Victor Kraft Bibliography

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Victor Kraft Bibliography VICTOR KRAFT BIBLIOGRAPHY 19040 'Das Problem der Aussenwelt',Archiv fur Philosophie, 2. Abteilung: Archiv fUr systematische Philosophie. Neue Falge 10,269-313. 1906 a 'Kind und Kunst', Zeitschrift fiir das Kindergartenwesen 25, 133-135. 1911 a 'Grundformen def Weltanschauung', Das Wissen /iir aile. Volkstumliche Hochschulvortriige und gemeinverstiindliche Einzeldarstellungen aus allen Gebieten des Wissens. Herausgegeben von der Vereinigung 6sterreichischer Hochschuldocenten 11, 141-145, 164-168, 184-188, 206-209, 229-231. 1912 a Weltbegriff und Erkenntnisbegriff. Eine Erkenntnistheoretische Untersuchung, Leipzig. 'Meter und Elle in ihrer geistesgeschichtlichen Bedeutung', Das Wissen fUr aile. Volkstiimliche Hochschulvortrage undgemeinverstdndliche Einzeldarstellungen aus allen Gebieten des Wissens. Herausgegeben von der Vereinigung oster­ reichischer Hochschuldocenten 12,41-45. 'Jean Jacques Rousseau. Zu seinem zweihundertsten Geburtstage', Das Wissen fUr aile 12,221-225. d 'Zu Jean Jacques Rousseaus zweihundertstem Gebwtstage', Zeitschrift fiir das Kindergartenwesen 31, 133-136, 154-160. 1914 a 'Gegenstand, Aufgaben und Methoden der Geographie als Wissenschaft', in Handbuch der geographischen Wissenschaft t, edited by O. Kende, Vienna, pp.I-8. 1915a 'Philosophie und Geschichte der Philosophie', Zeitschrift fUr Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 157,4-20. 1918 a 'Ein osterreichischer Denker: Ernst Mach', Donauland 2, 1209-1213. 1922a 'Die Philosophie in der Volksbildung', Volksbildung. Monatsschrift fUr die Fdrderung des Volksbildungswesens in Oste"eich 3,239-24 7. 1924a 'Von Kelsen zu Husser!' Schreiers Versuch einer philosophischen Fundierung der "reinen Rechtslehre''', Gerichtszeitung 75, 70-72. 1925a 'Die Grundformen der wissenschaftlichen Methoden', Sitzungsberichte der dste"eichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. philos.-histor. Klasse 203, 1-104 (second edition 1973b). 19280 'Ethik als Wissenschaft"lecture delivered in Vienna in 1928. in Wissenschaft­ lischer lahresbericht der Philosophischen Gesellschaft an der Universitiit zu Wien - Ortsgruppe Wien der Kant-Gesellschaft fiir die Vereinsjahre 1927/28, Vienna, pp. 35-38. 1929a 'Die Geographie als Wissenschaft', in Enzyklopiidie der Erdkunde. I. Teil: Methodenlehre der Geographie, edited by O. Kende, Leipzig and Vienna, pp.I-22. 'Intuitives Verstehen in der Geschichtswissenschaft' ,Mitteilungen des Institutes [fir 6sterreichische Geschichtsforschung, Ergiinzungsband Xl, Oswald Redlich zugeeignet anliisslich seines 70. Geburtstages, edited by W. Bauer, Innsbruck, pp.I-30. 188 VICTOR KRAFT BIBLIOGRAPHY 189 1935a eDie empirischen Grundlagen der Wertlehre', lecture delivered in Vienna in 1934, in Wi•• enschaftlicher Jahre.bericht der PhilollOphischen Gesellschaft an der Univemtiit zu Wien - Ortsgruppe Wien der Kant·Gesel/schaft fiir die Vereinsjahre 1933/34 und 1934/35, Vienna, pp. 18-23. 1936_ 'Moritz Schlick (1882-1936)',Philo.ophia 1,323-330. 1937 a Die Grundillgen einer wissenschaftlichen Wertlehre, Schriften ZUI wissenschaft· lichen Weltauffassung XI, edited by P. Frank and M. Schlick, Vienna (second edition 1951a). 1940a 'Die GrOsse eines Korpers gemass der Relativitatstheorie', Theoria 6, 58-66. b 'tlber Moralbegriindung', Theoria 6,191-226. 1946_ 'Logik und Erfahrung', Theoria 12,205-210. 