Developments in Non-Expected Utility Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Developments in Non-Expected Utility Theory Journal of Economic Literature Vol. XXXVIII (June 2000) pp. 332–382 Starmer: Developments in Non-Expected Utility Theory Developments in Non-Expected Utility Theory: The Hunt for a Descriptive Theory of Choice under Risk CHRIS STARMER1 1. Introduction stimulated developments in non-EU is surely of widespread concern: put bluntly, OW MANY THEORIES of decision the standard theory did not fit the facts. Hmaking under risk and uncertainty As the standard theory of individual can you think of? Readers of this article decision making, and as a core component will no doubt be familiar with Expected of game theory, EUT constitutes a key Utility Theory (EUT), the standard the- building block of a vast range of eco- ory of individual choice in economics. nomic theory. It should be no surprise, Many, I expect, will know of a few alter- therefore, that developing a better un- natives to this model. But how many, I derstanding of the determinants of indi- wonder, will be aware that these so- vidual choice behavior seemed a natural called non-expected utility models now research priority to many theorists. number well into double figures? An Around two decades of quite intensive enormous amount of theoretical effort research on the topic has generated a has been devoted towards developing al- great deal of theoretical innovation plus ternatives to EUT, and this has run a much richer body of evidence against hand-in-hand with an ongoing experi- which models can be judged. There can mental program aimed at testing those be few areas in economics that could theories. The good and proper division claim to have sustained such a rich in- of labor suggests that a relatively small teraction between theory and evidence group of specialists will be fully aware of in an ongoing effort to develop theories the details of this literature. At the same in closer conformity with the facts. time, the implications of developments Considered together, the accumulated in this field are of more than passing in- theory and evidence present an oppor- terest to the general economist, since what tunity to reflect on what has been 1 University of East Anglia, Norwich. I owe achieved. Perhaps the most obvious thanks to Colin Camerer, Robin Cubitt, Mark question to address to this literature is Machina, John Quiggin, Uzi Segal, Robert Sug- this: has it generated, or does it show den, Peter Wakker, and George Wu, plus an anonymous referee for extremely helpful com- the prospect of generating, a serious ments on and discussions around this paper. I am contender for replacing EUT, at least also grateful for support from the Economic and for certain purposes? If the question Social Research Council of the UK (Risk and Hu- man Behaviour Research Programme: Award No. seems disarmingly straightforward, pro- L211252053). viding a clear-cut answer will not be. 332 Starmer: Developments in Non-Expected Utility Theory 333 Identifying a “best theory” naturally re- experimental testing, (2) how new theo- quires judgements about the relative ries may help us to explain a range of importance of predictive accuracy, sim- phenomena “in the field,” and (3) plicity, tractability, and so on. Such whether non-expected utility theory of- judgments are complicated by the fact fers a viable alternative to EUT for that the evidence, much of which de- everyday theoretical use. In the penulti- rives from the experimental paradigm, mate Section 6, I discuss two emerging is open to different interpretations. lines of enquiry which I see as particu- In what follows, my aim will be to set larly exciting paths for future research. out what I take to have been key A final section offers some concluding theoretical developments in the area, to reflections. review the related evidence and draw conclusions about the current state of 2. Where It Began play and the prospects for the future. In Although the primary purpose of this doing so, rather than simply to present paper is to review alternatives to EUT, an exhaustive list of models, my aim will that theory provides the natural point of be to identify and discuss different departure, since most of the theories I modeling strategies picking specific will be discussing can be understood as models as illustrations. I also intend to generalizations of this base theory.2 narrow my sights in two significant re- EUT was first proposed by Daniel Ber- spects. First, my focus will be on de- noulli (1738) in response to an apparent scriptive as opposed to normative is- puzzle surrounding what price a reason- sues. Second, I will concentrate on the able person should be prepared to pay problem of modeling choices under risk to enter a gamble. It was the conven- as opposed to the more general cate- tional wisdom