THE ENLIGHTENMENTTHE the Nelson Cengage Has Developed This Series a Globalised World for Australian Senior Secondary Students of Age of Imperialism Modern History

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

THE ENLIGHTENMENTTHE the Nelson Cengage Has Developed This Series a Globalised World for Australian Senior Secondary Students of Age of Imperialism Modern History NELSON NELSON MODERNHISTORY MODERNHISTORY NELSON MODERNHISTORY THE ENLIGHTENMENT THE Nelson Cengage has developed this series A Globalised World for Australian senior secondary students of Age of Imperialism Modern History. The series includes titles Australia 1918–1950s that encompass the period from the 18th century to the contemporary world and China and Revolution ENLIGHTENMENT they explore the social, cultural and political Civil Rights in the United States of America developments that shape the 21st century. Decolonisation Written by experienced educators and Germany 1918–1945 experts in their fields, each book builds on India a narrative framework to incorporate recent research and historiography, primary and Recognition and Rights of Indigenous Peoples secondary sources, and learning activities. Russia and the Soviet Union These key features combine to support the The American Revolution development of historical knowledge and The Changing World Order understanding and historical skills that will enable students to interpret and reflect on The Enlightenment the experience and developments that have The French Revolution created the world in which they live. The Industrial Revolution The Struggle for Peace in the Middle East United States of America 1917–1945 Women’s Movements The Enlightenment Workers’ Rights An Experiment on a Bird in the Air Pump was painted in England by Joseph Wright of Derby in 1768. It was one of a number of scenes Wright painted in the 1760s that featured scientific experiments. In this case, the painting shows a scientist undertaking an experiment in which oxygen is drawn from a glass vessel. The experiment worked and the bird that was trapped in the glass vessel lost consciousness through lack of oxygen. This painting, like the others in the ADCOCK series, encapsulates the spirit of the Enlightenment, a movement that encouraged people to understand the world in rational terms rather rely on the irrational. ISBN: 978-0170243988 Joseph Wright of Derby (1734–1797) Joseph Wright was an English painter of portraits and landscapes who rose to prominence during the Enlightenment. MICHAEL ADCOCK Read more about Joseph Wright and the English Enlightenment in Chapter 3. SERIES EDITOR: TONY TAYLOR 9 780170 243988 For learning solutions, visit cengage.com.au enlightenment_sb_43988_cvr_gatefold_finalart.indd 1-4 23/07/14 9:53 AM The public use of one’s reason must always be free, and it alone can bring about enlightenment among men. Eric Hobsbawm Australia • Brazil • Japan • Korea • Mexico • Singapore • Spain • United Kingdom • United States 9780170243988 iii CONTENTS About the series iv Series editor acknowledgements vi Author acknowledgements vii 001 Introduction 103 CHAPTER 4 Responding to the Enlightenment 009 CHAPTER 1 What was the Enlightenment? 129 CHAPTER 5 What were the effects of the Enlightenment? 047 CHAPTER 2 Who were the main thinkers of the Enlightenment in France? 152 Conclusion 075 CHAPTER 3 The Enlightenment beyond France Index 160 9780170243988 ABOUT THE SERIES Using The Enlightenment The Enlightenment has been developed especially for senior secondary students of History and is part of the Nelson Modern History series. Each book in the series is based on the understanding that History is an interpretive study of the past by which you also come to better appreciate the making of the modern world. Developing understandings of the past and present in senior History extends on the skills you learnt in earlier years. As senior students you will use historical skills, including research, evaluation, synthesis, analysis and communication, and the historical concepts, such as evidence, continuity and change, cause and effect, significance, empathy, perspectives and contestability, to understand and interpret societies from the past. The activities and tasks in The Enlightenment have been written to ensure that you develop the skills and attributes you need in senior History subjects. KEY FIGURES AND ORGANISATIONS, KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS, KEY DOCUMENTS feature brief biographies, profiles, definitions and summaries of key documents as a ready reference for learning and revision. INQUIRY ILLUSTRATED TIMELINE QUESTIONS is a bird’s-eye view of the topic are listed at and summarises the major the start of the developments of the period. chapter. These questions provide a focus for you as you read each chapter. CHAPTER INTRODUCTIONS provide a context to the issues that are addressed. SOURCE STUDIES SIGNIFICANT INDIVIDUALS of visual and text primary sources and are biographical profiles and secondary literature appear frequently through assessments of key historical the text and are combined with questions figures and frequently include and activities to aid your evaluation and questions and activities. interpretation of evidence from the past. 9780170243988 v INFORMATION BOXES HISTORIAN BOXES DIAGRAMS AND contain extended discussions of introduce key historians and schools TALKING SOURCES key