1947a Mathematik, Logik und Erfahrung, Vienna (second edition 1970d). b 'Der Wiener Kreis und seine phDosophische Bedeutung', Wiener Zeltschrift fiir Philosophie, Psychologie, Padagogik I, 81-99. 1949_ 'Kants Erkenntnistheorie der Mathematik kritisch betrachtet', in Philo.ophie der Wirklichkeitsniihe. Festschrift zum 80. Geburtstag Robert Reininger., Vienna, pp. 134-145. 1950_ 'Die modeme und die traditionelle Logik', Wissenschaft und Weltbild 3, 28-34. b Einjiihrung in die PhilollOphie. Philosophie, Weltanschauung, Wis ..nschaft, Vienna (second edition 1967a). Der Wiener Kreis. DeT Ursprung des Neopofitivismus. Ein Kapitel der jiingsten PhUosophiegeschichte, Vienna (second edition 1968a; Eng. trans!. 1953b). d 'Das Problem der Willensfreiheit', Wiener Zeitschrift fiir Philosophie, Psycho· logie, Piidagogik 3, 1-13. 1951_ Die Grund/agen einer wissenschaftlichen Wertlehre, second (revised and en1asged) edition, Vienna (IlISt edition 1937a; Eng. trans!. 1981_). 1952a 'Franz Brentano', Wiener Zeitschrift fiir Philosophie, Psychologie, Padagogik 4, 1-8. b 'Die Grund1agen fliI die Anwendung der Mathematik auf die Erfahrungswelt', Die Pyramide 2, 206-208. 1953a 'Kritik des Eudaimonismus·. Anzeiger deT 6sten-eichischen Akademie deT Wissen.chaften, philo•. ·histor. Klasse 90, 345-355. b The Vienna Circle. The Origin of Neo·Positivism, New York (Eng. transl. by Arthur Pap of 1950c). 1954_ 'Dingle.. "Methodische Philosophie" und der Neopositivismus', Zeitschrift fiir philosophische Forschung 8, 259-266. b 'Die Einheit der Wissenschaften', Wiener Zeitschrift fiir Philosophie, Psycho· logie, Piidagogik 5, 7-16. c 'Del Positivismus', Studiurn Generale 7, 73~ 79. 1955a 'Del Wissenschaftscharakter der Erkenntnislehrc', in Actes du 2e Congres International de l'Union Intematio1lllie de Philosophie des Sciences, Zurich 1954, Neuch4tel, pp. 85-94. b 'Die Geschichtsforschung als exakte Wissenschaft', Anzeiger du oste"eichi­ schen Akademie der Wissenschaften, philos.·histor. Klasse 92, 239-251. (reprint 1965d). 1956a "Wissenschaft und Weltanschauung', Anzeiger deT oste"eichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, philos,./Jistor. Klasse 93, 239-251. 190 VICTOR KRAFT BIBLIOGRAPHY b 'Die Einheit der Wissenschaften', Studium Generale 9, 333-339. 'Die Stenung des Menschen in del Welt', Mitteilungen der anthropologischen Ge ..llochaft in Wien 86, 85-86, 19590 'Die Weltanschauungen del Kulturvolker', lecture delivered in Vienna in 1957, supplement (8 pages) to: Mitteilungen des Instituts fiir Wis ..nschaft und Kunst 2, Vienna, 1960a Erkenntnislehre, Vienna. b 'Was ist Wahrheit? Der Wahrheitsbegriff in Wisaenschaft und Philosophle', in Der Mensch, 80in Wesen und sein Wirken. Eine Vortragsreihe, herausgegeben .om Institut fiir Wissenschaft und Kunst, Vienna, pp. 77-85. 'Vorwort' ('Preface') to: Wesensz(ige der europiiischen Geschichte. Vortriige. Von Franz Heilsberg, edited by V. Kraft, Vienna, pp. 5-6. d 'Kano die Deduktion Neue. ergeben?', in Atti del XII Congresso InternJlzionale di Filosojia, Venezia 1958, V, Firenze, pp. 307-313. 1961a 'Pessimismus und Optimismus', in Erkenntnis und Erziehung. Festschrift fUr Richard Meister, Vienna, pp. 66-7S. b 'Ober den Sinn des Lebens', Anzeiger der Dsterreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, phi/os.·histor. Klasse 98, 29-41. 'Developpement et Evolution du Positivisme' in Les Grands Courant! de III Pensee Mondiale Contemporaine II, edited by M. F. Sci.cca, Milan, pp. 817- 870. 