Lukasiewicz and Many-Valued Logics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Lukasiewicz and Many-Valued Logics 1 Article 2 Lukasiewicz and Many-Valued Logics 3 Angel Garrido 1*, Piedad Yuste 2 4 1 Faculty of Sciences; [email protected] 5 2 Faculty of Philosophy; [email protected] 6 * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +34-91-398-72-37 7 Academic Editor: Angel Garrido 8 Received: date; Accepted: date; Published: date 9 Abstract: Our initial purpose is contributing to the search for the origins of many-valued logics 10 (MVLs, by acronym), and, within them, as a special case that of “Fuzzy Logic”, also called by 11 different manners, as Diffuse Logic, either Heuristic Logic, or `logique floue´ (in French), etc. Such 12 origins departing to Aristotle goes to our Lvov-Warsaw School, with an essential role played by the 13 philosopher and logician Jan Lukasiewicz. 14 Keywords: Mathematical Logic; Non-Classical Logics; Fuzzy Logic; Uncertainty; Vagueness; 15 Artificial Intelligence. 16 17 1. Introduction 18 The theory of “vague sets” (today so-called Fuzzy Sets) proceeds from the quantum 19 physicist and philosopher Max Black (1937), which also analyzes the problem of modeling 20 vagueness: “It is a paradox that the most developed and useful theories are expressed in terms of 21 objects never encountered in experience. While the mathematician constructs a theory in terms of 22 “perfect” objects, the experimental scientist observes of which the properties demanded by theory 23 are only approximately true. 24 25 2. Results about Vagueness 26 There are at least two fundamental approaches to Fuzzy Logic. The first of them may be 27 considered related with Multi-Valued Logical tradition; properly, the Petr Hájek´s school, centered 28 at Charles University of Prague group, or the group of Ostrava University, with Vilém Novák, Irina 29 Perfilieva, and other researchers [56-60], jointly with important ramifications on nearest countries, as 30 Poland, with Urzsula Wybraniec Skardowska, or Roman Murawski; Austria; Hungary, with Janos 31 Fodor; Belgium, with Etienne E. Kerre et al., or Italy, with Giangiacomo or Brunella Gerla, and also 32 Arianna Betti, for instance, etc. The procedure must be to fix a set of designed values, and then, to 33 define an entailment relation. We may define a suitable set of axioms and Inference Rules, as engine 34 for its deductive apparatus. 35 The second line of advance would be headed by Jan Pavelka, Goguen, Belohlavek, and 36 others, being directed on to provide a deductive apparatus in which approximate reasoning may be 37 admitted. It will be reached by a suitable fuzzy subset of logical axioms, and by Fuzzy Inference 38 Rules. 39 Between both approaches, it will be very different the logical consequence operator. In 40 the first case, it gives the set of logical consequences of a given axiomatic structures. While in the 41 second case it gives the fuzzy subset of logical consequences, into a given fuzzy subset of 42 hypotheses. 43 According to L. A. Zadeh, “More often than not, the classes of objects encountered in 44 the real physical world do not have precisely defined criteria of membership. Clearly, the “class of Axioms 2016, 5, x; doi:10.3390/ www.mdpi.com/journal/axioms Axioms 2016, 5, x 2 of 5 45 all real numbers which are much greater than 1”, or “the class of beautiful women” . , or “the class 46 of tall men”, do not constitute classes or sets in the usual mathematical sense of these terms. Yet, the 47 fact remains that such imprecisely defined “classes” play an important role in human thinking, 48 particularly in the domains of pattern recognition, communication of information, and abstraction”. 49 With the increasing of complexity our skill to make accurate diminishes. Real world problems are 50 too complex, and the difficulty involves the degree of vagueness. 51 Bertrand Russell wisely said that “there are two kinds of science: the old, which is the 52 official, and a new science, that most of the old look with horror. The result is a constant battle 53 between the old minds who admire science for its older and younger women, who appreciate the 54 value of the work of their peers. To some extent, this struggle is useful, but beyond a certain point, it 55 becomes disastrous.” 56 [B. R., Autobiography, p. 722]. 57 58 This lucid commentary, very typical of this British mathematician and philosopher, 59 seems tailored to the controversy that we study, as has rarely been given in the history of the new 60 scientific theories such bitter and unjust insults as those that occurred with the development and 61 deployment of Non-Classical Logics, and particularly of Fuzzy Logic, Fuzzy Logic or also called 62 Heuristic Logic. 