hegel and Aristotle / Alfredo Ferrarin. p. cm.–(Modern European philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 0-521-78314-3 1. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 1770–1831. 2. Aristotle – Influence. I. Title. II. Series. B2948 .F425 2000 193–dc21 00-029779 ISBN 0 521 78314 3 hardback CONTENTS Acknowledgments page xiii List of Abbreviations xv Introduction 1 § 1. Preliminary Notes 1 § 2. On the Object and Method of This Book 7 § 3. Can Energeia Be Understood as Subjectivity? 15 part i the history of philosophy and its place within the system 1. The Idea of a History of Philosophy 31 § 1. The Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Editions and Sources 31 § 2.
    [Show full text]
  • GALGAN, Gerald J., God and Subjectivity Roy Martinez
    Document generated on 09/30/2021 1:58 a.m. Laval théologique et philosophique GALGAN, Gerald J., God and Subjectivity Roy Martinez Volume 49, Number 1, février 1993 URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/400749ar DOI: https://doi.org/10.7202/400749ar See table of contents Publisher(s) Faculté de philosophie, Université Laval ISSN 0023-9054 (print) 1703-8804 (digital) Explore this journal Cite this review Martinez, R. (1993). Review of [GALGAN, Gerald J., God and Subjectivity]. Laval théologique et philosophique, 49(1), 166–167. https://doi.org/10.7202/400749ar Tous droits réservés © Laval théologique et philosophique, Université Laval, This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit 1993 (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit. Érudit is a non-profit inter-university consortium of the Université de Montréal, Université Laval, and the Université du Québec à Montréal. Its mission is to promote and disseminate research. https://www.erudit.org/en/ COMPTES RENDUS observed. At the foundation of this study, and present This disparity between the existence of the "this" like a shadow throughout it, is the Platonic-Christian and the cognizing agent posed no problem for first view of time as an image of eternity, and of ourselves philosophy since 'the other", or object of cognition, as redeemed from time, and able in part to compre• was simply given, there for apprehension or obser• hend it, through being in the image of God.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes for Our Seminar: Objectivity and Subjectivity
    Notes for our seminar: Objectivity and Subjectivity B.M. December 14, 2019 Contents I A preview and overview of the topics we may cover 2 1 The nature of our seminar-course 3 II Readings and Notes for the sessions of Sept 11, Oct 2, Oct 30, and part of Dec 4 13 2 Readings for the September 11 session 13 2.1 Excerpt from [9] . 14 3 Some notes for Sep 11: Subjectivity, Universal Subjectivity, Objectivity 15 3.1 Objective . 16 4 Readings for October 2: 25 5 Notes for Oct 21 session: Objectivity and Subjectivity in Mathematics 36 5.1 What is the number `A thousand and one'?....................... 37 5.2 Plato ............................................ 38 5.3 `Tower Pound' definition ................................ 39 1 5.4 J.S. Mill .......................................... 39 5.5 Georg Cantor: ...................................... 40 5.6 Gottlob Frege (∼ 1900) ................................ 41 5.7 Foundations::: or Constitutions ............................. 43 5.8 David Hilbert ....................................... 43 5.9 L.E.J. Brouwer ...................................... 46 5.10 The simple phrase \and so on::: "............................ 48 6 Readings for October 30, 2019: (Shades of Objectivity and Subjectivity in Epistemology, Probability, and Physics) 50 7 Notes for October 30, 2019:(Shades of Objectivity and Subjectivity in Epistemology, Probability, and Physics) 51 8 Subjectivity and Objectivity in Statistics: `Educating your beliefs' versus `Test- ing your Hypotheses' 55 8.1 Predesignation versus the self-corrective nature of inductive reasoning . 57 8.2 Priors as `Meta-probabilities' . 59 8.3 Back to our three steps . 61 8.4 A numerical example and a question . 62 9 Issues of Subjectivity and Objectivity in Physics 63 10 Consequentialism of Meaning|notes for part of session of December 4 65 11 Dealing with nonexistent objects 69 2 Part I A preview and overview of the topics we may cover 1 The nature of our seminar-course Phil273O (Objectivity and Subjectivity) will be the fourth seminar- course I've taught with Amartya Sen and Eric Maskin.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relationship Between Consciousness and Intentionality
    University of Central Florida STARS HIM 1990-2015 2013 The relationship between consciousness and intentionality Jordan Bell University of Central Florida Part of the Philosophy Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses1990-2015 University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in HIM 1990-2015 by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Recommended Citation Bell, Jordan, "The relationship between consciousness and intentionality" (2013). HIM 1990-2015. 1384. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses1990-2015/1384 THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN CONSCIOUSNESS AND INTENTIONALITY by JORDAN BELL A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Honors in the Major Program in Philosophy in the College of Arts & Humanities and in The Burnett Honors College at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Spring Term 2013 Thesis Chair: Dr. Mason Cash ABSTRACT Within the Philosophy of Mind two features of our mental life have been acknowledged as the most perplexing—consciousness, the phenomenal “what it is likeness” of our mental states, and intentionality, the aboutness or directedness of our mental states. As such, it has become commonplace to develop theories about these phenomena which seek to explain them naturalistically, that is, without resort to magic or miracles. Traditionally this has been done by analyzing consciousness and intentionality apart from one another. However, in more recent years the tide has turned. In contemporary theories these phenomena are typically analyzed in terms of the other.