1962a 'Die Akademie der Wissenschaften', in Mensch und Staat. Handbuch der osterrelchischen Politik I, edited by B. Pittermann, Vienna, pp. 461-468. b 'Erkenntnis und Moralbegriindung', lecture delivered in Vienna in 1962, Anzeiger der osterreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, philos.-histor. KlIlsse 99, 123. 1963a 'Rationale Moralbegriindung', Sitzungsberichte der oste"eichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, phi/os.·histor. Klas .. 242, 1-65. 1964a 'Die Reh.bUitierung der Metaphysik in der deutschen Philosophie 'des 20. Jahrhunderts', in Danish Yearbook ofPhilosophy I, Copenhagen, pp. 1-13. b 'Nachwort' ('Postscriptum') to: K. D. Heller, Ernst Mach. Wegbereiter der modernen Physik. Mit ausgewiihlten Kapiteln aus seinem Werk, Vienna and NewYork,pp.168-169. 1965a 'Die -Begriindung von Aussagen', in The Foundations of Statements and Decisions, Warsaw 1965, pp. 21-26. b 'Der Wiener Kreis. Die Spr.chanalyse', Wissenschaft und Weltbild 18, 14-25. c 'Die Philosophie und die neue Logik', Studiurn Generale 18,497 -S09. d 'Die Geschichtsforschung als exakte Wissenschaft', in Logik der Sozialwissen­ schaften, edited by E. Topitsch, Cologne and Berlin, pp. 72-82 (reprint of I95Sb). 1966a 'The Problem of Induction', in Mind. Matter. and Method. Essays in Philos· ophy and Science in Honor of Herbert Feigl, edited by P. Feyer.bend and G. Maxwell, Minneapolis, Minn. 1966, pp. 306-318. b 'Ernst Mach als Philosoph', Almanach der osterreichischen Akademie de, Wissenschaften 116,373-387. 'Vorwort' ('Preface') to: H. Scbleichert, Elemente der physikalischen Seman· tik, Vienn., pp. 7-9. VICTOR KRAFT BIBLIOGRAPHY 191 1967 a Einfohrung in die Philosophie. Philosoph ie, Weltanschauung, Wissenschaft, second (enlarged) edition, Vienna and New York (fIrSt edition 1950b). 1968 a Der Wiener Kreis. Der Ursprung des Neopodtivismus. Ein KapUel der jungsten Philosophiegeschichte, second (enlarged and revised) edition, Vienna and New York (first edition 1950c). Die Gnmd/agen der Erkenntnis und der Moral; Erfahnmg und Denken. Schrif­ ten ZUI Forderung del Beziehungen zwischen Phiiosophie uDd Einzelwissen­ schaften 18, edited by V. Kraft among others, Berlin. 'Del Wiener Kreis', in Philosophie in Osterreich, edited by L. Gabriel and J. Mader, Vienna, pp. 57-76. 19690 'Das Problem der Willensfreiheit in Moral und Recht', Oste"eichische Zeit· schrift /iir 6ffentliches Recht 19,405-413. 19700 'Das Problem der Induktion', Zeitschri!t /iir allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 1, 71-82. 'Are All Laws of Nature Only Probable?', L ~ge de /0 Science 3, 247~254. c 'Recht und Moral', !uristische Blatter 92,543-544. d Mathematik, Logik und ErfahlUng, Library of Exact Philosophy II, second (revised) edition, Vienna and New York (first edition 1947a). 1971 a 'Dreierlei Philosophiegeschichte', in Philomathes. Studies and Essays in the Humanities
Recommended publications
  • Arthur Pap Archive I. Manuscripts and Typscripts I.1
