Curriculum Vitae (Abridged) KENDALL LEWIS WALTON

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Curriculum Vitae (Abridged) KENDALL LEWIS WALTON Curriculum Vitae (abridged) KENDALL LEWIS WALTON (Revised 13 December 2016) Department of Philosophy E-Mail: [email protected] 2215 Angell Hall WARNING: This email address con- 435 S. State St. tains TWO initials. Omitting the 'L' will University of Michigan send your message to another person. Ann Arbor, MI 48109 E-Mail: [email protected] Webpage: https://sites.lsa.umich.edu/kendallwalton/ EDUCATION University of California, Berkeley. B.A., 1961. Cornell University. Ph.D., 1967. DISSERTATION Conceptual Schemes: A Study of Linguistic Relativity and Related Philosophical Problems. PROFESSIONAL POSITIONS Lecturer, Assistant Professor, Associate Professor, Professor, University of Michi- gan, 1965 – 2012. Charles L. Stevenson Collegiate Professor of Philosophy, University of Michigan, 1999 - 2012. Professor, School of Art and Design, University of Michigan, 2005 - 2012. Professor Emeritus of Philosophy, University of Michigan, 2012-present. Cowling Distinguished Visiting Professor in Philosophy, Carleton College, spring quarter, 2012. Wm H. Bonsall Visiting Professor, Stanford University (spring quarters), 2015 - pre- sent. FELLOWSHIPS AND AWARDS (Selected) Princeton University, Carl Hempel Lecturer, 1991. American Academy of Arts and Sciences, Fellow, elected 1998. Romanell-Phi Beta Kappa Professor of Philosophy, 2001-2002. President, American Society for Aesthetics, 2003-2005. Honorary degree: Doctor of Letters, University of Nottingham (UK), conferred July 2005. Hägerström Lecturer, Uppsala, Sweden (2017). Curriculum Vitae, - KENDALL L. WALTON 2 SYMPOSIA AND WORKSHOPS ON MY WRITINGS Symposium, Listening with Imagination, on my writings on music. American Musico- logical Society, New York. Four speakers, with my responses. November 1995. “Workshop on the work of Kendall Walton,” Nottingham University (UK), July 2005. “Metaphysics, Mimesis, and Make-Believe: A Conference in Honour of Kendall Walton.” Leeds University, U.K. 21-23 June, 2007. Symposium: “Kendall Walton and the Aesthetics of Photography and Film.” University of Kent (Canterbury, U.K.), School of Drama, Film, & Visual Arts. November- December, 2007. “Miniconference Celebrating the Work of Kendall Walton,” Victoria University of Wel- lington (New Zealand), Philosophy Department, March, 2008. “Workshop on Kendall Walton’s work at the intersection of aesthetics and philosophy of mind.” University of Warwick, June, 2008. “Imagination and Make-Believe in Art and Philosophy” (“Kenfest”). University of Mich- igan, 5-6 October, 2012. PUBLISHED INTERVIEWS “Can Seeing Be an Art Really,” with Richard West (interviewed jointly with Patrick Maynard). Source: Photographic Review, Issue 53 (Winter 2007), pp 38-41. “Aesthetics and Theory Construction,” with Hans Maes (translated into Dutch by Hans Maes as “Esthetica en Theorievorming: Een Interview met Kendall Wal- ton.” Esthetica: Tijdschrift voor Kunst en Filosofie (Jaargang 2008). “Only a Game.” Interview with Chris Bateman, 2010. http://onlyagame.typepad.com/only_a_game/2010/06/walton-on- makebelieve.html Audio Interview on photography, with Nigel Warburton. Philosophy Bites. http://philosophybites.com/2012/12/kendall-walton-on-photography.html. Interview with Christophe Lemaitre. Published in Lemaitre, Le livre de go, 2nd part (Frans Masereel Centrum, 2015). PUBLICATIONS Books: Mimesis As Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts (Harvard University Press, 1990). 