Did Socrates Separate the Forms?1

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Did Socrates Separate the Forms?1 David O. Brink; UCSD Draft of 10-25-20 DID SOCRATES SEPARATE THE FORMS?1 Abstract: Aristotle tells us that Plato separates the forms whereas Socrates does not. Aristotle himself thinks that Plato was wrong to separate the forms and that Socrates was right not to. Commentators have focused on the meaning of separation and reconstructing and assessing Aristotle’s criticisms of Plato, for the most part accepting Aristotle’s claim that Socrates did not separate the forms. This essay challenges that assumption. Separation involves the capacity for independent existence. If so, Socratic assumptions about definition, knowledge, and the primacy of character imply that the forms of the virtues not only can but do exist uninstantiated. In addition to Plato’s early dialogues, Aristotle provides some of the most important and influential evidence we have about Socrates and his relationship to Plato.2 Among the things that Aristotle tells us is that Plato separates the forms whereas Socrates does not (Metaphysics I.6, 987a31-b10; XIII.4, 1078b29-31; XIII.9, 1086a30-b12). Aristotle himself thinks that Plato was wrong to separate the forms and that Socrates was right not to (1086b3-7). Though we are free to disagree with Aristotle’s philosophical verdict about the merits of separation, we have reason to take his testimony about the content of the views of Socrates and Plato quite seriously. He was a member of Plato’s Academy for twenty years, and he presumably had better information about the views of Socrates and Plato than is available to us. Aristotle’s testimony provides evidence for distinguishing within Plato’s dialogues between Socratic and Platonic dialogues and for a broadly developmental, rather than unitarian, reading of the relation between Socrates and Plato.3 Aristotle’s claims raise a number of interpretive and systematic issues. What exactly does it mean to separate the forms? Though there are several possible forms of separation (chōrismos), Gail Fine has made a strong case in her article “Separation” for thinking that the relevant kind of separation in this context for both Plato and Aristotle is the capacity for independent existence.4 On this conception of separation, forms are separate just in case they can exist uninstantiated by sensible particulars. But even if this is what separation involves, it leaves many questions about Aristotle’s testimony unanswered. In what sense does Socrates not separate the forms? Does Plato indeed separate the forms and, if so, why? What are Aristotle’s objections to separating forms, and are these good objections to Plato? 1 I am grateful for helpful feedback from Lesley Brown, Gail Fine, Monte Johnson, and Sam Rickless. 2 As is common, I assume that Plato’s early dialogues, supplemented by Aristotle’s testimony, provide our best evidence of the philosophical views of Socrates. In particular, I assume that by relying on a combination of philosophical content, dramatic content, and stylometric analysis we can provisionally divide Plato’s dialogues into different periods and groups: early Socratic dialogues (e.g. Apology, Crito, Euthyphro, Laches, Charmides, Euthydemus and Lysis), transitional dialogues (e.g. Protagoras and Gorgias), middle period Platonic dialogues (e.g. Meno, Phaedo, Republic, Symposium, Phaedrus, Parmenides, and Theaetetus), and late period Platonic dialogues (e.g. Timaeus, Sophist, Statesman, Philebus, and Laws). I read transitional dialogues as ones in which Plato is reflecting on and exploring the presuppositions and implications of philosophical commitments in the Socratic dialogues. 3 For a good discussion of unitarian and developmental narratives in Plato, see Terence Irwin, Plato’s Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), Chapter 1. 4 Gail Fine, “Separation” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 2 (1984): 31-87 and reprinted in Gail Fine, Plato on Knowledge and Forms (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2003) (my pagination for this article is indexed to the reprint in Fine’s book). Also see Gregory Vlastos, Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991), pp. 256-64. 2 The nature of forms and separation is just one dimension along which to assess Aristotle’s relation to Plato.5 Although many commentators accept Aristotle’s comparative claim that Plato separated the forms, whereas Socrates did not, there has been considerable focus on interpreting and assessing Aristotle’s claims about and disagreement with Plato. 