    Arthur Pap Archive Inventory of the „Nachlass“ of Arthur Pap at the Institute Vienna Circle, by Christoph Limbeck-Lilienau I. Manuscripts and Typscripts I.1 Pap „Absolute Motion and the Clock Paradox“ [1953], 34 p., A4, Typscript Box 1/Folder 1 “Are Physical Magnitudes Operally Definable?” 1959, Typscript with a few handwritten corrections, 19 p., A4, 9 carbon copies. Published in: Box 1/2 Abstract for: “Are Physical Magnitudes Operally Definable?” 1956, Typscript, 3 p., A4 Box 1/3 “Are Physical Magnitudes Operationally Definable?” 1959, Typscript, 19 p., A4, Typscript, Box 1/3 “Are Physical Magnitudes Operationally Definable?” 1959, Typscript, 19 p., A4, Typscript, 8 Copies Box 1/3 “Basic Propositions, Certainty, and Intersubjective Language” [1958], Typscript, 21 p., A4 Box 1/4 “Basic Propositions, Certainty, and Intersubjective Language” [1960], Typscript, marginal handwritten corrections, 21 p., A4 Box 1/4 “Belief and Natural-Language-Intentions” No Date, Typscript, 5 p., A4 (from “Manila Folder”) Box 1/4 Abstract for: “Belief and Proposition” No Date, Typscript, 1 p., A4 Box 1/ 4 “Comments on M. Scriven´s `Certain Weaknesses in the Deductive Model of Explanation´” [1955], 5 p., A4, Typscript, Copy, (Original in the letter of M. Scriven from May 9, 1955) Scriven´s Reply is “Reply to Pap General Points-Specific Points”. Box 1/ 4 Critical Comments on Paul Weiss´ “Real Possibility” No Date, 3 p., A4, Typescript Box 1/ 4 “Mr. O´Connor on Incompatibility” [1955 or later], 4 p., A4, Typescript Box 1/ 4 Criticism of Sellars´ “On the Logic of Complex particulars” (from a letter of July 28) No Date, Typscript, 3 p., A4 (from “Manila Folder”) Box 1/4 1 “The Dispensibility of Material Implication for Applied Logic” 1959, Typescript with handwritten additions, 13 p., A4 (Contains a letter of rejection by John Rawls, see Correspondence “Rawls” (No.
    [Show full text]
  • Passmore, J. (1967). Logical Positivism. in P. Edwards (Ed.). the Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Vol. 5, 52- 57). New York: Macmillan
    Passmore, J. (1967). Logical Positivism. In P. Edwards (Ed.). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Vol. 5, 52- 57). New York: Macmillan. LOGICAL POSITIVISM is the name given in 1931 by A. E. Blumberg and Herbert Feigl to a set of philosophical ideas put forward by the Vienna circle. Synonymous expressions include "consistent empiricism," "logical empiricism," "scientific empiricism," and "logical neo-positivism." The name logical positivism is often, but misleadingly, used more broadly to include the "analytical" or "ordinary language philosophies developed at Cambridge and Oxford. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND The logical positivists thought of themselves as continuing a nineteenth-century Viennese empirical tradition, closely linked with British empiricism and culminating in the antimetaphysical, scientifically oriented teaching of Ernst Mach. In 1907 the mathematician Hans Hahn, the economist Otto Neurath, and the physicist Philipp Frank, all of whom were later to be prominent members of the Vienna circle, came together as an informal group to discuss the philosophy of science. They hoped to give an account of science which would do justice -as, they thought, Mach did not- to the central importance of mathematics, logic, and theoretical physics, without abandoning Mach's general doctrine that science is, fundamentally, the description of experience. As a solution to their problems, they looked to the "new positivism" of Poincare; in attempting to reconcile Mach and Poincare; they anticipated the main themes of logical positivism. In 1922, at the instigation of members of the "Vienna group," Moritz Schlick was invited to Vienna as professor, like Mach before him (1895-1901), in the philosophy of the inductive sciences. Schlick had been trained as a scientist under Max Planck and had won a name for himself as an interpreter of Einstein's theory of relativity.