450 pages. Italian translation, Mimesi come Far Finta, translated by Marco Nani (Milano: Mimesis Edizioni, 2011). Chinese translation (Beijing: The Commercial Press, 2013). Korean translation (Bookorea, 2015). Curriculum Vitae KENDALL L. WALTON 3 Japanese translation, Hitoshi Tamura translator (University of Nagoya Press, 2016). Selections titled ”Fiction and Nonfiction” and “Fearing Fictionally” reprinted in Dom Lopes and Eileen John (editors), Philosophy of Literature: Contemporary and Classic Readings (Blackwell’s, 2004). French translation of § 5.2, in Lorenzo Menoud, Qu’est-ce que la Fiction (Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. VRIN, 2005). Translation and commentary by Lo- renzo Menoud. § 2.8 “Legends and Myths” reprinted in John Gibson, Wolfgang Huemer, Luca Pocci, A Sense of the World: Fiction, Narrative and Knowledge (Routledge, 2007). Selections reprinted in Alex Neill and Aaron Ridley, Arguing about Art, 3rd edi- tion (Routledge, 2007). Selections reprinted in Thomas E. Wartenberg, The Nature of Art: An Anthology, 2nd and 3rd editions (Wadsworth, 2007, 2012) Marvelous Images: On Values and the Arts (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008). In Other Shoes: Music, Metaphor, Empathy, Existence (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015). Articles: “Categories of Art,” The Philosophical Review 79 (July 1970), pp. 334-367. Reprintings: (a) W. E. Kennick, Art and Philosophy, 2nd edition (St. Martin's Press, 1979); (b) J. Margolis, Philosophy Looks at the Arts, 2nd and 3rd editions (Temple University Press, 1978, 1986); (c) George Dickie, Richard Sclafani, and Ronald Robin, Aesthetics: A Critical Anthology, 2nd edition (St. Martin’s Press, 1989); (d) Finnish translation in Lammenranta—Haapala: Taidé ja tiede (Helsinki: Gaudeamus Ltd.); (e) Swedish translation in Jeanette Emt and Göran Her- merén, Konst och Filosofi; (f) French translation in Poetique (No. 86, April 1991); (g) Philip Alperson, The Philosophy of the Visual Arts (Oxford University Press, 1992); (h) French translation reprinted in Esthétique et Poétique, edited by Gér- ard Genette (Editions du Seuil, 1992); (i) John Bender and Gene Blocker, Con- temporary Philosophy of Art: Readings in Analytic Aesthetics (Prentice Hall, 1993); (j) Alex Neill and Aaron Ridley, Philosophy of Art: Readings Ancient and Modern (McGraw-Hill, 1995); (k) David Goldblatt and Lee B. Brown, Aesthetics: A Read- er in Philosophy of the Arts: (Prentice Hall, 1997, 2nd edition 2005, 3rd edition 2010), 4th edition (2017); (l) Steven M. Cahn, Philosophy for the 21st Century: A Compre- hensive Reader (Oxford University Press, 2003); (m) Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen, Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art: The Analytic Tradition (Blackwell’s, 2003); (n) Giovanni Matteuci (editor), Estetica Analitica (McGraw Hill, forthcoming); (o) Stephen Cahn and Aaron Meskin, Aesthetics: A Compre- hensive Anthology (Blackwell’s, 2007). Curriculum Vitae KENDALL L. WALTON 4 “Languages of Art: An Emendation,” Philosophical Studies (October-December 1971), pp. 82-85. “Pictures and Make-Believe,” The Philosophical Review (July 1973), pp. 283-319. Reprinted in W. E. Kennick, Art and Philosophy, 2nd edition (St. Martin's Press, 1979). “Linguistic Relativity,” in Conceptual Change, ed. by Glenn Pearce and P. Maynard (Reidel, 1973), pp. 1-30. “Are Representations Symbols?,” The Monist 58 (April 1974), pp. 236-254. Reprinted in Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen, Aesthetics and the Phi- losophy of Art: The Analytic Tradition (Blackwell’s, 2003). “Points of View in Narrative and Depictive Representation,” Nous 10 (March 1976), pp. 49-61. “The Presentation and Portrayal of Sound Patterns,” In Theory Only (Febru- ary/March 1977), pp. 3-16. “Fearing Fictions,” The Journal of Philosophy 75 (January 1978), pp. 5-27. Reprintings: (a) The Philosopher's Annual, edited by D. Boyer, P. Grim, and J. T. Sanders (Rowand and Littlefield, 1979); (b) Philosophy of Literature: A Book of Readings, edited by David Davies and Carl Matheson (Broadview Press, 2001); (c) Peter Lamarque and Stein Haughom