63 The logic is a well-constructed set of formulas, with a ratio of inference. However, 64 classical logic is bivalent, therefore, is very limited when it comes to solving problems with 65 uncertainty in the data, which are most common in the real world. It is well known that artificial 66 intelligence logic requires. Because its classic shows too many shortcomings, it is necessary to 67 introduce more sophisticated tools, such as non-classical logics, including fuzzy logic, modal logic, 68 non-monotonic logic, the order-consistent, and so successively. 69 All in the same line: against dogmatism and dualistic view of the world: absolutely true 70 vs. false absolutely, black against white, good or bad by nature, Yes vs. No, 0 vs. 1, full vs. empty, 71 and so on. For this reason, we try to analyze here some of them, being very interesting both classical 72 and modern non-classical logics, focusing in particular on the theme of your reception, which was 73 quite different between countries. 74 At first (like almost all new ideas), the work of Lotfi A. Zadeh [72-73, 85], and other 75 precursors, had no scientific enthusiastic reception, but over time, these ideas gradually gained 76 acceptance in many cases, with the emergence of inspired followers. So these theories have grown 77 considerably in a way, being accepted by scientists today most professional. 78 One of the sharpest and persistent controversies was promoted by the so-called old 79 “patriarch” of the probabilistic Italian Academy, Bruno de Finetti (1906-1985), and his school. 80 However, some minor authors have followed repeating several objections, which are often based on 81 ignorance, prejudice and various misunderstandings. 82 Many statisticians were persuaded-and still are, by the influential work of the author 83 before mentioned about only one type of treatment of uncertainty, from a mathematical point of 84 view is needed, and therefore the fuzzy logic would be superfluous. It's kind of jealous rage after 85 finding that a potentially strong rival invades our “little plot”. 86 Let's look here not only the characteristics of each of this non-classical logic, jointly 87 with their interrelationships and possible applications to various fields, but also and mainly the lines 88 of resistance observed for its implementation and use in our universities to better understand its 89 development and progress. That is, Controversies and Disputes have arisen before its appearance, as 90 a remarkable example of the questions that often accompany any new scientific theories. But even 91 so, in this particular case have shown a fiercer fury, especially in Western countries, instead being 92 very well accepted, and naturally, in Asian countries, especially in Japan. Has the typical mental 93 blindness, some inertia opposed to change, or has been a problem of cultural tradition, imbued as we 94 are a strong Aristotelian tradition in our school systems...? Are all them different issues of great 95 interest for the advancement of science and the historical-philosophical analysis? 96 Axioms 2016, 5, x 3 of 5 97 The concept of validity is the more essential key to logic, because when we affirm the 98 validity of an argument, we are saying it is impossible that its conclusion is false if its premises are 99 true. This leads to two questions still controversial. So, what are the “bearers of truth”? The answers 100 are multiple judgments, statements, sentences, propositions. And what is truth? An issue far more 101 radical and it is no easy answer. Intuitively, we tend to assign to the truth two fundamental 102 properties, namely universality and objectivity. 103 We can all tell the truth, regardless of who, or what, we are. But both properties alone 104 do not guarantee anything, not even differentiate the mere opinion or belief of the truth. But we 105 cannot address an argument on the concept of truth, if we do not decide first what things can be true 106 or false. We say that propositions are those who can be true or false. Propositions are descriptions of 107 the world, are statements or denials of events in possible worlds. 108 The future contingencies were dealt with by Aristotle, as interpreted by Jan 109 Lukasiewicz, pushes us toward fatalism [5-40]. Accepting that a proposition about a future event is 110 true or false becomes necessary or impossible (respectively) the event expressed by the proposition. 111 The solution proposed by himself in his classic work is the acceptance of logic with three truth 112 values, which in addition to true and false, accepting an indeterminate truth value. Naturally the 113 laws of excluded and not stop working contradiction with the effects resulting therefrom as will be 114 seen later. 115 To search for the origins could lead too far and eventually disperse, which, as we know 116 is not very convenient for a job pretending to be research. So we will refer to these first signs that 117 appear in the East (China, India…), and then we may analyze the problem of “future contingents”, 118 treated by Aristotle in Peri hermeneias, or De Interpretatione (in Latin).