    [Show full text]
  • Ronald Endicott, “Multiple Realizability” (Final Draft) Forthcoming in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2Nd Edition, Macmillan Press, 2005
    Ronald Endicott, “Multiple Realizability” (Final Draft) Forthcoming in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition, MacMillan Press, 2005 Multiple realizability is a key issue in debates over the nature of mind and reduction in the sciences. The subject consists of two parts: “multiplicity” and “realizability.” “Multiplicity” designates a kind of variability in the mechanism and materials from which a particular type of thing can be made. “Realizability” designates a specific relation that exists when there is the stated variability. Realizability Apart from the broad folk notion of realization meaning that a thing is “made real,” philosophers apply several technical notions to paradigm cases such computational states realized by engineering states, minds realized by brains, and persons realized by their bodies. The technical notions fall into three broad traditions: “mathematical,” “logico- semantic,” and “metaphysical.” The mathematical tradition equates realization with a form of mapping between objects. Generally speaking, x mathematically realizes y because elements of y map onto elements of x. The notion is useful for many purposes, for example, when constructing a formal model of a particular domain. However, since mapping extends to models as well as reality, it fails to distinguish between “simulated” versus “genuine” realizations. Heavenly stars can be mapped onto grains of sand, but grains of sand do not realize heavenly stars in any genuine sense. Similarly, the mental states described by a cognitive program can be mapped onto unthinking groups of things, but unthinking groups of things do not realize mental states in any genuine sense (Block, 1978). Hence, to capture what is essential to genuine realization, William Lycan (1987) adds ideas about evolutionary function, while David Chalmers (1994) emphasizes facts about causal structure.
    [Show full text]
  • The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: a Version of the Argument from Reason
    University of Calgary PRISM: University of Calgary's Digital Repository Graduate Studies The Vault: Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2019-04-30 The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: A Version of the Argument from Reason Hawkes, Gordon Hawkes, G. (2019). The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: A Version of the Argument from Reason (Unpublished master's thesis). University of Calgary, Calgary, AB. http://hdl.handle.net/1880/110301 master thesis University of Calgary graduate students retain copyright ownership and moral rights for their thesis. You may use this material in any way that is permitted by the Copyright Act or through licensing that has been assigned to the document. For uses that are not allowable under copyright legislation or licensing, you are required to seek permission. Downloaded from PRISM: https://prism.ucalgary.ca UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: A Version of the Argument from Reason by Gordon Hawkes A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS GRADUATE PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY CALGARY, ALBERTA APRIL, 2019 © Gordon Hawkes 2019 i Abstract The argument from reason is the name given to a family of arguments against naturalism, materialism, or determinism, and often for theism or dualism. One version of the argument from reason is what Victor Reppert calls “the argument from the psychological relevance of logical laws,” or what I call “the argument from logical principles.” This argument has received little attention in the literature, despite being advanced by Victor Reppert, Karl Popper, and Thomas Nagel.
    [Show full text]
  • Subjectivity and Objectivity Intentional Inexistence and the Independence of the Mind Michael Oliva Córdoba University of Hamburg Version: Wednesday, 4 July 2018
    Subjectivity and objectivity Intentional inexistence and the independence of the mind Michael Oliva Córdoba University of Hamburg Version: Wednesday, 4 July 2018 Introduction Few distinctions in philosophy are as pervasive as the distinction between the subjective and the objective. Apparently, this distinction has less often been submitted to thorough examination than one would expect. Perhaps this is due to its diffcult nature. It might also be due to the uneasiness with which the subjective-objective distinction is brought to harmony with the received scientifc perspective on the world. Yet so deep entrenched in our conceptual scheme is this distinction that to cast light on it is a worthwhile undertaking even if that did not lead to a complete, convenient, or coherent conception. But there is no need for pessimism. A clear and viable reformulation of that venerable distinction seems possible. It would bring out its essence and at the same time it would exceed mere historical interest. This paper aims at such a reformulation. In what follows, I offer an explanation of the central idea of independence in terms of non-inference and causal non-determination. Also, I point to the essential intentionality of the subjective and stress the central feature of intentional inexistence. In the course of this I shall use the most limited means only. Thus I hope to lay bare what the subjective-objective distinction comes down to, and I hope to do so in a manner acceptable on all sides. I close with some indications as to what such a reformulation may have a bearing on.