Olsen, Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art: The Analytic Tradition (Blackwell’s, 2003). (d) Portugese translation in Te- oria Contemporanea do Cinema, Vol. 1, edited by Fernãao Pessoa Ramos (São Paulo: Editora Senac, 2005); (e) German translation in Fiktion, Wahrheit, Wirk- lichkeit, edited by Maria Reicher (Mentis, 2006); (f) Philosophy of Film: an Anthol- ogy, edited by Noel Carroll and Jinhee Choi (Blackwell’s, 2005); (g) Aesthetics, edited by Steven Cahn and Aaron Meskin (Blackwells, 2007); (h) Exploring Phi- losophy: An Introductory Anthology, 4th and 5th editions, edited by Steven Cahn (Oxford, 2012, 2014); (i) Serbian translation, in The Paradox of Fiction, Aleksan- dra Kostic, editor (Beograd: Fedon, forthcoming); (j) Czech translation forth- coming in Social Sciences and Audiovision (AMU Press, 2014?); (k) Japanese translation in anthology edited by Kiyokazu Nishimura, trans. by Norihide Mori (forthcoming); (l) German translation, “Furcht vor Fictionen,” in Maria E. Reicher (Hg.): Fiktion, Wahrheit, Wirklichkeit. Philosophische Grundlagen der Literaturtheorie. Paderborn 2007, S. 94–119. “How Remote Are Fictional Worlds From the Real World?,” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 37 (Fall 1978), pp. 11-23. Partially reprinted in Peter A. French and Curtis Brown, Puzzles, Paradoxes, and Problems: A Reader for Introductory Philosophy (St. Martin’s Press, 1987). Czech Translation in Aluze: revue pro literaturu, filozofii a jiné, 2005. “Style and the Products and Processes of Art,” in The Concept of Style, ed. by Berel Lang (University of Pennsylvania Press, 1979), pp. 45-66. Second edition (Cor- nell University Press, 1987), pp. 72-103. Curriculum Vitae KENDALL L. WALTON 5 “Appreciating Fiction: Suspending Disbelief or Pretending Belief?,” Dispositio (Invierno Primavera), 1980, pp. 1-18. Italian translation in Asmodeo/Asmodèe. French translation as “Comment on ap- précie la fiction” in Agone: Litterature, Critique & Philosophie, numéro 14 (1995); volume titled, "Quand y a-t-il fiction?". “Fiction, Fiction-Making, and Styles of Fictionality,”
Recommended publications
  • Impurely Musical Make-Believe
    Impurely Musical Make-Believe [Penultimate draft] Forthcoming in How to Make-Believe: The Fictional Truths of the Representational Arts, edited by J. Alexander Bareis and Lene Nordrum. Berlin: De Gruyter, 2015. Eran Guter and Inbal Guter Impurely Musical Make-Believe The mode of narration appropriate to absolute music, that is, “pure instrumental music without text, title, programme, dramatic setting, or any other extraordinary music apparatus” (Kivy 2009, 157), has been a matter of controversy in contemporary Anglophone philosophy of music for some three decades. Musicologist Anthony Newcomb put the issue succinctly: A large component of most music lies in its power […] to delight with its patterns in sound. (Hanslick likened music to the arabesque and the kaleidoscope.) But in some music these patterns seem to force upon some of us recognition of meaning connected to other aspects of our life – of a representational and expressive power. (Newcomb 1997, 132) The crux of the problem is the conviction, which germinated in Eduard Hanslick’s seminal treatise On the Musically Beautiful (Hanslick 1986 [1885]), that pure instrumental music lacks representational, narrative, semantic, or other extra-musical content, hence whatever meaning such music has consists in what Richard Wollheim (1987, 45) called “the much maligned property of the decorative.” Yet arguably, such extra-musical content, and accordingly, the power of music to be “about” such content in some sense, seem to play a prominent role in our understanding and appreciation of pure instrumental music and seem vital to the value that it holds for us. Without extra-musical content we are left with pure repetitive form.