Recommended publications
  • Hubert Kennedy Eight Mathematical Biographies
    Hubert Kennedy Eight Mathematical Biographies Peremptory Publications San Francisco 2002 © 2002 by Hubert Kennedy Eight Mathematical Biographies is a Peremptory Publications ebook. It may be freely distributed, but no changes may be made in it. Comments and suggestions are welcome. Please write to [email protected] . 2 Contents Introduction 4 Maria Gaetana Agnesi 5 Cesare Burali-Forti 13 Alessandro Padoa 17 Marc-Antoine Parseval des Chênes 19 Giuseppe Peano 22 Mario Pieri 32 Emil Leon Post 35 Giovanni Vailati 40 3 Introduction When a Dictionary of Scientific Biography was planned, my special research interest was Giuseppe Peano, so I volunteered to write five entries on Peano and his friends/colleagues, whose work I was investigating. (The DSB was published in 14 vol- umes in 1970–76, edited by C. C. Gillispie, New York: Charles Scribner's Sons.) I was later asked to write two more entries: for Parseval and Emil Leon Post. The entry for Post had to be done very quickly, and I could not have finished it without the generous help of one of his relatives. By the time the last of these articles was published in 1976, that for Giovanni Vailati, I had come out publicly as a homosexual and was involved in the gay liberation movement. But my article on Vailati was still discreet. If I had written it later, I would probably have included evidence of his homosexuality. The seven articles for the Dictionary of Scientific Biography have a uniform appear- ance. (The exception is the article on Burali-Forti, which I present here as I originally wrote it—with reference footnotes.
    [Show full text]
  • Logique Combinatoire Et Physique Quantique
    Eigenlogic Zeno Toffano [email protected] CentraleSupélec, Gif-sur-Yvette, France Laboratoire des Signaux et Systèmes, UMR8506-CNRS Université Paris-Saclay, France Zeno Toffano : “Eigenlogic” 1 UNILOG 2018 (6th World Congress and School on Universal Logic), Workshop Logic & Physics, Vichy (F), June 22, 2018 statement facts in quantum physics Quantum Physics started in 1900 with the quantification of radiation (Planck’s constant ℎ = 6.63 10−34 J.s) It is the most successful theory in physics and explains: nuclear energy, semiconductors, magnetism, lasers, quantum gravity… The theory has an increasing influence outside physics: computer science, AI, communications, biology, cognition… Nowadays there is a great quantum revival (second quantum revolution) which addresses principally: quantum entanglement (Bell inequalites, teleportation…), quantum superposition (Schrödinger cat), decoherence non-locality, non- separability, non-contextuality, non-classicality, non-… A more basic aspect is quantification: a measurement can only give one of the (real) eigenvalues of an observable. The associated eigenvector is the resulting quantum state. Measurements on non-eigenstates are indeterminate, the outcome probability is given by the Born rule. The eigenvalues are the spectrum (e.g. energies for the Hamiltonian). In physics it is natural to “work” in different representation eignespaces (of the considered observable) e.g: semiconductors “make sense” in the reciprocal lattice (momentum space 푝 , spatial Fourier transform of coordinate
    [Show full text]
  • Computable Functions A