events, concepts and historical of interpretation as a way of making are used to visually summarise developments. Many also include historiography clearer. complex ideas and events. questions and activities. CHAPTER SUMMARY AND CHAPTER REVIEW ACTIVITIES conclude each chapter. They include a brief precis of the topic, suggestions for further reading, and a range of learning activities that consolidate knowledge and understanding of the chapter’s content. These tasks incorporate a range of historical understandings and skills. THE CONCLUSION summarises the topic and includes a series of activities to consolidate your knowledge of it. More importantly, these final tasks will help you build an understanding and interpretation of this period in history. Beyond this book The Nelson Modern History series includes numerous titles on a range of topics covered in senior History courses around Australia. For further information about the series visit: www.nelsonsecondary.com.au. 9780170243988 The National Gallery, London. Licensed under the GNU Free Documentation License. The National Gallery, 9780170243988 KEY FIGURES ANTHONY COLLINS BENJAMIN FRANKLIN FRANCIS HUTCHESON (1676–1729) (1706–1790) (1694–1746) A leading thinker of the Freethinking Franklin was both a leading Hutcheson spread the word about the Movement in England, Collins wrote Enlightenment thinker in America and a scientific method of Francis Bacon and A Discourse of Freethinking (1713). leader of the ‘Patriot’, or Revolutionary, Isaac Newton, with their emphasis on Movement, which resulted in the experimentation, direct observation 13 American colonies breaking and evidence. Hutcheson also expressed perfectly the Enlightenment DENIS DIDEROT (1713–1784) away from Britain. As a scientist, he made significant advances in the belief that the main task of reason understanding of electricity; and as an and science is to increase human Diderot was the editor (with Jean inventor, he created many practical wellbeing, famously commenting that le Rond d’Alembert) of the great devices, such as bifocal lenses. their role was to ‘produce the greatest Encyclopaedia (1750–65), but good for the greatest numbers’. was also one of the most diverse writers in French literature. Apart DAVID HUME (1711–1776) from writing treatises, such as IMMANUAL KANT his Supplement to the Voyage of (1724–1804) Bougainville (1772), he proved to be Hume is often regarded as one of a brilliant writer in art criticism (for the greatest thinkers in Western Kant was a leading German philosophe example, his reviews for the Salons: philosophy, and he inspired Adam (see below), best known for his see below) and in avant-garde novels Smith, Immanuel Kant, Jeremy Critique of Pure Reason (1781). (such as Jacques the Fatalist and his Bentham and Charles Darwin. In A Master (1796)). Treatise on Human Nature (1738) he argued that we can apply scientific reasoning to moral and ethical issues. He suggested that we must create a ‘science of man’ that would use scientific reasoning to understand human nature itself. 9780170243988 The Bridgeman Art Library; © Hunterian, University of Glasgow 2014; De Agostini Picture Library/The Bridgeman Art Library; © DHM/The Bridgeman Chicago History Museum, USA/The Bridgeman Art Library; Mary Evans Picture Library 2 the American colonists during their GOTTFRIED LEIBNIZ rebellion against British authority. Voltaire (FRANÇOIS- (1646–1716) In 1776, he published Common Marie Arouet) (1694–1778) Sense, which drew upon the political Voltaire enjoyed a long life, wrote theories of John Locke and Jean- numerous works, and effectively Jacques Rousseau to prove that informed public opinion on important it was ‘common sense’ that the political and social issues. After colonies should free themselves visiting England (1726–29), he from British rule, both for reasons of turned to serious political and social principle and for practical reasons. ‘The philosopher’s philosopher’, commentary, criticising France Leibniz was one of the most complex by praising England in his Letters thinkers of the Enlightenment. In the Concerning the English Nation (1733). JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU field of physics, he guessed the nature He had powerful friends, ranging from (1712–1778) of what we now call kinetic energy. He Madame de Pompadour in France to was equally a pioneer in mathematics, Rousseau made his first contribution King Frederick II in Prussia, which and is regarded as one of the great to the French Enlightenment by he visited in 1750–53. He settled in inventors of mathematical logic. He writing
Recommended publications
  • Voltaire Voltaire's Enlightenment Philosophy