    [Show full text]
  • Why We Should Give up on the Imagination DEREK MATRAVERS
    misp_205 190..199 MIDWEST STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXXIV (2010) Why We Should Give Up on the Imagination DEREK MATRAVERS lthough there is recent and interesting work on film acting directly on our Anerve endings so as to stimulate feelings and emotions, it is assumed, in Anglo-American philosophy of film (also known as “cognitive film theory”), that our engagement with film is largely mediated by the imagination (Coplan forth- coming). Hence, any account of the relation between film and emotion should take as central that viewers, generally, imagine the contents of the films they are shown. I think this is a mistake. In this paper, I want to argue that the imagination is not a helpful concept in accounting for our engagement with film (or indeed with litera- ture, although here I will focus exclusively on film). More specifically, it is simply not clear what theorists mean when they talk of “the imagination.” Famously, in Mimesis as Make-Believe, Kendall Walton describes the term as “serving as a placeholder for a notion yet to be fully clarified” (Walton 1990, 21). The lack of progress with such clarification has always hampered the debate, but now—in my view—it has become a real barrier to progress. Let us call the claim that viewers are mandated to imagine the content of films the “i-claim.” Although it might look as if this paper is directed against Walton (and some of it is) I think it is much closer to his position than might appear. I shall say a little about this at the end, but in the meantime will omit caveats that explain when Walton’s view escapes my arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 5450: Advanced Philosophy of Art Spring 2019 Prof
    Philosophy 5450: Advanced Philosophy of Art Spring 2019 Prof. Robert Kraut Course Overview This course is aimed at philosophy graduate students and advanced undergraduate majors. The goal is to explore a number of issues that concern the interpretation and evaluation of artworks and artistic performances. Philosophy 2450 is not a prerequisite; but reasonable background in metaphysics, epistemology, and philosophy of language is vital. Familiarity with certain metaethical theories (e.g., expressivism) would also be helpful. Our concern is with artworld objects and practices: familiarity with aspects of the visual arts, music, dance, sculpture, literature, photography, and/or other artistic domains is essential. Here are the topics to be explored: 1) The “ontology of art”: What is it? What questions is it intended to answer? Is there any more to the ontology of art than idle (and useless) re-description of the artworld data? How does an ontology of art add to our explanatory and/or justificatory power? 2) Is testimony about aesthetic properties of artworks a sufficient condition for aesthetic knowledge? Or is “direct acquaintance” with the works themselves necessary for such knowledge? Is there an interesting disanalogy between the epistemic credentials of testimony in the sciences and testimony in the arts? Perhaps only expert testimony is relevant here: But who are the artworld experts? By virtue of what do they qualify as experts? We will look at some literature on “moral experts” to see whether it is relevant (and if not, why not); we will also look at Kant’s views about the “autonomy” of “judgments of taste” and ask whether he saw the situation clearly (Hint: he did not).
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae: KENDALL LEWIS WALTON
    Curriculum Vitae: KENDALL LEWIS WALTON (Revised 31 October 2015) Department of Philosophy E-Mail: [email protected] 2215 Angell Hall WARNING: My email address contains 435 S. State St. TWO initials. Omitting the 'L' will send University of Michigan your message to another person. Ann Arbor, MI 48109 Webpage: https://sites.lsa.umich.edu/kendallwalton/ EDUCATION University of California, Berkeley, B.A. Cornell University, Ph.D. DISSERTATION Conceptual Schemes: A Study of Linguistic Relativity and Related Philosophical Problems. PROFESSIONAL POSITIONS Lecturer, Assistant Professor, Associate Professor, Professor, University of Michigan, 1965 – 2012. Charles L. Stevenson Collegiate Professor of Philosophy, University of Mich- igan, 1999 - 2012. Professor, School of Art and Design, University of Michigan, 2005 - 2012. Professor Emeritus of Philosophy, University of Michigan, 2012-present. Cowling Distinguished Visiting Professor in Philosophy, Carleton