at the time that it would gory of uncertainty (the distinction is be reasonable to pay anything up to the explained in the next section). Clearing expected value of a gamble, but Ber- the ground in this way will, I hope, noulli presents this counterexample. A sharpen the focus on one central re- coin is flipped repeatedly until a head is search problem which continues to mo- produced; if you enter the game, you tivate much of the research in this receive a payoff of, say, $2n where n is arena: the endeavor to develop a “satis- the number of the throw producing the factory” account of actual decision be- first head. This is the so-called St. Pe- havior in situations of risk. It will be a tersburg game. It is easy to see that its personal view, but one which I hope expected monetary payoff is infinite, yet will help the interested nonspecialist Bernoulli believed most people would find a trail through this expansive and only be prepared to pay a relatively quite detailed literature. small amount to enter it, and he took this The paper is organized as follows. intuition as evidence that the “value” of Sections 2 and 3 set the scene with dis- a gamble to an individual is not, in gen- cussions of the standard theory and the eral, equal to its expected monetary evidence that prompted theorists to value. He proposed a theory in which look for alternatives. Section 4 provides individuals place subjective values, or the core overview of non-expected util- “utilities,” on monetary outcomes and ity theories. Section 5 seeks to evaluate what has been achieved so far, and in 2 I shall not dwell on this account of EUT. For those interested in further discussion an excellent three subsections I discuss (1) how new starting place is Paul Schoemaker’s (1982) review theories have fared in a second phase of in this journal. 334 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXVIII (June 2000) the value of a gamble is the expectation ternative models of choice, it will be of these utilities. While Bernoulli’s the- useful to present one set of axioms from ory—the first statement of EUT— which EUT can be derived. In the ap- solved the St. Petersburg puzzle, it did proach I adopt, at least to begin with, not find much favor with modern preferences are defined over prospects economists until the 1950s. This is where a prospect is to be understood as partly explained by the fact that, in the a list of consequences with associated form presented by Bernoulli, the theory probabilities. I will assume throughout presupposes the existence of a cardinal that all consequences and probabilities utility scale; an assumption that did not are known to the agent, and hence, in sit well with the drive towards ordinaliza- choosing among prospects, the agent tion during the first half of the twentieth can be said to confront a situation of century. risk (in contrast to situations of uncer- Interest in the theory was revived tainty in which at least some of the out- when John von Neumann and Oskar comes or probabilities are unknown). I Morgenstern (1947) showed that the ex- will use lowercase letters in bold (e.g. pected utility hypothesis could be de- q, r, s) to represent prospects, and the rived from a set of apparently appealing letter p to represent probabilities (take axioms on preference. Since then, nu- it that p always lies in the interval merous alternative axiomatizations have [0,1]). A given prospect may contain been developed, some of which seem other prospects as consequences, but highly appealing, some might even say assuming that such compound prospects compelling, from a normative point of can be reduced to simple prospects fol- view (see for example Peter Hammond lowing the conventional rules of prob- 1988).3 To the extent that its axioms can ability, any prospect q can be repre- be justified as sound principles of ra- sented by a probability distribution q = tional choice to which any reasonable (p1, . , pn) over a fixed set of pure person would subscribe, they provide consequences X = (x1, . , xn) where grounds for interpreting EUT norma- pi is the probability of xi, pi ≥ 0 for all i, tively (as a model of how people ought and Σipi = 1. Hence, the elements of X to choose) and prescriptively (as a prac- are to be understood as an exhaustive tical aid to choice). My concern, how- and mutually exclusive list of possible ever, is with how people actually choose, consequences which may follow from a whether or not such choices conform particular course of action. While this with a priori notions of rationality. Con- notation allows a prospect to be written sequently, I will not be delayed by simply as vector of probabilities (as q questions about whether particular axi- above) it will sometimes be useful to be oms can or cannot be defended as explicit about the consequences too sound principles of rational choice, and (e.g.