6 For instance, there is lively controversy about whether Aristotle correctly understands Plato’s reasons for separating the forms and whether Aristotle’s reasons for refusing to separate the forms are sound.7 By contrast, there seems to be less controversy about Aristotle’s testimony about Socrates, in particular, his claim that Socrates did not separate the forms.8 However, I want to take seriously some skepticism about Aristotle’s testimony about Socrates. There is an interesting interpretation of Socratic commitments about the virtues that implies that the forms of the virtues are not just separable but in fact separate. The foundation of this argument for separation is Socratic intellectualism about the virtues. Because the virtues require knowledge of definitions of the virtues — definitions that must meet some fairly exacting criteria — we should conclude that Socrates believes that no one possesses the requisite knowledge and, hence, that no one is in fact virtuous. This is skepticism, not about the possibility of virtue, but about whether anyone is in fact virtuous. If no one is virtuous, then no one instantiates the virtues. This might seem to imply straightaway that the forms of the virtues exist uninstantiated. However, that is too quick a route to separation, because we might claim that there can be and are virtuous actions and institutions even if no one is in fact virtuous, because these are the actions that a virtuous person would perform or the institutions that a virtuous polis would enact. But we remove this obstacle to separation if we adopt a principle about the primacy of character that maintains that actions only count as genuinely virtuous if performed in the right way by a virtuous person and that institutions only count as genuinely virtuous if adopted in the right way by virtuous individuals or groups. Socratic skepticism about moral knowledge and virtues of character together with this thesis about the primacy of character imply that the forms of the virtues are separate. The primacy of character is perhaps the most controversial part of this argument for Socratic separation. It is neither obviously Socratic nor obviously correct, but it has some plausibility as both an interpretive and a systematic claim. At the very least, we can defend the interesting and non-trivial conclusion that Socrates does separate the forms insofar as he embraces the primacy of character. This should give us some pause about accepting Aristotle’s testimony about Socratic assumptions about the forms. 5 Famously, conflicting developmental narratives of Aristotle’s relation to Plato are presented in Werner Jaeger, Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development, trs. R. Robinson (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1934) and G.E.L. Owen, “The Platonism of Aristotle” Proceedings of the British Academy 51 (1966): 125-50. More nuanced views can be found in Gail Fine, On Ideas (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993) and Christopher Shields, “Plato and Aristotle in the Academy” in The Oxford Handbook of Plato, ed. G. Fine (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2008). 6 See, e.g., J.D. Mabbott, “Aristotle and the Chorismos of Plato” Classical Quarterly 20 (1926): 72-79; Harold Cherniss, Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato and the Academy, vol. 1 (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press, 1944); W.D. Ross, Plato’s Theory of Ideas (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1951), ch. 10; F.M. Cornford, Plato and Parmenides (London: Routledge, 1939), p. 74; Terence Irwin, Plato’s Moral Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 148-57; and Fine, “Separation,” pp. 295-98. 7 See, especially, Fine “Separation” and On Ideas. 8 R.E. Allen appears to be an exception, claiming that Socrates did separate the forms, because he distinguished between forms (universals) and their instances. See R.E. Allen, Plato’s Euthyphro and the Earlier Theory of Forms (London: Routledge, 1970), p. 136. But that cannot be the meaning of separation for purposes of evaluating Aristotle’s testimony about Socrates and Plato forms, since Aristotle himself separated the forms in that sense. See, Fine, “Separation,” pp. 295-98. 3 1. ARISTOTLE’S TESTIMONY AND SEPARATION Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle all recognize the existence of forms (eide) or universals (katholou, koina) and assign them epistemological importance. But they differ in their reasons for recognizing forms, their beliefs about the nature of forms, and the epistemological significance they ascribe to forms. As with many topics in the Metaphysics and elsewhere, Aristotle situates his own views in relation to those of his predecessors, especially Socrates and Plato. For instance, in Metaphysics I.6 Aristotle contrasts Socratic and Platonic reasons for recognizing forms and their conceptions of them. For, having in his youth first become familiar with Cratylus and with the Heraclitean doctrines (that all sensible things are ever in a state of flux and there is no knowledge about them), these views he [Plato] held even in later years. Socrates, however, was busying himself about ethical matters and neglecting the world of nature as a whole but seeking the universal in these ethical matters, and fixed thought for the first time on definitions; Plato accepted his teaching, but held that the problem applied not to any sensible thing but to entities of another kind …. Things of this other sort, then, he called Ideas, and sensible things, he said, were apart [para] from these … [987a31-b7].9 Later in Metaphysics XIII Aristotle is discussing the forms for mathematical objects, such as triangles and circles, and their relation to actual material bodies.