    [Show full text]
  • Nikolay Milkov and Volker Peckhaus (Eds.): the Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science 273
    556 B OOK R EVIEWS Nikolay Milkov and Volker Peckhaus (eds.): The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science 273. Springer, Dordrecht, 2013, x+332 pages During the last few decades, historians and philosophers of science radically changed our perspective on logical empiricism in general, and on the Vienna Circle in particular. Though there are still some members of the Circle who did not get much attention (Victor Kraft, Richard von Mises, Felix Kaufmann, Josef Schächter etc.), we are in a quite good position to judge many of their efforts. On the other hand, our historical understanding of logical empiricism in general leaves some- thing to be desired due to the circumstances that the so-called “Berlin Group” is underestimated in the literature. The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism, edited by Nikolay Milkov and Volker Peckhaus, is meant to bring attention to the German wing of logical empiricism, thus doing justice to that forgotten projects and figures who had (in)directly an important influence on the philosophy of science in the United States after World War II. Among the most important members, one finds Hans Reichenbach, Kurt Grelling, Walter Dubislav, Paul Oppenheim, Olaf Helmer, Kurt Lewin, and Carl Gustav Hempel. The collection is devoted to their ideas and con- text in the European philosophy of science scene. Part 1 is an introductory chapter composed of two papers: a longer article by Nikolay Milkov about the ‘affinities and divergences’ between the Vienna Circle and the Berlin Group. Though Milkov provides many important details and no- tions, his explanations are lacking sometimes, but I will come back to that later.
    [Show full text]
  • Prof. Dr. Victor Kraft (4.7.1880 – 3.1.1975)
    Prof. Dr. Victor Kraft (4.7.1880 – 3.1.1975) Victor Kraft, der bis heute als einer der bedeutendsten Vertreter der wissenschaftlichen Philosophie gilt und zu dessen Schülern Paul Feyerabend und Ingeborg Bachmann zählen, wurde am 4. Juli 1880 als Sohn des Bürgerschuldirektors Josef Kraft in Wien geboren.1 Hier absolvierte er auch das Realgymnasium (mit Griechisch) im 6. Bezirk und legte im Jahre 1899 die Matura mit Auszeichnung ab. Er studierte an der Universität Wien Geschichte, Geographie und Philosophie. Darüberhinaus hörte er Vorlesungen in Botanik, Kunst- geschichte und Volkswirtschaftslehre. Die ursprünglich angestrebte Lehramtsprüfung legte er nicht mehr ab, da er sich in der Folge ganz dem Studium der Philosophie zuwandte. Im Jahre 1903 promovierte er mit einer philosophischen Dissertation zum Thema „Die Erkenntnis der Außenwelt“.2 Danach setzte Kraft seine Ausbildung für ein Semester lang in Berlin fort, wo er Vorlesungen und Seminare bei Wilhelm Dilthey, Georg Simmel, Carl Stumpf, Heinrich Wölfflin und anderen besuchte. Im Herbst 1904 wurde er zum Militärdienst einberufen, wurde aber wegen eines Herzleidens vorzeitig entlassen und mußte im Frühjahr 1905 einen längeren Kuraufenthalt in Lussin antreten. Seine Berufslaufbahn begann er im Jahre 1911 als Praktikant an der Universitäts- bibliothek Wien, im nächsten Jahr wurde er dort angestellt. Im gleichen Jahr erschien auch seine Habilitationsschrift zum Thema „Weltbegriff und Erkenntnisbegriff“. Im Jahre 1914 erhielt er die Venia legendi für theoretische Philosophie und hielt von da an als Privatdozent Vorlesungen u.a. aus den Gebieten Erkenntnislehre und Methodologie. Im Jahre 1922 erfolgte die Ernennung zum Staatsbibliothekar I. Klasse. Zwei Jahre später wurde ihm der Titel eines außerordentlichen Professors verliehen.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of Karl Popper