Recommended publications
  • Economics & Finance 2011
    Economics & Finance 2011 press.princeton.edu Contents General Interest 1 Economic Theory & Research 15 Game Theory 18 Finance 19 Econometrics, Mathematical & Applied Economics 24 Innovation & Entrepreneurship 26 Political Economy, Trade & Development 27 Public Policy 30 Economic History & History of Economics 31 Economic Sociology & Related Interest 36 Economics of Education 42 Classic Textbooks 43 Index/Order Form 44 TEXT Professors who wish to consider a book from this catalog for course use may request an examination copy. For more information please visit: press.princeton.edu/class.html New Winner of the 2010 Business Book of the Year Award, Financial Times/Goldman Sachs Fault Lines How Hidden Fractures Still Threaten the World Economy Raghuram G. Rajan “What caused the crisis? . There is an embarrassment of causes— especially embarrassing when you recall how few people saw where they might lead. Raghuram Rajan . was one of the few to sound an alarm before 2007. That gives his novel and sometimes surprising thesis added authority. He argues in his excellent new book that the roots of the calamity go wider and deeper still.” —Clive Crook, Financial Times Raghuram G. Rajan is the Eric J. Gleacher Distinguished Service Profes- “Excellent . deserve[s] to sor of Finance at the University of Chicago Booth School of Business and be widely read.” former chief economist at the International Monetary Fund. —Economist 2010. 272 pages. Cl: 978-0-691-14683-6 $26.95 | £18.95 Not for sale in India ForthcominG Blind Spots Why We Fail to Do What’s Right and What to Do about It Max H. Bazerman & Ann E.
    [Show full text]
  • The Allais Paradox: What It Became, What It Really Was, What It Now Suggests to Us
    Economics and Philosophy (2019), 35, 423–459 doi:10.1017/S0266267118000469 ARTICLE The Allais paradox: what it became, what it really was, what it now suggests to us Philippe Mongin GREGHEC, 1 rue de la Libération, F-78350 Jouy-en-Josas, France Email: [email protected] (Received 11 June 2018; revised 24 August 2018; accepted 27 August 2018; first published online 30 January 2019) Abstract Whereas many others have scrutinized the Allais paradox from a theoretical angle, we study the paradox from an historical perspective and link our findings to a suggestion as to how decision theory could make use of it today. We emphasize that Allais proposed the paradox as anormativeargument, concerned with ‘the rational man’ and not the ‘real man’,touse his words. Moreover, and more subtly, we argue that Allais had an unusual sense of the normative, being concerned not so much with the rationality of choices as with the rationality of the agent as a person. These two claims are buttressed by a detailed investigation – the first of its kind – of the 1952 Paris conference on risk, which set the context for the invention of the paradox, and a detailed reconstruction – also the first of its kind – of Allais’s specific normative argument from his numerous but allusive writings. The paper contrasts these interpretations of what the paradox historically represented, with how it generally came to function within decision theory from the late 1970s onwards: that is, as an empirical refutation of the expected utility hypothesis, and more specifically of the condition of von Neumann–Morgenstern independence that underlies that hypothesis.
    [Show full text]
  • I'll Have What She's Having: Reflective Desires and Consequentialism
    I'll Have What She's Having: Reflective Desires and Consequentialism by Jesse Kozler A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts with Honors Department of Philosophy in the University of Michigan 2019 Advisor: Professor James Joyce Second Reader: Professor David Manley Acknowledgments This thesis is not the product of solely my own efforts, and owes its existence in large part to the substantial support that I have received along the way from the many wonderful, brilliant people in my life. First and foremost, I want to thank Jim Joyce who eagerly agreed to advise this project and who has offered countless insights which gently prodded me to refine my approach, solidify my thoughts, and strengthen my arguments. Without him this project would never have gotten off the ground. I want to thank David Manley, who signed on to be the second reader and whose guidance on matters inside and outside of the realm of my thesis has been indispensable. Additionally, I want to thank Elizabeth Anderson, Peter Railton, and Sarah Buss who, through private discussions and sharing their own work, provided me with inspiration at times I badly needed it and encouraged me to think about previously unexamined issues. I am greatly indebted to the University of Michigan LSA Honors Program who, through their generous Honors Summer Fellowship program, made it possible for me to stay in Ann Arbor and spend my summer reading and thinking intentionally about these issues. I am especially grateful to Mika LaVaque-Manty, who whipped me into shape and instilled in me a work ethic that has been essential to the completion of this project.