College, spring quarter, 2012. Wm H. Bonsall Visiting Professor, Stanford University, spring quarters 2015 - present. FELLOWSHIPS AND AWARDS (Selected) Stanford Humanities Center, Marta Sutton Weeks Fellowship, 1982-83. Rockefeller Foundation Humanities Fellowship, 1982-83. National Endowment for the Humanities Fellowship, 1990-91. Princeton University, Carl Hempel Lecturer, 1991. American Academy of Arts and Sciences, Fellow, elected 1998. Romanell-Phi Beta Kappa Professor of Philosophy, 2001-2002. President, American Society for Aesthetics, 2003-2005. Honorary degree: Doctor of Letters, University of Nottingham (UK), con- ferred July 2005. Curriculum Vitae KENDALL L. WALTON 2 SYMPOSIA AND WORKSHOPS ON MY WRITINGS Symposium, Listening with Imagination, on my writings on music. American Musicological Society, New York. Four speakers, with my responses. November 1995. “Workshop on the work of Kendall Walton,” Nottingham University (UK), July 2005.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae (Abbreviated) KENDALL L. WALTON
    Curriculum Vitae (abbreviated) KENDALL L. WALTON (Revised 24 March 2014) Department of Philosophy E-Mail: [email protected] 2215 Angell Hall WARNING: My email address 435 S. State St. contains TWO initials. Omitting the University of Michigan 'L' will send your message to Ann Arbor, MI 48109-1003 another person. Webpage: (734) 763-3492; (734) 764-6285 http://sitemaker.umich.edu/klwalton FAX: (734) 763-8071 EDUCATION B.A., University of California, Berkeley; PhD, Cornell University. PROFESSIONAL POSITIONS Charles L. Stevenson Collegiate Professor of Philosophy, University of Michigan. Currently Emeritus. Cowling Distinguished Visiting Professor in Philosophy, Carleton College, spring quarter, 2012. Wm H. Bonsall Visiting Professor, Stanford University, spring quarters 2015, 2016, 2017. FELLOWSHIPS AND AWARDS (Selected) Princeton University, Carl Hempel Lecturer, 1991. American Academy of Arts and Sciences, Fellow, elected 1998. President, American Society for Aesthetics, 2003-2005. Honorary degree: Doctor of Letters, University of Nottingham (UK), conferred July 2005. Fellowships from: American Council of Learned Societies, Australian National University, National Endowment for the Humanities, Stanford Humanities Center, Rockefeller Foundation, Sydney University. SYMPOSIA AND WORKSHOPS ON MY WRITINGS Symposium, Listening with Imagination, on my writings on music. American Musicological Society, New York. Four speakers, with my responses. November 1995. Curriculum Vitae, - KENDALL L. WALTON 2 “Workshop on the work of Kendall Walton,” Nottingham University (UK), July 2005. “Metaphysics, Mimesis, and Make-Believe: A Conference in Honour of Kendall Walton.” Leeds University, U.K. 21-23 June, 2007. Symposium: “Kendall Walton and the Aesthetics of Photography and Film.” University of Kent (Canterbury, U.K.), School of Drama, Film, & Visual Arts.
    [Show full text]
  • Aesthetics—What? Why? and Wherefore?
    KENDALL WALTON Aesthetics—What? Why? and Wherefore? It is a very great honor to address my friends and philosophy of quantum physics are younger. But colleagues as president of the American Society these are clearly subcategories of traditional, well- for Aesthetics, an organization that plays a unique established areas of philosophy—ethics and phi- role in a field that is, at once, a major traditional losophy of science—and they inherit much of their branch of philosophy and also central to disci- identity and sense of purpose from their parents. plines often regarded as remote from philosophy, Aesthetics is not so fortunate. It is related in vari- as well as depending crucially on their contribu- ous important ways to epistemology, metaphysics, tions. philosophy of mind, philosophy of language— I will follow the lead of one of my distinguished indeed it overlaps all of them—but these older predecessors in this office, Peter Kivy, who used relatives are at best aunts and uncles to aesthetics, the occasion of his own presidential address twelve not parents. Aesthetics must figure out for itself years ago to step back and reflect on the state of what exactly it is. the discipline and the nature of aesthetics.1 Two kinds of issues about the field need to be addressed: What is distinctive about this branch i. what is aesthetics? of philosophy, in contrast to others? And what is philosophy? Under the first heading, we will ask Aesthetics is a strange field, in some ways a con- what aesthetics is the philosophy of , what domain fused one.