    http://dx.doi.org/10.1090/stml/019 STUDENT MATHEMATICAL LIBRARY Volume 19 Computable Functions A. Shen N. K. Vereshchagin Translated by V. N. Dubrovskii #AMS AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Editorial Board Robert Devaney Carl Pomerance Daniel L. Goroff Hung-Hsi Wu David Bressoud, Chair H. K. BepemarHH, A. Illem* BMHHCJIHMME ^YHKUMM MIIHMO, 1999 Translated from the Russian by V. N. Dubrovskii 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 03-01, 03Dxx. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Vereshchagin, Nikolai Konstantinovich, 1958- Computable functions / A. Shen, N.K. Vereshchagin ; translated by V.N. Dubrovskii. p. cm. — (Student mathematical library, ISSN 1520-9121 ; v. 19) Authors' names on t.p. of translation reversed from original. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-8218-2732-4 (alk. paper) 1. Computable functions. I. Shen, A. (Alexander), 1958- II. Title. III. Se• ries. QA9.59 .V47 2003 511.3—dc21 2002038567 Copying and reprinting. Individual readers of this publication, and nonprofit libraries acting for them, are permitted to make fair use of the material, such as to copy a chapter for use in teaching or research. Permission is granted to quote brief passages from this publication in reviews, provided the customary acknowledgment of the source is given. Republication, systematic copying, or multiple reproduction of any material in this publication is permitted only under license from the American Mathematical Society. Requests for such permission should be addressed to the Acquisitions Department, American Mathematical Society, 201 Charles Street, Providence, Rhode Island 02904- 2294, USA. Requests can also be made by e-mail to reprint-permissionQams.org. © 2003 by the American Mathematical Society.
    [Show full text]
  • July, and October
    ISSN 0739-4934 NEWSLETTER I {!STORY OF SCIENCE _iu_'i_i_u~-~-~-o~_9_N_u_M_B_E_R_3__________ S00ETY AAASREPORT HSSEXECUTIVE A Larger Role for History of Science COMMITTEE PRESIDENT in Undergraduate Education STEPHEN G. BRUSH, University of Maryland NORRISS S. HETHERINGTON VICE-PRESIDENT Office for the History of Science and Technology, SALLY GREGORY KOHLSTEDT, University of California, Berkeley University of Minnesota EXECU11VESECRETARY HISTORIANS OF SCIENCE have often been called to contribute to under­ MICHAEL M. SOKAL, Worcester graduate education. As HSS President Stephen G. Brush notes jNewsletter, Polytechnic Institute January 1990, pp. 1, 8-10), historically oriented science courses could be­ TREASURER come a valuable part of the core curriculum at many institutions, and fac­ MARY LOUISE GLEASON, New York City ulty at many colleges-especially science professors-have expressed strong EDITDR interest in using materials and perspectives from history of science. RONALD L. NUMBERS, University of We are now called again, this time by the American Association for the Wisconsin-Madison Advancement of Science. The Liberal Art of Science: Agenda for Action, published by the AAAS in May 1990, argues that science is one of the liberal The Newsletter of the History of Science arts and that it should be taught as such, as integrated into the totality of Society is published in January, April, July, and October. Regular issues are sent to individual human experience. This argument and advice may seem obvious to histori­ members of the Society who reside in North ans of science, but it is a revolutionary departure from tradition for many America. Airmail copies are sent to those scientists, and one that could transform both undergraduate education and members overseas who pay $5 yearly to cover postal costs: The Newsletter is available to the role of our discipline.