    [Show full text]
  • Victory and Defeat in a Model of Behavior in Games and Toward Risk
    Victory and Defeat in a Model of Behavior in Games and Toward Risk William S. Neilson Department of Economics Texas A&M University College Station, TX 77843-4228 [email protected] January 24, 2000 The standard expected utility model is augmented by allowing individuals to receive additional utility in states in which they consider themselves victorious and to lose a utility increment in which they consider themselves defeated. The resulting event-dependent expected utility model is used to explain behavior in games and toward risk. In games, players consider themselves defeated when their monetary payoffs are low compared to their opponents' payoffs, and they consider themselves victorious when their payoffs are high, but not too high, compared to their opponents' payoffs. Under these conditions the model can accommodate behavior that has been interpreted elsewhere as inequity aversion, as well as cooperation in the prisoner's dilemma and in public good provision games. In situations of risk, individuals consider themselves victorious (defeated) when they receive an unlikely, avoidable, high (low) outcome. Under these conditions the model can accommodate such behavior as the Allais paradox, boundary effects, and simultaneous gambling and insurance. Keywords: Event-dependent preferences, behavioral economics, inequity aversion, Allais paradox, boundary effects JEL codes: D81, C72 I am grateful to Robert Slonim and participants at the 1999 Lonestars Conference for helpful comments, and to the Private Enterprise Research Center for financial support. 1. Introduction People like winning and dislike losing, yet this feature has never been incorporated into the study of games. This paper remedies that situation. It is assumed that besides the utility he receives from his monetary payoff, a player gets a positive utility increment in situations in which he considers himself victorious, and suffers a negative utility increment in any situation that he considers a defeat.
    [Show full text]
  • New Paradoxes in Intertemporal Choice
    Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011, pp. 122–129 New paradoxes in intertemporal choice Li-Lin Rao∗ Shu Li† Abstract Similar to research on risky choice, the traditional analysis of intertemporal choice takes the view that an individual behaves so as to maximize the discounted sum of all future utilities. The well-known Allais paradox contradicts the fundamental postulates of maximizing the expected value or utility of a risky option. We describe a violation of the law of diminishing marginal utility as well as an intertemporal version of the Allais paradox. Keywords: intertemporal choice, risky choice, cancellation. 1 Introduction The most prominent idea to account for these anoma- lies is the hyperbolic discounting model (Ainslie, 1975). In the field of intertemporal choice, the discounted-utility This model suggests that the discount rate is not dy- (DU) theory proposed by Paul Samuelson in 1937 was namically consistent but that the rate is higher be- presented not only as a valid normative standard but also tween the present and near future and lower between as a descriptive theory of actual intertemporal choice be- the near and far distant future. Numerous theories have havior (Frederick, Loewenstein, & O’Donoghue, 2002; been developed by transforming the discount function Samuelson, 1937). In its general form, the DU theory to other forms, from one-parameter hyperbolic discount- proposes that the value of an option, (x; t), is the prod- ing (Mazur, 1984) to generalized hyperbolic discounting uct of its present utility, U(x), and an exponential tem- (Loewenstein & Prelec, 1992), to proportional discount- poral discounting function, F(t), where t is the time at ing (Harvey, 1994), and to quasi-hyperbolic discount- which x is acquired.
    [Show full text]
  • Paradoxes Situations That Seems to Defy Intuition
    Paradoxes Situations that seems to defy intuition PDF generated using the open source mwlib toolkit. See http://code.pediapress.com/ for more information. PDF generated at: Tue, 08 Jul 2014 07:26:17 UTC Contents Articles Introduction 1 Paradox 1 List of paradoxes 4 Paradoxical laughter 16 Decision theory 17 Abilene paradox 17 Chainstore paradox 19 Exchange paradox 22 Kavka's toxin puzzle 34 Necktie paradox 36 Economy 38 Allais paradox 38 Arrow's impossibility theorem 41 Bertrand paradox 52 Demographic-economic paradox 53 Dollar auction 56 Downs–Thomson paradox 57 Easterlin paradox 58 Ellsberg paradox 59 Green paradox 62 Icarus paradox 65 Jevons paradox 65 Leontief paradox 70 Lucas paradox 71 Metzler paradox 72 Paradox of thrift 73 Paradox of value 77 Productivity paradox 80 St. Petersburg paradox 85 Logic 92 All horses are the same color 92 Barbershop paradox 93 Carroll's paradox 96 Crocodile Dilemma 97 Drinker paradox 98 Infinite regress 101 Lottery paradox 102 Paradoxes of material implication 104 Raven paradox 107 Unexpected hanging paradox 119 What the Tortoise Said to Achilles 123 Mathematics 127 Accuracy paradox 127 Apportionment paradox 129 Banach–Tarski paradox 131 Berkson's paradox 139 Bertrand's box paradox 141 Bertrand paradox 146 Birthday problem 149 Borel–Kolmogorov paradox 163 Boy or Girl paradox 166 Burali-Forti paradox 172 Cantor's paradox 173 Coastline paradox 174 Cramer's paradox 178 Elevator paradox 179 False positive paradox 181 Gabriel's Horn 184 Galileo's paradox 187 Gambler's fallacy 188 Gödel's incompleteness theorems