    Voltaire François-Marie d'Arouet (1694–1778), better known by his pen name Voltaire, was a French writer and public activist who played a singular role in defining the eighteenth-century movement called the Enlightenment. At the center of his work was a new conception of philosophy and the philosopher that in several crucial respects influenced the modern concept of each. Yet in other ways Voltaire was not a philosopher at all in the modern sense of the term. He wrote as many plays, stories, and poems as patently philosophical tracts, and he in fact directed many of his critical writings against the philosophical pretensions of recognized philosophers such as Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes. He was, however, a vigorous defender of a conception of natural science that served in his mind as the antidote to vain and fruitless philosophical investigation. In clarifying this new distinction between science and philosophy, and especially in fighting vigorously for it in public campaigns directed against the perceived enemies of fanaticism and superstition, Voltaire pointed modern philosophy down several paths that it subsequently followed. To capture Voltaire's unconventional place in the history of philosophy, this article will be structured in a particular way. First, a full account of Voltaire's life is offered, not merely as background context for his philosophical work, but as an argument about the way that his particular career produced his particular contributions to European philosophy. Second, a survey of Voltaire's philosophical views is offered so as to attach the legacy of what Voltaire did with the intellectual viewpoints that his activities reinforced.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes Steven Shapin Isis, Vol. 72, No. 2. (Jun., 1981), Pp
    Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes Steven Shapin Isis, Vol. 72, No. 2. (Jun., 1981), pp. 187-215. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-1753%28198106%2972%3A2%3C187%3AOGAKNP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-C Isis is currently published by The University of Chicago Press. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/ucpress.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Mon Aug 20 10:29:37 2007 Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes By Steven Shapin* FTER TWO AND A HALF CENTURIES the Newton-Leibniz disputes A continue to inflame the passions.
    [Show full text]
  • Berkeley Studies
    Berkeley Studies No. 28 (2019) Editors Stephen H. Daniel, Senior Editor College Station, Texas, USA John R. Roberts, Coordinating Editor Tallahassee, Florida, USA Silvia Parigi, Bibliographical Editor Cassino, Italy Tom Stoneham, News Editor York, UK Contents Jessica Gordon-Roth Tracing Reid’s ‘Brave Officer’ Objection Back to Berkeley—And Beyond 3 Daniel E. Flage Rickless and Passive Obedience 23 News and Announcements 47 Recent Works on Berkeley (2017-2019) 48 Berkeley Studies 28 (2019) 2 © Berkeley Studies and Contributors 2019 Berkeley Studies is sponsored by Florida State University and the International Berkeley Society Berkeley Studies 28 (2019) 3 Tracing Reid’s ‘Brave Officer’ Objection Back to Berkeley—And Beyond Jessica Gordon-Roth Abstract: Berkeley’s two most obvious targets in Alciphron are Shaftesbury and Mandeville. However, as numerous commentators have pointed out, there is good reason to think Berkeley additionally targets Anthony Collins in this dialogue. In this paper, I bolster David Berman’s claim that “Collins looms large in the background” of Dialogue VII, and put some meat on the bones of Raymond Martin and John Barresi’s passing suggestion that there is a connection between the Clarke–Collins correspondence, Alciphron, and the objection that Berkeley raises regarding persons and their persistence conditions therein. Specifically, I argue that we have evidence that Berkeley’s objection to consciousness–based views of personal identity, as found in VII.8, is a response to a challenge that Collins raises to Clarke in “An Answer to Mr. Clarke’s Third Defense of his Letter to Mr. Dodwell.” This is significant not just because this objection is usually—and consistently—taken to be an objection to Locke, but also because Berkeley’s objection works against Collins’s theory of personal identity in a way that it doesn’t against Locke’s.
    [Show full text]
  • The European Enlightenment HI 215/PO 393
    The European Enlightenment HI 215/PO 393 Fall Term 2014 Professor James Schmidt Tuesday & Thursday 2:00-3:30 - 2:00, Shaw 201 745 Comm. Ave., Room 618A Office Hours: Tues 11:30AM-1:00PM & 617-358-1781 ([email protected]) Thurs. 3:45PM – 5 PM During the eighteenth century, Europe became modern. As a result of a transnational movement known as the Enlightenment many of the ideas, practices, and attitudes that have come to define what it means to be “modern” first began to take root in Europe and on the eastern coast of North America. This course explores how this change came about by tracing the transformation of European culture and society between the last decades of the seventeenth century and the end of the eighteenth century. Readings will be quite diverse in their concerns, their style, and their approach. Texts assigned include political tracts, philosophical essays, theological treatises, as well as a few examples from the “literary underground” of the eighteenth century. They will draw rather heavily on a few major figures — Voltaire, Diderot, Condorcet, Lessing, and the Scottish moralists — but will also pay attention to important eighteenth-century figures who are sometimes overlooked in introductory surveys (e.g., Moses Mendelssohn, Richard Price, and Joseph Priestley). Requirements and Grading Policy: There will be a mid-term exam during class on October 21 and a final exam on Tuesday, December 16 from 3:00-5:00 PM. Both will consist of a combination of short answers and somewhat more extended responses. You can expect questions that call upon you to discuss central concepts, institutions, and individuals covered in the readings or lectures.