Recommended publications
  • Gregory Vlastos
    Gregory Vlastos: A Preliminary Inventory of His Papers at the Harry Ransom Center Descriptive Summary Creator: Vlastos, Gregory, 1907-1991 Title: Gregory Vlastos Papers Dates: circa 1930s-1991 Extent: 100 document boxes (42.00 linear feet) Abstract: The papers of philosopher Gregory Vlastos, a scholar of ancient Greek philosophy who spent most of his career studying the thought of Plato and Socrates, document his studies, his writings, and his career as an educator at several American universities. Call Number: Manuscript Collection MS-4361 Language: English, with Ancient Greek, French, German, Italian, Latin, Modern Greek, and Spanish Access: Open for research Administrative Information Acquisition: Gifts, 1993-2010 (G9070, G9134, G9163, G9225, G9252, G9628, G9979, G9982, G10214, G10288, G11877, 10-03-014-G) Processed by: Hope Rider, 2006; updated by Joan Sibley, 2016 Repository: The University of Texas at Austin, Harry Ransom Center Vlastos, Gregory, 1907-1991 Manuscript Collection MS-4361 Scope and Contents The papers of philosopher Gregory Vlastos (1907-1991), a scholar of ancient Greek philosophy who spent most of his career studying the thought of Plato and Socrates, document his studies, his writings, and his career as an educator at several American universities, especially Cornell, Princeton, and The University of California at Berkeley. The papers are arranged in six series: I. Correspondence and Offprint Files, II. Study, Lecture, and Teaching Files, III. Works, IV. Works by Others, V. Miscellaneous, and VI. Offprints Removed from Manuscripts. The Correspondence and Offprint Files (35 boxes) in Series I. represent Vlastos' extensive correspondence with other philosophers, classicists, former students, academics, and others. The files are arranged alphabetically by correspondent name, and generally include not only letters received, but copies of Vlastos' responses.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Revision of Platonic Erōs and Philia A
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Texas A&M University EMBRACING THE HALF: ARISTOTLE’S REVISION OF PLATONIC ERŌS AND PHILIA A Thesis by EMIL SALIM Submitted to the Office of Graduate Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS May 2006 Major Subject: Philosophy EMBRACING THE HALF: ARISTOTLE’S REVISION OF PLATONIC ERŌS AND PHILIA A Thesis by EMIL SALIM Submitted to the Office of Graduate Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS Approved by: Chair of Committee, Robin Smith Committee Members, Scott Austin Craig Kallendorf Head of Department, Robin Smith May 2006 Major Subject: Philosophy iii ABSTRACT Embracing the Half: Aristotle’s Revision of Platonic Erōs and Philia. (May 2006) Emil Salim, B.A., Universitas Tarumanagara, Indonesia; M.Div., Evangelical Reformed Theological Seminary, Indonesia Chair of Advisory Committee: Dr. Robin Smith In this thesis, I am investigating the nature of e[rwV (erōs) and filiva (philia) in Plato and Aristotle. I have confined this project to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics (EN) and Metaphysics, with a background discussion of Plato’s Symposium and Phaedrus. I will argue for the following claims. First, Plato’s Symposium poses a dilemma with respect to the object and nature of e[rwV. The dilemma is that the objects of e[rwV must be either particular individuals or the Beautiful itself. Second, Plato’s Phaedrus may be seen as Plato’s attempt to solve the dilemma by giving a synthesis: e[rwV is a virtuous maniva and should be directed to particular individuals en route to the Beautiful.
    [Show full text]
  • Pleonexia, Parasitic Greed, and Decline in Greek Thought from Thucydides to Polybius
    ABSTRACT Title of Document: HOW THINGS FALL APART: PLEONEXIA, PARASITIC GREED, AND DECLINE IN GREEK THOUGHT FROM THUCYDIDES TO POLYBIUS William D. Burghart, Doctor of Philosophy, 2015 Directed By: Professor Arthur M. Eckstein, Department of History This dissertation examines how Greek authors from the fifth to the second century BCE employed the concept of pleonexia to explain why cities lost power on the international stage and why they lost internal cohesion. First, it argues that Greek authors understood pleonexia to mean “the desire for more at the expense of another” as opposed simply “greed” as most modern authors translate it. Second, it contends that Greeks authors deployed the concept of pleonexia to describe situations that modern authors would describe as societal collapse—defined as the reduction of societal complexity, which can be measured through either the loss of material or immaterial means, e.g., land, wealth, political power, influence over others, political stability, or political autonomy. Greek authors used the language of pleonexia to characterize the motivation of an entity, either an individual within a community or a city or state, to act in a way that empowered the entity by taking or somehow depriving another similar entity of wealth, land, or power. In a city, pleonexia manifested as an individual seeking to gain power through discrediting, prosecuting, or eliminating rivals. In international affairs, it materialized as attempts of a power to gain more territory or influence over others. Acting on such an impulse led to conflict within cities and in the international arena. The inevitable result of such conflict was the pleonexic power losing more than it had had before.