    [Show full text]
  • Learning in the Allais Paradox
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Erasmus University Digital Repository J Risk Uncertainty (2006) 33:155–164 DOI 10.1007/s11166-006-0390-3 Learning in the Allais paradox Gijs van de Kuilen · Peter P. Wakker∗ C Springer Science + Business Media, LLC 2006 Abstract Whereas both the Allais paradox, the first empirical challenge of the classical ra- tionality assumptions, and learning have been the focus of many experimental investigations, no experimental study exists today into learning in the pure context of the Allais paradox. This paper presents such a study. We find that choices converge to expected utility maxi- mization if subjects are given the opportunity to learn by both thought and experience, but less so when they learn by thought only. To the extent that genuine preferences should be measured with proper learning and incentives, our study gives the first pure demonstration that irrationalities such as in the Allais paradox are less pronounced than often thought. Keywords Learning . Rational choice . Allais paradox . Nonexpected utility JEL Classification D81 . D83 The first empirical challenge of the classical rationality assumption in economics was made by Allais (1953), through his famous choice paradox for decision under risk. It showed that the majority of people systematically violate expected utility, the model commonly accepted as the hallmark of rationality for choice under risk in those days. Allais’ paradox initiated a flurry of empirical demonstrations that more and more basic rationality assumptions are violated empirically (Camerer, 1995). To model these findings, theories were developed that explicitly depart from rational choice and only pretend to be descriptive, such as prospect theory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979).
    [Show full text]
  • How Economists Came to Accept Expected Utility Theory: the Case of Samuelson and Savage
    Journal of Economic Perspectives—Volume 30, Number 2—Spring 2016—Pages 219–236 Retrospectives How Economists Came to Accept Expected Utility Theory: The Case of Samuelson and Savage Ivan Moscati This feature addresses the history of economic terms and ideas. The hope is to deepen the workaday dialogue of economists, while perhaps also casting new light on ongoing questions. If you have suggestions for future topics or authors, please contact Joseph Persky, Professor of Economics, University of Illinois, Chicago, at [email protected]. Introduction In the expected utility approach to decision-making under risk, the utility of a risky prospect is given by the sum of the utilities u of the alternative possible outcomes of the prospect, each weighted by the probability that the outcome will occur. Thus, for example, the utility of a lottery yielding either a trip to London with probability p or a payment of $2,000 with probability (1 p) is given by − (u(trip to London) p) (u($2,000) (1 p)). According to expected utility × + × − theory, the decision maker will choose among these risky prospects, or lotteries, and will choose the one with the highest expected utility. This theory dominated the economic analysis of individual decision-making under risk from the early 1950s to the 1990s. Beginning in the late 1970s, the accumulation of robust experi- mental evidence against the expected utility hypothesis prompted decision theorists ■ Ivan Moscati is Associate Professor of Economics, University of Insubria, Varese, Italy. He also teaches History of Economics at Bocconi University, Milan, Italy. His email address is [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • List of Paradoxes 1 List of Paradoxes
    List of paradoxes 1 List of paradoxes This is a list of paradoxes, grouped thematically. The grouping is approximate: Paradoxes may fit into more than one category. Because of varying definitions of the term paradox, some of the following are not considered to be paradoxes by everyone. This list collects only those instances that have been termed paradox by at least one source and which have their own article. Although considered paradoxes, some of these are based on fallacious reasoning, or incomplete/faulty analysis. Logic • Barbershop paradox: The supposition that if one of two simultaneous assumptions leads to a contradiction, the other assumption is also disproved leads to paradoxical consequences. • What the Tortoise Said to Achilles "Whatever Logic is good enough to tell me is worth writing down...," also known as Carroll's paradox, not to be confused with the physical paradox of the same name. • Crocodile Dilemma: If a crocodile steals a child and promises its return if the father can correctly guess what the crocodile will do, how should the crocodile respond in the case that the father guesses that the child will not be returned? • Catch-22 (logic): In need of something which can only be had by not being in need of it. • Drinker paradox: In any pub there is a customer such that, if he or she drinks, everybody in the pub drinks. • Paradox of entailment: Inconsistent premises always make an argument valid. • Horse paradox: All horses are the same color. • Lottery paradox: There is one winning ticket in a large lottery. It is reasonable to believe of a particular lottery ticket that it is not the winning ticket, since the probability that it is the winner is so very small, but it is not reasonable to believe that no lottery ticket will win.