    [Show full text]
  • Superstition, Anticlericalism, and Cicero's De Divinatione in Enlightenment England, C.1700-1730
    East, K.A. (2018) Deconstructing Divination: Superstition, Anticlericalism, and Cicero's De Divinatione in Enlightenment England, c.1700-1730. In: Richard Evans (ed.) Prophets and Profits: Ancient Divination and Its Reception. Abingdon: Routledge, pp.183-198. Copyright: This is an Accepted Manuscript of a book chapter published by Routledge in Prophets and Profits: Ancient Divination and Its Reception on 05/09/2017, available online: https://www.routledge.com/Prophets-and- Profits-Ancient-Divination-and-Its-Reception/Evans/p/book/9781138290150 Date deposited: 05/04/2017 Embargo release date: 05 March 2019 Newcastle University ePrints - eprint.ncl.ac.uk DECONSTRUCTING DIVINATION: SUPERSTITION, ANTICLERICALISM, AND CICERO’S DE DIVINATIONE IN ENLIGHTENMENT ENGLAND, C. 1700-1730 Katherine A. East Abstract In the complex inter-confessional exchanges which defined Enlightenment England the accusation of ‘superstition’ became a powerful weapon to wield, and few wielded it more extensively and controversially than those radical figures waging war on the power of the clergy. As treatises proliferated which condemned miracles, prophecies, and sacerdotal authority as superstitions with no place in a true religion, one text in particular was regularly invoked in support: the second book of Cicero’s theological dialogue De Divinatione, in which, in response to his brother’s defence of divination in the first book, Cicero deconstructed the proffered examples of divinatory activity, the oracles and dreams, with rational argument. This chapter will examine how Cicero’s attack on superstitio in De Divinatione was adapted and deployed by three anticlerical writers: John Toland, Anthony Collins, and Matthew Tindal. In the work of these men ancient perceptions of divination and its place in religion and society can be found informing Enlightenment efforts to challenge the customary authority of the Church.
    [Show full text]
  • Atheism and Analogy: Aquinas Against the Atheists Dan Linford Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of the Virginia Polytechnic Instit
    Atheism and Analogy: Aquinas Against the Atheists Dan Linford Thesis submitted to the faculty of the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts In Philosophy Joseph C. Pitt Benjamin Jantzen Matthew Goodrum April 25, 2014 Blacksburg, Virginia Keywords: atheism, theology, analogy, God, Berkeley, Hume, Anthony Collins, d'Holbach Atheism and Analogy: Aquinas Against the Atheists Dan Linford ABSTRACT In the 13th century, Thomas Aquinas developed two models for how humans may speak of God – either by the analogy of proportion or by the analogy of proportionality. Aquinas's doctrines initiated a theological debate concerning analogy that spanned several centuries. In the 18th century, there appeared two closely related arguments for atheism which both utilized analogy for their own purposes. In this thesis, I show that one argument, articulated by the French materialist Paul-Henri Thiry Baron d'Holbach, is successful in showing that God-talk, as conceived of using the analogy of proportion, is unintelligible non-sense. In addition, I show that another argument, articulated by Anthony Collins (Vindication of Divine Attributes), George Berkeley (chapter IV of Alciphron), and David Hume (chapter XII of Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion) can be restructured into an argument for the position that the analogy of proportionality makes the distinction between atheism and theism merely verbal. Since both of these are undesirable consequences for the theist, I conclude that Aquinas's doctrine of analogy does not withstand the assault of 18th century atheists. Acknowledgements I would like to thank Aaron Yarmel,1 Walter Ott,2 Ted Parent,3 Roger Ariew,4 and Dan Fincke5 for discussions that helped to complete this thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • A Reading of Shaftesbury's Characteristicks