    P1: JZX 0521839467Agg.xml CY443/Keuth 0521839467 August 25, 2004 16:38 The Philosophy of Karl Popper HERBERT KEUTH Eberhard Karls Universitat,¨ Tubingen¨ iii P1: JZX 0521839467Agg.xml CY443/Keuth 0521839467 August 25, 2004 16:38 published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, ny 10011-4211, usa 477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, vic 3207, Australia Ruiz de Alarcon´ 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org Die Philosophie Karl Poppers C J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck) 2000 English translation C Herbert Keuth 2005 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published in German in 2000 English edition first published 2005 Printed in the United States of America Typeface itc New Baskerville 10/13 pt. System LATEX 2ε [tb] A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication data Keuth, Herbert, 1940– [Philosophie Karl Poppers. English] The philosophy of Karl Popper / Herbert Keuth. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and indexes. isbn 0-521-83946-7 – isbn 0-521-54830-6 (pbk.) 1. Popper, Karl Raimund, Sir, 1902–1994 I. Title. b1649.p64k4813 2004 192 – dc22 2004045179 isbn 0 521 83946 7 hardback isbn 0 521 54830 6 paperback iv P1: JZX 0521839467Agg.xml CY443/Keuth 0521839467 August 25, 2004 16:38 Contents List of Abbreviations page xiii Preface xv Introduction 1 part i.
    [Show full text]
  • Against Method (AM for Short)
    First published by New Left Books, 1975 Revised edition published by Verso 1988 Third edition published by Verso 1993 © Paul Feyerabend 1975, 1988, 1993 All rights reserved Verso UK: 6 Meard Street, London WIV 3HR USA: 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001-2291 Verso is the imprint of New Left Books British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data available ISBN 0-86091-48 1-X ISBN 0-8609 1 -646-4 US Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data available Typeset by Keyboard Services, Luton Printed and bound in Great Britain by Biddies Ltd, Guildford and King's Lynn Contents Preface vii Preface to the Third Edition IX Introductionto the Chinese Edition 1 Analytical Index 5 Introduction 9 Parts1-20 14 Postscript on Relativism 268 Index 273 Preface In 1970 Imre Lakatos, one of the best friends I ever had, corneredme at a party. 'Paul,' he said, 'you have such strange ideas. Why don't you write them down? I shall write a reply, we publish the whole thing and I promise you - we shall have lots of fun.' I liked the suggestion and started working. The manuscript of my part of the book was finished in 1972 and I sent it to London. There it disappeared under rather mysterious circumstances. lmre Lakatos, who loved dramatic gestures, notified Interpol and, indeed, Interpol found my manu­ script and returned it to me. I reread it and made some final changes. In February 1974, only a few weeks after I had finished my revision, I was informed of Imre's death.