    [Show full text]
  • Possible Worlds I: Modal Realism
    Possible Worlds I: Modal Realism May 31, 2009 It is difficult to wander far in contemporary metaphysics without bumping into talk of possible worlds. And reference to possible worlds is not confined to metaphysics. It can be found in contemporary epistemology and ethics, and has even found its way into linguistics and decision theory. But what are those possible worlds, the entities to which theorists in these disciplines all appeal? Call any attempt to answer this question a theory of possible worlds. This paper sets out and evaluates a leading contemporary theory of possible worlds. The view’s principal proponent is David Lewis, and his label for it is ‘Modal Realism,’ which I will abbreviate ‘MR.’1 The view accepts the following sys- tematic correspondence between certain modal facts and facts regarding the existence of possible worlds: (SC) it is possible that φ iff there is a w such that w is a possible world and ‘φ’ is true at w. Lewis proposes MR, in part, as an attempt to specify the nature of the possible worlds whose existence is required by (SC)’s instances. This paper outlines Lewis’s view and discusses some main lines of objection. I will start by noting two competing ambitions for a theory of possible worlds (§1): that a theory of possible worlds be reductive and user-friendly. I will then outline Lewis’s version of MR (§2), and consider objections on the grounds that MR is not reductive (§3) and not user-friendly (§4). 1 Two Ambitions for a Theory of Possible Worlds There are at least two ambitions one might have for a theory of possible worlds.
    [Show full text]
  • The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History
    The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History 1960 FIRST COLLOQUIUM Wilfrid Sellars, "On Looking at Something and Seeing it" Ronald Hepburn, "God and Ambiguity" Comments: Dennis O'Brien Kurt Baier, "Itching and Scratching" Comments: David Falk/Bruce Aune Annette Baier, "Motives" Comments: Jerome Schneewind 1961 SECOND COLLOQUIUM W.D. Falk, "Hegel, Hare and the Existential Malady" Richard Cartwright, "Propositions" Comments: Ruth Barcan Marcus D.A.T. Casking, "Avowals" Comments: Martin Lean Zeno Vendler, "Consequences, Effects and Results" Comments: William Dray/Sylvan Bromberger PUBLISHED: Analytical Philosophy, First Series, R.J. Butler (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell's, 1962. 1962 THIRD COLLOQUIUM C.J. Warnock, "Truth" Arthur Prior, "Some Exercises in Epistemic Logic" Newton Garver, "Criteria" Comments: Carl Ginet/Paul Ziff Hector-Neri Castenada, "The Private Language Argument" Comments: Vere Chappell/James Thomson John Searle, "Meaning and Speech Acts" Comments: Paul Benacerraf/Zeno Vendler PUBLISHED: Knowledge and Experience, C.D. Rollins (ed.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1964. 1963 FOURTH COLLOQUIUM Michael Scriven, "Insanity" Frederick Will, "The Preferability of Probable Beliefs" Norman Malcolm, "Criteria" Comments: Peter Geach/George Pitcher Terrence Penelhum, "Pleasure and Falsity" Comments: William Kennick/Arnold Isenberg 1964 FIFTH COLLOQUIUM Stephen Korner, "Some Remarks on Deductivism" J.J.C. Smart, "Nonsense" Joel Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions" Comments: Keith Donnellan/Keith Lehrer Nicholas Rescher, "Evaluative Metaphysics" Comments: Lewis W. Beck/Thomas E. Patton Herbert Hochberg, "Qualities" Comments: Richard Severens/J.M. Shorter PUBLISHED: Metaphysics and Explanation, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966. 1965 SIXTH COLLOQUIUM Patrick Nowell-Smith, "Acts and Locutions" George Nakhnikian, "St. Anselm's Four Ontological Arguments" Hilary Putnam, "Psychological Predicates" Comments: Bruce Aune/U.T.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics Seminar Spring 2019, Andy Egan Theories of Subjectivity Or: What Kind of Relativism Is Right for You? Course Descrip
    Metaphysics seminar Spring 2019, Andy Egan Theories of Subjectivity or: What Kind of Relativism is Right for You? Course Description There are a bunch of subject matters about which various people have, at various times, had an inclination to say something like, “Hey, that stuff’s not fully objective. It’s not part of reality as it is in itself. It’s something that we bring to reality, or at least it’s partly something we bring to reality. It’s in the eye of the beholder. It’s subjective!” How to cash out that kind of thought in a careful and precise way is really, really not straightforward. What we’ll be doing in this seminar is looking at a few different domains about which people have sometimes wanted to say such things (color, taste, and ethics), and at the different kinds of theoretical apparatus people have offered to try to cash the thought(s) out (various kinds of contextualism, various kinds of response-dependence, weird metaphysics, various kinds of relativism about mental and/or linguistic content, probably etc.). What I’m hoping to get from the seminar is a clearer picture of how all these different bits of theoretical apparatus relate to each other, what kind of phenomena or theoretical desiderata would properly motivate *some* kind of subjectivist-y thought or other, and what kind of phenomena or theoretical desiderata would properly motivate one, rather than another, theory of subjectivity. (So: how should we go about deciding, faced with some subject matter, whether to try and offer a subjective theory of it, what would
    [Show full text]