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 2010 Sea-Cards for the Impetuous Muse: A Reading of Shaftesbury's Characteristicks Travis Sean Cook Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Cook, Travis Sean, "Sea-Cards for the Impetuous Muse: A Reading of Shaftesbury's Characteristicks" (2010). Dissertations. 31. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/31 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 2010 Travis Sean Cook LOYOLA UNIVERSITY CHICAGO SEA-CARDS FOR THE IMPETUOUS MUSE: A READING OF SHAFTESBURY'S CHARACTERISTICKS A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY PROGRAM IN POLITICAL SCIENCE BY TRAVIS SEAN COOK CHICAGO, ILLINOIS MAY 2010 Copyright by Travis S. Cook, 2010 All rights reserved. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I have incurred many debts in the writing of this dissertation--in fact, too many to catalogue accurately. Nevertheless: I have been blessed with many excellent teachers over the years. I am very grateful to the members of my committee for the time, care, insight, and patience they offered as I worked on this project. Professor John Danford has been an excellent teacher and keen reader; I am grateful for the generosity and kindness he has shown to me.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography Primary Sources Abbadie, Jacques
    On the Spirit of Rights Dan Edelstein Published by the University of Chicago Press, 2018 Bibliography Primary Sources Abbadie, Jacques. Défense de la nation britannique, ou Les droits de Dieu, de la Nature, & de la Société clairement établis au sujet de la révolution d’Angleterre. The Hague, 1693. ———. Les Droits de Dieu, de la nature et des gens, tirés d’un livre de M. Abbadie intitulé: “Défense de la nation britannique . .” On y a ajouté un discours de M. Noodt sur les droits des souverains (traduit du latin par Barbeyrac). Amsterdam, 1775. ———. Traité de la vérité de la religion chretienne. Rotterdam: R. Leers, 1684. Académie française. Dictionnaire. Paris, 1694. ———. Dictionnaire. Paris, 1762. ———. Dictionnaire. Paris, 1798. Acta Sanctae Sedis. 41 vols. Rome, 1865–1908. http://www.vatican.va/archive/ass/index_en.htm. Adams, John. The Works of John Adams. 10 vols. Edited by Charles Francis Adams. Boston: Little, Brown, 1856. Adams, John, Samuel Adams, and James Warren. Warren-Adams Letters. Boston: Massachusetts Historical Society, 1917. Addison, Joseph. The Evidences of the Christian Religion. London: Tonson, 1733. ———. The Free-holder, Or Political Essays. London: D. Midwinter, 1716. All Canada in the Hands of the English. Boston: B. Mecom, 1760. Almain, Jacques. “A Book Concerning the Authority of the Church.” In Conciliarism and Papalism, edited by J. H. Burns and Thomas M. Izbicki, 134–200. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997. Alsop, Vincent. A Reply to the Reverend Dean of St. Pauls’s Reflections on the Rector of Sutton, 1 &c. London, 1681. Annet, Peter. A Discourse on Government and Religion. Boston: Daniel Fowle, 1750.
    [Show full text]
  • Does Matter Think?
    Does Matter Think? Introduction to the Excerpt Descartes’s philosophy had introduced a rigid separation between the spiritual and the material, so the question of the extent of matter’s participation in thought was recast as the question of the “materiality” of consciousness. Late 17 th -century thinkers associated with Epicureanism in France and the Deist movement in England began to toy with the idea that Man is nothing more than a Cartesian beast-machine. Richard Bentley condemned this idea in 1692, but John Locke had affirmed at least the possibility (non-contradiction) of “thinking matter” in 1690 in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (IV.III.13). So, there was a lively philosophical and theological controversy on this topic by the first decade of the 18 th century. Against this background, Henry Dodwell published Epistolatory Discourses in 1706 supporting the materiality of the soul (made immortal at baptism!). A pamphlet war broke out among Dodwell, Samuel Clarke, and Anthony Collins, who sided with Dodwell. Samuel Clarke had attacked Dodwell in a pamphlet entitled A Letter to Mr. Dodwell . Collins wrote a pamphlet defending Dodwell and attacking Clarke. Clarke replied to Collins’s attack, and, in the pamphlet from which this excerpt is taken, Collins attacked Clarke’s reply, and so on for several more iterations. One of Clarke’s main arguments against thinking matter is that each particle of matter would have to be conscious, which would mean that the brain would consist of a multitude of separate consciousnesses, whereas we are only aware of having a single, unified consciousness.