    [Show full text]
  • Hans Reichenbach
    Coming to America: Carnap, Reichenbach and the Great Intellectual Migration Part II: Hans Reichenbach Sander Verhaegh Tilburg University Ich habe das Gefühl, dass gerade Amerika mit seinem Sinn für das konkrete und technische mehr Verständnis haben müsste für meine naturwissenschaftliche Philosophie als Europa, wo noch immer die mystisch-metaphysischen Spekulationen als die wahre Philosophie angesehen werden. ⎯ Reichenbach to Sidney Hook, January 31, 1935 II.1. Introduction In the late-1930s, Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach, arguably the two most prominent scientific philosophers of their time, emigrated to the United States, escaping the increasingly perilous situation on the continent. Once in the U.S., the two significantly changed the American philosophical landscape. In this two-part paper, I reconstruct Carnap’s and Reichenbach’s surprisingly numerous interactions with American scholars throughout the 1920s and 1930s in order to better explain the transformation of analytic philosophy in the years before and after the Second World War. In the first part of this paper, I reconstructed Carnap’s contacts with American philosophers throughout the 1920s and 1930s. In this second part, I focus on Reichenbach’s interactions with the American philosophical community before he moved to the United States. I argue that some of Reichenbach’s work from the mid-1930s⎯ in particular Experience and Prediction (1938)⎯ can be better understood if we take into account the context in which it was written. This paper is structured as follows. After an overview of Reichenbach’s ignorance about Anglophone philosophy in the first stages of his academic career (§II.2), I reconstruct his ‘American turn’ in the early 1930s, focusing especially on the reception of his philosophy by a group of New York philosophers (§II.3).
    [Show full text]
  • Gender and Literature
    english edition 2 2017 Gender and Literature issue editor ANNA NASIŁOWSKA SŁAWOMIR BURYŁA Manly Fascism AGNIESZKA DAUKSZA KwieKulik as an Unknown: A Neo-Avant-gardist Laboratory of Experience ARÁNZAZU CALDERÓN PUERTA The Theme of Rape in Ida Fink’s Aryan Papers and Tadeusz Słobodzianek’s Our Class KRYSTYNA KŁOSIŃSKA The Secret of the Dulskis’ Establishment WOJCIECH ŚMIEJA A Piece of Fedora Cake: The Male-Centric Imagination of Jerzy Andrzejewski and the Scholarly Reconnaissance MONIKA ŚWIERKOSZ Arachne and Athena: Towards a Different Poetics of Women’s Writing teksty drugie · Institute of Literary Research Polish Academy of Science index 337412 · pl issn 0867-0633 EDITORIAL BOARD Agata Bielik-Robson (uk), Włodzimierz Bolecki, Maria Delaperrière (France), Ewa Domańska, Grzegorz Grochowski, Zdzisław Łapiński, Michał Paweł Markowski (usa), Maciej Maryl, Jakub Momro, Anna Nasiłowska (Deputy Editor-in-Chief), Leonard Neuger (Sweden), Ryszard Nycz (Editor-in-Chief), Bożena Shallcross (usa), Marta Zielińska, Tul’si Bhambry (English Translator and Language Consultant), Justyna Tabaszewska, Marta Bukowiecka (Managing Editor) ADVISORY BOARD Edward Balcerzan, Stanisław Barańczak (usa) , Małgorzata Czermińska, Paweł Dybel, Knut Andreas Grimstad (Norway), Jerzy Jarzębski, Bożena Karwowska (Canada), Krzysztof Kłosiński, Dorota Krawczyńska, Vladimir Krysinski (Canada), Luigi Marinelli (Italy), Arent van Nieukerken (the Netherlands), Ewa Rewers, German Ritz (Switzerland), Henryk Siewierski (Brasil), Janusz Sławiński , Ewa Thompson (usa), Joanna Tokarska-Bakir,
    [Show full text]
  • Theory and Experiment in the Work of Alonzo Church and Emil Post
    Theory and Experiment in the work of Alonzo Church and Emil Post Liesbeth De Mol Abstract While most mathematicians would probably agree that ‘experi- mentation’ together with an ‘empirical’ attitude – both understood in their most general sense – can be important methods of mathematical discovery, this is often obscured in the final presentation of the results for the sake of mathematical elegance. In this paper it will be shown how this “method” has played a significant role in the work of two ma- jor contributors to the rather abstract discipline called mathematical logic, namely Alonzo Church and Emil Post. 1 Introduction In this paper it will be investigated in what way ‘experiment’ and ‘em- pirical evidence’ played an important role in the work of two mathemati- cians/logicians – Alonzo Church