    [Show full text]
  • Musical Expression
    AESTHETIC GESTURES: ESSAY IN FREGE–WITTGENSTEIN THEORY OF ART Nikolay Milkov (University of Paderborn) Summary Frege’s conception of works of art was scarcely discussed in the literature. This is a pity since, as we are going to see in this paper, his innovative philosophy of language also outlined fruitful perspectives in the realm of aesthetics. In short, Frege holds that only complete sen- tences express thought. Sentences of literature express only “mock thoughts”. The early Wittgenstein closely followed Frege on this point. The Tractatus holds that only propositions model (“picture”) states of affairs. Works of art are merely objects seen sub specie aeternitatis, beyond time (Wittgenstein 1961, p. 83). In the 1930s and 1940s, however, Wittgenstein started to claim that works of art can convey thoughts. But these thoughts do not model the world of facts. Instead, they can shape the style of our life. To be more exact, successful (gelungene), or cogent works of art can play the role of gestures that show life directions. In this sense, artists “have something to teach” (Wittgenstein 1980, p. 36). 1. Frege: Works of Art as One and Many We shall begin with Gottlob Frege’s philosophy of language which claims that only com- plete sentences express thoughts. Sentences stating commands, wishes, requests, etc., are “exclamations in which one vents feelings, groans, sighs, laugh”. (Frege 1918, p. 355) They are “mock thoughts” (Scheingedanken). Staring from this position, Frege advanced an idiosyncratic theory of art. According to it, “the poet does not really depict (malt) anything: he only provides the impetus for others to do so, furnishing hints (Winke) to this end, and leaving it to the hearer to give his words body and shape.” (Frege 1897, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Shelby Moser
    Shelby Moser [email protected] Curriculum Vitae (March 2020) AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION PHILOSOPHY, ANALYTIC AESTHETICS, ART HISTORY EDUCATION JULY 2018 PHD, UNIVERSITY OF KENT, CANTERBURY History & Philosophy of Art. Thesis title: Digitally Interactive Works and Video Games: A Philosophical Exploration. NOVEMBER 2013 MA, UNIVERSITY OF KENT, CANTERBURY History & Philosophy of Art. Graduated with Distinction and won Best in Program award. AUGUST 2006 MA, CALIFORNIA STATE UNIVERSITY, LOS ANGELES Art History. Honors. ACADEMIC EMPLOYMENT 2020 – PRESENT ADJUNCT FACULTY, AZUSA PACIFIC UNIVERSITY Department of Philosophy 2020 – PRESENT PART-TIME FACULTY, RIO HONDO COLLEGE Department of Arts & Cultural Programs 2010 – PRESENT ADJUNCT FACULTY, AZUSA PACIFIC UNIVERSITY Department of Art & Design 2013 – 2014 ASSISTANT LECTURER, UNIVERSITY OF KENT, CANTERBURY Philosophy and History of Art 2003-2004 STUDENT LECTURER, CALIFORNIA SATE UNIVERSITY, LOS ANGELES Department of Art History PUBLICATIONS ACADEMIC BOOK CHAPTERS • “Toward a New Theory of Appreciating Digital Works” (working title) forthcoming chapter (2021) in The Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Painting and Sculpture, Noël Carroll & Jonathan Gilmore, eds. • “The Ontology of Interactivity in Digital Art”, forthcoming (2020) chapter in the Routledge Handbook to the Philosophy of Games, C. Thi Nguyen & John Sageng, Eds. • “Videogame Ontology, Constitutive Rules, and Algorithms”, (2018) chapter in The Aesthetics of Video Games, in the Routledge Studies in Contemporary Philosophy series, Grant Tavinor & Jonathan Robson, Eds. SELECT JOURNAL ARTICLES • “The Philosophy of Digital Art”, the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2019), co-authored with Katherine Thomson-Jones. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/digital-art/#Bib • “Art and the Emotions: Debating the Work of Jenefer Robinson”, co-authored with Ryan Doran.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Cinematic Philosophy
    1 CINEMATIC PHILOSOPHY: EXPERIENTIAL AFFIRMATION IN MEMENTO Rafe McGregor The purpose of this paper is to demonstrate that Memento (Christopher Nolan, 2000) meets both conditions of Paisley Livingston’s bold thesis of cinema as philosophy. I introduce the bold thesis and delineate my argument in terms of Aaron Smuts’ clarifications of Livingston’s conditions in §1. §2 explains how Memento meets the results condition, which is concerned with the nature of the philosophical content, by employing a development of Berys Gaut’s conception of narrational confirmation that I designate experiential affirmation. In §3, I show that experiential affirmation is a function of cinematic depiction and therefore meets Livingston’s means condition, which is concerned with the capacities of the medium or art form. I address two objections to my argument in §4: that it collapses into Thomas Wartenberg’s moderate pro-cinematic philosophy position; and Smuts’ claim that the audience enacts the philosophy, not the film. I conclude with a brief commentary on the implications of my discussion of Memento for the broader relationship between film and philosophy. 1. Introduction provided by Edge Hill University Research Information Repository View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk CORE brought to you by There is a bewildering array of topics at the intersection of cinematic art and philosophical inquiry, and a variety of approaches within each topic. The confusion arising from the multitude of approaches to a multitude of issues is reflected in the nomenclature employed to link philosophy and film: philosophy of film, philosophy in film, philosophy on film, 2 philosophy through film, film as philosophy, film-philosophy, and filmosophy – amongst others.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Aesthetics 1. Course Overview 2. Requirements 3