    [Show full text]
  • HALL-DISSERTATION-2021.Pdf (3.174Mb)
    Copyright by Kirsten Anne Hall 2021 The Dissertation Committee for Kirsten Anne Hall certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: Between Christ and Achilles: Christian Humanism in Crisis and a New Heroic Ideal in English Fiction, 1713-1813 Committee: Janine Barchas, Co-Supervisor Elizabeth Hedrick, Co-Supervisor Lance Bertelsen Ashley Marshall Martha Bowden Between Christ and Achilles: Christian Humanism in Crisis and a New Heroic Ideal in English Fiction, 1713-1813 by Kirsten Anne Hall Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of The University of Texas at Austin in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Texas at Austin May 2021 Acknowledgements I’m grateful, first, to Janine Barchas and Beth Hedrick for their encouragement and intellectual energy as my co-supervisors. At every stage, they championed my progress and challenged me to deepen and clarify my claims. I am also thankful for the mentorship of Lance Bertelsen as well as the support of my committee members outside of the University of Texas at Austin: Ashley Marshall and Martha Bowden. I would also like to express my gratitude to colleagues who offered to read parts of this project at different stages of the writing process: to James Bryant Reeves at Texas State University for his feedback on my Cato article, to Erik Dempsey at the University of Texas at Austin for helping me think through the intellectual background of my project and pointing me to Diogenes Laertius, and to Jocelyn Harris at the University of Otago for reading my Notes & Queries manuscript.
    [Show full text]
  • Samuel Clarke and Anthony Collins on the Immortality
    The Sleeping Habits of Matter and Spirit: Samuel Clarke and Anthony Collins on the Immortality of the Soul1 Jeffrey R. Wigelsworth In 1706, Samuel Clarke, Newtonian and theologian, engaged in a debate with Anthony Collins, deist and country gentleman, over the nature ofthe soul and matter. Both men were responding to the work of Henry Dodwell, who earlier that year suggested that the soul was a substance naturally mortal, which was given immortality by God alone. While historians have long noted this debate, the underlying assumptions and intellectual debts of both Clarke and Collins have not been fully explored. Clarke's arguments clearly revealed his Newtonianism and, what is more, it is now evident that he shared Newton's conception ofthe soul. Collins followed a deist interpretation of both the soul and matter, a view first proposed by the deist John Toland. This article brings these assumptions to light and in so doing, demonstrates that Clarke was even more Newtonian than was previously thought and that deists shared more ofa worldview than the denial ofrevelation. Among the anxious divines who in the early eighteenth century saw the spectre of deism as an increasing shadow of darkness, which threatened to cover England in unbelief concerning revealed religion, was Samuel Clarke (1675-1729), theologian and close friend of Isaac Newton (1642-1727). One of the deists whom Clarke sought to refute, in an attempt to demonstrate the errors of these heretics to the English public, was Anthony Collins (1676-1729). The first literary duel between the two men occurred in a series of pamphlets published between 1706 and 1708 brought about by the work of Henry Dodwell (1641-1711), who in early 1706 hypothesized that the human soul was naturally 1 For their aid during the various stages of this article, I should like to thank J.
    [Show full text]
  • ASEMP2019 Abstracts Fatema Amijee Plural Explanation in Leibniz According to the Principle of Sufficient Reason
    ASEMP2019 Abstracts Fatema Amijee Plural Explanation in Leibniz According to the Principle of Sufficient Reason (‘PSR’), every fact has a sufficient reason for why it obtains rather than does not obtain. Leibniz subscribes to the PSR, yet claims that nothing in the world—taken as a series of contingent things—can be a sufficient reason for the existence of any contingent thing. Leibniz further claims that this is because a contingent thing can never completely explain another contingent thing. I first develop Leibniz’s conception of a complete explanation. I then argue that this conception, along with his commitment to the PSR and to the existence of contingent things, commits Leibniz to plural explanation—the view on which the totality of contingent things is sufficiently explained plurally, yet each individual contingent thing lacks an explanation when taken on its own. I thereby highlight a limitation on Leibniz’s commitment to the PSR. In developing Leibniz’s conception of a complete explanation, I first show that Leibniz’s conception of a sufficient reason is remarkably stable and remains constant over a period that ranges from c. 1671-72 through to his mature metaphysics in the early 1700s. In particular, I show that a sufficient reason for a thing, for Leibniz, (at least partially) consists in the totality of the thing’s necessary causal conditions, and that this requirement on a sufficient reason is a constant in Leibniz’s philosophy. I then discuss why Leibniz thinks that no contingent thing can explain the existence of other contingent things and rule out three candidate explanations.
    [Show full text]