and Emil Post. Both made significant con- tributions to computer science, although at the time they wrote down their results it didn’t even exist yet. In Sec. 2 it will be shown in what way Post 1 had to rely on the more ‘experimental’ work of testing out specific cases in order to get a grip on certain formal systems called tag systems and how this led him to the at that time innovating idea that the Entscheidungsproblem might not be solvable. In investigating Church’s work, it will be explained how the notion of ‘empirical evidence’ played a significant role in the de- velopment of his ideas leading to his seminal 1936 paper (Sec. 3). From this perspective it is interesting to confront what is here called Post’s second thesis with Church’s thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Kazimierz Kuratowski (Warsaw)
    Kazimierz Kuratowski (Warsaw) THE PAST AND THE PRESENT OF THE POLISH SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICS I am concentrating in this article on two main subjects. Firstly: I am trying to answer the question what brought about such an “explosion” of mathematics in a country in whose scientific tradition there was hardly any mathematics and which happened at the time when after an over-one-century-long foreign rule the nation was trying hard to reconstruct its now independent country, ravaged by the First World War. Secondly: was this explosion a short-lived enthusiasm or, on the contrary, the Polish school of .mathematics struck roots so deeply that it was sub­ sequently able to survive the cataclysm of the Second World War and rebuild in the new circumastances — in People’s Poland — the internationally re­ cognized edifice of Polish mathematics? There will be in this article no mathematical theorems, no definitions or geometrical constructions. I shall be trying to use the language which can be understood without mathematical qualifications. It is therefore my hope that this text will be intelligible not only to mathematicians.1 1. PRECURSORS OF THE POLISH SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICS It was the years 1918—1920 when the Polish School of Mathematics was emerging. Before describing this period and the subsequent years one should, I think, review, be it only summarily, the contemporary state of Polish mathematics. I am going to mention those of its representatives the majority of whom had in fact been active in the 19th century but who also worked in the 20th century and so could influence the formation of the School of Mathematics being thus its precursors as it were.
    [Show full text]
  • This Volume on the Vienna Circle's Influence in the Nordic Countries
    Vol. 8, no. 1 (2013) Category: Review essay Written by Carlo Penco This volume on the Vienna Circle’s influence in the Nordic countries gives a very interesting presentation of an almost forgotten landmark. In the years preceding the Second World War, European philosophy was at the high point of its intellectual vitality. Everywhere philosophical societies promoted a dense network of connections among scholars, with international meetings and strong links among individuals and associations. In this context, the Vienna Circle emerges as one of the many, also if probably the most well-known, centres of diffusion of a new style of philosophy, closely linked to the new logic and with a strongly empiricist attitude. At the same time, empiricism, formal logic and psychology constituted (and still constitute) the common background of most of the Nordic philosophers, a background which permitted them to develop connections with Vienna’s cultural environment (well known also for the work of psychologists such as Sigmund Freud, but also Charlotte and Karl Bühler). This piece of history, although limited to the connection between Nordic philosophy and Vienna Circle, helps to clarify the history of European philosophy, and the sharp difference of Nordic philosophy in respect of the development of philosophy in Southern and Central Europe in the half a century following the Second World War. The editors say in the introduction: . one of the least known networks of the Vienna Circle is the “Nordic connection”. This connection had a continuing influence for many of the coming decades, beginning with the earliest phase of the Vienna Circle and continuing with a number of adaptations and innovations well into contemporary times.