    [Show full text]
  • Paul Feyerabend, 1924-1994 a Personal Memoir
    Paul Feyerabend, 1924-1994 A Personal Memoir Paul Feyerabend died on February 11, a month after his seventieth birthday. He wrote the last of his many letters to me in October 1993, and on the outside of the envelope, in typically casual fashion, he scribbled a message saying that he might soon be coming to Brighton, because his wife was helping to organise a conference there on conservation. That would have been his first visit to England for twenty years; the first since he taught at the U ni versity of Sussex for two terms when he was considering, and being considered for, the second chair of philosophy there. I first met Paul in the mid 1950s when he joined the Philosophy Department at Bristol University. We shared a room in the university tower and became close friends. When he married his second wife, one of our students, I was his best man. He took the opportunity to scawl on an off­ print of one of his early papers: 'To the best man, from the best philosopher' . It was in those days that he developed the endearing habit of walking with his hand on my leaning shoulder, a gesture both affectionate and useful. He was a cripple. He walked with a crutch, the legacy of a bullet in the spine during the retreat from the Russian front in 1945. I gather that his war service earned him the Iron Cross, but I never heard Paul himself refer to the subject. at Berkeley, and his criticisms of Popper's falsificationism He was Viennese.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of Logical Positivism ______
    The Philosophy of Logical Positivism ________________________________________________ Mauro Murzi Member of Società Filosofica Italiana [email protected] http://www.murzim.net 1 2 Table of Contents 1. Introduction.................................................................................................5 2. The Main Philosophical Tenets of Logical Positivism...............................7 a. Verifiability Principle.............................................................................7 b. Elimination of Metaphysics...................................................................7 c. The Language of Science.......................................................................8 d. Observational and Theoretical Terms..................................................10 e. Synthetic and Analytic Statements.......................................................11 f. Probability and Inductive Logic...........................................................12 g. Ethics....................................................................................................14 3. History of Logical Positivism...................................................................15 a. Before Logical Positivism....................................................................15 b. Early Research in Europe.....................................................................17 c. The American Period............................................................................17 d. Influences on European Philosophy.....................................................18
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 2021; 2(1): 47–69
    Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 2021; 2(1): 47–69 Thomas Mormann* Two Kindred Neo-Kantian Philosophies of Science: Pap’s The A Priori in Physical Theory and Cassirer’s Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics https://doi.org/10.1515/jtph-2021-0001 Published online April 8, 2021 Abstract: The main thesis of this paper is that Pap’s The Functional A Priori in Physical Theory and Cassirer’s Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics may be conceived as two kindred accounts of a late Neo-Kantian philosophy of science. They elucidate and clarify each other mutually by elaborating conceptual possibilities and pointing out affinities of neo-Kantian ideas with other currents of 20th century’s philosophy of science, namely, pragmatism, conventionalism, and logical empiricism. Taking into account these facts, it seems not too far fetched to conjecture that under more favorable circumstances Pap could have served as a mediator between the “analytic” and “continental” tradition thereby overcoming the dogmatic dualism of these two philosophical currents that has characterized philosophy in the second half the 20th century. Keywords: neo-Kantianism, pragmatism, logical empiricism, Arthur Pap, Ernst Cassirer 1 Introduction The main thesis of this paper is that Pap’s The A Priori in Physical Theory (Pap 1946, henceforth FAP) and Cassirer’s Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics (Cassirer 1937, henceforth DI) may be conceived as two kindred accounts of a late Neo-Kantian philosophy of science. They elucidate and clarify each other mutually by elaborating conceptual possibilities and pointing out affinities of neo-Kantian ideas with other currents of 20th century’s philosophy of science, namely, prag- matism, conventionalism, and logical empiricism.
    [Show full text]
  • Austrian Philosophy: Outlines of a Discipline at the University of Vienna in the 20Th Century*
    FRIEDRICH STADLER Austrian Philosophy: Outlines of a Discipline at the University of Vienna in the 20th Century* I. BACKGROUND Since the foundation of the University of Vienna, the Faculty of Philosophy, as a “faculty of the arts”, had played a subordinate role – also as a field of study – in relation to the faculties of Medicine, Law and Theology.1 The Faculty con- tinued to be instrumentalized as an ancilla by the respective prevailing powers until 1848. In predominantly Catholic Austria, Immanuel Kant’s philosophy was marginalized for being enlightening or revolutionary, and the position on the philosophy of German idealism was regarded as crucial to the development of a specifically “Austrian philosophy” after 1848. This happened in the spirit of an alleged Austrian Sonderweg (distinct course in Austria-Hungary) against each form of dialectic, transcendental and aprioristic philosophy of Prussian-German origin.2 But given the specific development in the monarchy, this very claim should be examined with a critical eye to increase the focus on Kant’s polariz- ing or identity-defining role in proportion to the Austrian line of tradition ex- tending from Bernard Bolzano through Robert Zimmermann and up to Franz Brentano and his influential school.3 There is no question that the Königsberg philosopher remained a reference until the heyday of the Vienna Circle and also thereafter. It was about answering the question of the autonomy and scientific nature of philosophy given the growing importance of individual disciplines of the cultural, social and natural sciences (including mathematics) in the mael- strom of the second scientific revolution.