    Eliot Michaelson Philosophy 336 Leacock 919 Fall 2013 [email protected] Office Hours: F 9:30–10:30 Introduction to Aesthetics 1. Course Overview This course will serve as a general introduction to aesthetics. Aesthetics is concerned pri- marily with questions of art and beauty: for example, what is art? What makes a work of art beautiful or valuable? Is aesthetic value objective or subjective? How are fictions and other aspects of artistic works created, and what are they about? In this course, we will examine these questions in particular through the medium of film. Films are particularly interesting for several reasons: we tend to think of them, by default, as both representational and real- istic. What’s more, they are plausibly the products of a whole group of artists — many of whom can lay claim to having had some agency over the final product — rather than any particular individual. This focus will lead us to ask a couple of more specific questions that arise in particular with regard to film: how do realistic media represent the world? What is realism itself? And can realism be valuable? 2. Requirements Students who take this course must be prepared to complete readings on time, as lectures will assume that students have read that weeks texts closely. Students are expected to have their texts with them at each class, and students may be called upon at random to discuss or explain parts of the weeks readings. 3. Prerequisites There are no formal prerequisites for this course, but it is a surprisingly challenging subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Fictionalism
    Moral Fictionalism Daniel Nolan (Syracuse University) Greg Restall (University of Melbourne) Caroline West (University of Sydney) Draft only. Please do not cite without permission. Introduction What would morality have to be like in order to answer to our everyday moral concepts? What are we committed to when we make moral claims such as “female infibulation is wrong”; or “we ought give money to famine relief”; or “we have a duty to not to harm others”, and when we go on to argue about these sorts of claims? It has seemed to many—and it seems plausible to us— that when we assert and argue about things such as these we presuppose at least the following. First, that there is a realm of moral facts (in a non-technical sense of ‘facts’); facts in virtue of which claims like “female infibulation is wrong” are true and claims like “acts of senseless cruelty are right” are false. When we argue about whether female infibulation is wrong, for example, we seem to presuppose that that there is a fact of the matter about the rightness or wrongness of female infibulation about which we can form beliefs and which makes at most one of the disagreeing parties right. Furthermore, we suppose that the rightness or wrongness of female infibulation is something that we can discover. The assumption that there is a discoverable fact about the rightness or wrongness of female infibulation, for example, which our moral beliefs can get right or wrong, explains the purpose and nature of ordinary moral debate. Second, we take these facts to be objective facts—the rightness or wrongness of female infibulation, for example, doesn’t depend on what we happen to think or feel.
    [Show full text]
  • Paths from the Philosophy of Art to Everyday Aesthetics
    PATHS FROM THE PHILOSOPHY OF ART TO EVERYDAY AESTHETICS Eds. Oiva Kuisma, Sanna Lehtinen and Harri Mäcklin Published in Helsinki, Finland by the Finnish Society for Aesthetics, 2019 MARKUS LAMMENRANTA HOW ART TEACHES: A LESSON FROM GOODMAN ABSTRACT It is often thought that art teaches us and that we can learn from it. To learn that p is to come to know that p. So, art can teach us only if we can gain knowledge through art. How is this possible? Nelson Goodman tries to explain it by his theory of symbols. However, his theory just explains how works of art can refer to the world, and referring to the world is not enough for having knowledge about the world. Because knowledge is a matter of having true beliefs, in order to give us knowledge, works of art must say something that is true. It is argued that we can explain how they can do this, if we revise and supplement certain aspects of Goodman’s theory of symbols. Furthermore, we can even explain how our built and natural environment can teach us. INTRODUCTION rtists typically think that they are doing research. They study the world and want to say something about it through their art. For example, in a recent documentary,1 Martin Scorsese was asked Awhy Woody Allen has made so many movies. He answered: “Because he has so much to say.” One hears this sort of statement every day—even from abstract artists. They think they do research, study reality. If this is what artists do—if they say things through their art—then at least sometimes what they say is true, and we can know that it is true.
    [Show full text]