    [Show full text]
  • Contribution of Warsaw Logicians to Computational Logic
    axioms Article Contribution of Warsaw Logicians to Computational Logic Damian Niwi ´nski Institute of Informatics, University of Warsaw, 02-097 Warsaw, Poland; [email protected]; Tel.: +48-22-554-4460 Academic Editor: Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska Received: 22 April 2016; Accepted: 31 May 2016; Published: 3 June 2016 Abstract: The newly emerging branch of research of Computer Science received encouragement from the successors of the Warsaw mathematical school: Kuratowski, Mazur, Mostowski, Grzegorczyk, and Rasiowa. Rasiowa realized very early that the spectrum of computer programs should be incorporated into the realm of mathematical logic in order to make a rigorous treatment of program correctness. This gave rise to the concept of algorithmic logic developed since the 1970s by Rasiowa, Salwicki, Mirkowska, and their followers. Together with Pratt’s dynamic logic, algorithmic logic evolved into a mainstream branch of research: logic of programs. In the late 1980s, Warsaw logicians Tiuryn and Urzyczyn categorized various logics of programs, depending on the class of programs involved. Quite unexpectedly, they discovered that some persistent open questions about the expressive power of logics are equivalent to famous open problems in complexity theory. This, along with parallel discoveries by Harel, Immerman and Vardi, contributed to the creation of an important area of theoretical computer science: descriptive complexity. By that time, the modal m-calculus was recognized as a sort of a universal logic of programs. The mid 1990s saw a landmark result by Walukiewicz, who showed completeness of a natural axiomatization for the m-calculus proposed by Kozen. The difficult proof of this result, based on automata theory, opened a path to further investigations.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 on the Life and Work of Andrzej Mostowski? STANISŁAW
    On the life and work of Andrzej Mostowski ? STANISŁAW KRAJEWSKI and MARIAN SREBRNY (Warsaw, Poland) Andrzej Stanisław Mostowski was born on November 1, 1913, in Lwów. His father, Stanisław Mostowski, was a medical doctor and worked as an assistant at the Physical Chemistry Department of the University of Lwów; he was conscripted in 1914 as a military doctor and soon after died of typhus. The family had to be provided for by the mother, Zofia née Kramsztyk (1881-1963), who worked for many years in a bank. Andrzej (by his mother called Staszek after the father) had one sister Krystyna (after the war she settled abroad – first in France, then in Montreal). In the summer of 1914 Mostowski’s mother went with her children to Zakopane to spend holidays there; in the face of the outbreak of war and the death of the father they ? This text is translated from its Polish original published in “Wiadomo ści matematyczne”, Annales Societatis Mathematicae Polonae XXII.1 (1979), pp. 53-64, updated slightly where necessary. It is meant to present solely the events of Andrzej Mostowski’s biography. We do not discuss the content of his scientific output as such (other articles are devoted to it), but only provide some information on when he was involved in what and when his major works were created. The information included in this article have been taken from three following sources. Firstly, from the existing publications on the life and scientific output of Andrzej Mostowski. They are listed at the end of this text. The article by S.
    [Show full text]
  • Ontological, Epistemological, and Methodological Positions
    ONTOLOGICAL, EPISTEMOLOGICAL, AND METHODOLOGICAL POSITIONS James Ladyman INTRODUCTION This chapter summarises various important ontological, epistemological and methodological issues in the philosophy of science. Ontology is the theory of what exists and is the foremost concern of metaphysics, which is the study of the most fundamental questions about being and the nature of reality. Ontological issues in the philosophy of science may be specific to a particular special science, such as questions about the ontological status of biological species, or they may be more general, such as whether or not there are objective natural kinds. In the history of science ontological issues have often been of supreme importance; for example, whether or not atoms exist was a question that occupied many scientists in the nineteenth century. In what follows, some fundamental questions of ontology are discussed, some of which, such as those concerning laws of nature, are also ad- dressed in analytic metaphysics. A number of these issues also relate to debates in the foundations of physics about the ontological implications of our best physical theories. Readers who wish to know more about the philosophy of space and time and the nature of matter and motion should consult the companion volume to this on the philosophy of physics. Epistemology is the theory of knowledge and as such is concerned with such matters as the analysis of knowledge and its relationship to belief and truth, the theory of justification, and how to respond to the challenge of local scepticism, say about the past, or global scepticism, which suggests that there is no knowledge.
    [Show full text]