    [Show full text]
  • Luz Chapa: Bibliografía Tesis Doctoral
    Bibliografía La bibliografía de este trabajo está ordenada en dos secciones distintas. En primer lugar se relacionan por orden cronológico de edición original los artículos y libros de Popper en las ediciones consultadas y expresamente citadas a lo largo de este trabajo. Por la naturaleza de la investigación se han citado por separado los artículos posteriormente recopilados y publicados en forma de libro. Una bibliografía completa hasta la fecha de su publicación puede encontrarse en P. A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Karl Popper, Open Court, La Salle (Illinois), 1974, 1201-1297 y después en http//www.univie.ac.at/science-archives/popper/biblio.html. En segundo lugar se relaciona por orden alfabético de autores toda la bibliografía general consultada y expresamente citada a lo largo del trabajo. Los artículos y libros de Carnap, Feigl, Kraft, Schlick, Russell y Wittgenstein se relacionan por orden cronológico de edición original. 1. Obras de Karl R. Popper (1931) “Die Gedächtnispflege unter dem Gesichtspunkt der Selbsttätigkeit”, Die Quelle, 81, 1931, 607-619. (1933) “Carta al Editor de Erkenntnis” en The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Routledge, London, 1997, 312-314. (1934) “On the so-called „Logic of Induction‟ and the „Probability of Hypotheses‟” en The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Routledge, London, 1997, 315-317. 404 POPPER, EL CÍRCULO DE VIENA Y WITTGENSTEIN (1945) The Open Society and Its Enemies, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1971. (1950-1951) “Indeterminism in Quantum Physics and in Classical Physics”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, I, 2, 1950-1951, 117-133. (1954) “Corroboration, the Weight of Evidence, and Statistical tests” en The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Routledge, London, 1997, 387-419.
    [Show full text]
  • School of Philosophy Risen in Austria and Germany During 1920S, Primarily Concerned with the Logical Analysis of Scientific Knowledge
    Mauro Murzi’s pages on Philosophy of Science Logical positivism – page 1 of 3 School of philosophy risen in Austria and Germany during 1920s, primarily concerned with the logical analysis of scientific knowledge. Among its members were Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, Hans Reichenbach, Herbert Feigl, Philipp Frank, Kurt Grelling, Hans Hahn, Carl Gustav Hempel, Victor Kraft, Otto Neurath, Friedrich Waismann. Logical positivists denied the soundness of metaphysics and traditional philosophy; they asserted that many philosophical problems are indeed meaningless. According to logical positivism, there are only two sources of knowledge: logical reasoning and empirical experience. The former is analytic a priori, while the latter is synthetic a posteriori; hence synthetic a priori does not exist. The fundamental thesis of logical positivism consists in denying the possibility of synthetic a priori knowledge; you can see an explicit disagreement with Kantian philosophy. Einstein's theory of relativity exerted a great influence on logical positivism. At its origin, logical positivism was primary concerned with the philosophical interpretation of theory of relativity. I can remember, as an example of the great influence exerted by Einstein's theory of relativity, that Schlick wrote in 1915 and 1917 two essays on relativity, Reichenbach attended Einstein's lectures on the theory of relativity at Berlin in 1917 and wrote in 1920s four books on relativity, Carnap's first work was an essay about the theory of space published in 1922. Other works on relativity were published in 1950s by Frank. Also quantum mechanics was a major subject of philosophical investigation. Works about quantum theory were published by Schlick and Reichenbach.
    [Show full text]