    [Show full text]
  • Bilan Scientifique Annexes
    BILAN SCIENTIFIQUE ANNEXES 2007 ­ 2012 PARIS JOURDAN SCIENCES ECONOMIQUES – UMR8545 CNRS – ENS – EHESS – ECOLE DES PONTS PARIS TECH – INRA Bilan scientifique - Annexes UMR8545 | 2007 - 2012 Sommaire ANNEXE 1 : LISTES DES PUBLICATIONS ET DES PRODUCTIONS........................................................................ - 3 - Liste des publications .............................................................................................................................- 5 - PSE Working Papers............................................................................................................................- 41 - ANNEXE 2 : RAYONNEMENT ET ATTRACTIVITE ECONOMIQUES....................................................................... - 57 - Conférences EEP.................................................................................................................................- 61 - Colloques et workshops organisés ou co-organisés par un chercheur de PSE ..................................- 64 - Séminaires – Groupes de travail organisés par PSE...........................................................................- 71 - Invités à PSE (hors invités seminaires)..............................................................................................- 170 - Existence de collaborations suivies avec d’autres laboratoires .........................................................- 178 - Participation à des comités éditoriaux, à des comités scientifiques de colloques ou de congrès, à des instances d’expertise scientifique..............................................................................-
    [Show full text]
  • The Economics of Risk
    Upjohn Press Upjohn Research home page 1-1-2003 The Economics of Risk Donald J. Meyer Western Michigan University Follow this and additional works at: https://research.upjohn.org/up_press Part of the Economics Commons, and the Insurance Commons Citation Meyer, Donald J., ed. 2003. The Economics of Risk. Kalamazoo, MI: W.E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research. https://doi.org/10.17848/9781417505937 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 4.0 License. This title is brought to you by the Upjohn Institute. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Economics of Risk The Economics of Risk Donald J. Meyer Editor 2003 W.E.Upjohn Institute for Employment Research Kalamazoo, Michigan Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data © 2003 W.E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research 300 S. Westnedge Avenue Kalamazoo, Michigan 49007–4686 The facts presented in this study and the observations and viewpoints expressed are the sole responsibility of the authors. They do not necessarily represent positions of the W.E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research. Cover design by Alcorn Publication Design. Index prepared by Diane Worden. Printed in the United States of America. Printed on recycled paper. Contents Introduction 1 Donald J. Meyer Western Michigan University 1 Risk and Risk Management 9 Keith J. Crocker University of Michigan Business School 2 States of the World and the State of Decision Theory 17 Mark J. Machina University of California, San Diego 3 Gambling with the Future 51 William R. Eadington University of Nevada, Reno 4 Common Value Auctions and the Winner’s Curse 65 John H.
    [Show full text]
  • Activities 2010
    Activities 2010 Activities - 2010 Table of contents General Information .........................................................................................................................4 Unit Description ....................................................................................................................4 General Objectives .............................................................................................................5 Main Achievements ............................................................................................................7 Integrative/multidisciplinary activities ..............................................................................8 Outreach activities ........................................................................................................... 10 Outreach/Science and Society ..................................................................................... 11 Networking Actions .......................................................................................................... 13 Training Activities ............................................................................................................... 14 Organization of International Events ............................................................................. 15 Internal Services and Resources .................................................................................... 16 External Services and Resources ...................................................................................
    [Show full text]