    [Show full text]
  • CU Classics Graduate Handbook
    Graduate Handbook (CU Boulder, Classics) 1 Graduate Handbook University of Colorado Boulder Department of Classics Last updated: October 2018; minor corrections September 2020 Graduate Handbook (CU Boulder, Classics) 2 Contents Graduate Introduction .................................................................................................................... 4 M.A. Tracks.................................................................................................................................. 4 Ph.D. Track .................................................................................................................................. 4 Graduate Degrees in Classics .......................................................................................................... 5 Graduate Degrees and Requirements ........................................................................................ 5 Doctor of Philosophy in Classics ................................................................................................. 6 M.A. in Classics, with Concentration in Greek or Latin ............................................................... 8 M.A. in Classics, with Concentration in Classical Antiquity ........................................................ 9 M.A. in Classics, with Concentration in Classical Art and Archaeology .................................... 11 M.A. in Classics, with Concentration in the Teaching of Latin .................................................. 12 Ph.D. Requirements .....................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Gregory Vlastos, Myles Burnyeat
    This is the companion volume to Gregory Vlastos' highly acclaimed work Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Four ground-breaking papers which laid the basis for his understanding of Socrates are collected here, in revised form: they examine Socrates' elenctic method of investigative argument, his disavowal of knowledge, his concern for definition, and the complica- tions of his relationship with the Athenian democracy. The fifth chapter is a new and provocative discussion of Socrates' arguments in the Protagoras and Laches. The epilogue "Socrates and Vietnam" suggests that Socrates was not, as Plato claimed, the most just man of his time. The papers have been prepared for publication by Professor Myles Burnyeat with the mini- mum of editorial intervention. This book will be essential reading for all students and scholars of ancient philosophy. SOCRATIC STUDIES SOCRATIC STUDIES GREGORY VLASTOS Formerly Emeritus Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University and at the University of California at Berkeley EDITED BY MYLES BURNYEAT Laurence Professor of Ancient Philosophy in the University of Cambridge m>;|§gj CAMBRIDGE 0 UNIVERSITY PRESS CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sao Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521442138 © Cambridge University Press 1994 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 1994 Reprinted 1995 A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication data Vlastos, Gregory.
    [Show full text]
  • [Individuality and Love in Plato]
    Love and the Individual The Morality of Platonic Love and its Metaphysical Presuppositions by Hege Dypedokk Johnsen Thesis presented for the degree of MASTER OF PHILOSOPHY Supervised by Professor Øyvind Rabbås Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Art and Ideas Faculty of Humanities UNIVERSITY OF OSLO Spring 2011 II Suppose you were molding gold into every shape there is, going on non-stop remolding one shape into the next. If someone then were to point at one of them and ask you, “What is it?”, your safest answer by far, with respect to the truth, would be to say “gold”, but never “triangle” or any of the other shapes that come to be in the gold, as though it is these, because they change even while you‟re making the statement. Timeaus, 50a–b “That,” he said, “is my speech about Love, Eryximachus. It is rather different from yours. As I begged you earlier, don‟t make comedy of it…” Symposium, 193d III IV Abstract What is it that we really love when we love an individual person, and to what extent are we egoistical in the search for happy love? Moreover, what/whom should we love, and for what reason? I approach the subject “Love and the Individual” by analyzing Gregory Vlastos‟ two main charges against Plato‟s theory of love: Firstly, that Plato‟s theory fails to give a satisfying account of love directed from one individual towards another individual; and secondly, that it is essentially egoistical. Throughout the thesis I underscore the points considered vulnerable to criticism, and highlight the phenomena subjected to insufficient treatment.
    [Show full text]
  • Proceedings from the Australasian Society for Continental Philosophy
    parrhesia 28 · 2017 proceedings from the australasian society for continental philosophy conference 2016 edited by sean bowden and matthew sharpe editorial assistance from timothy deane- freeman and max lowdin parrhesia 28 · 2017 · 1-18 abundance—of critique penelope deutscher In the context of a dialogue with Carole Pateman1 and intersectionality frame- works, Charles Mills has grouped himself with those who would render more complex the account of women as historically subordinated by virtue of European legal traditions such as the feme covert status denying them an independent legal identity. To factor the histories of colonialism, slavery, and race hierarchies, is to reconsider the analysis of women’s subordination and exclusion from the public and political sphere by virtue of sex. It is also to reconsider some of the conven- tions of white feminism’s historical rights claims, among them, the depiction of the family and home as spaces in which women have primarily been confined to a subordinated and limiting domestic role. This depiction, as has been empha- sized by a number of intersectionality theorists, occludes the different status and meaning of home and family under the conditions of colonization and slavery. For example, bell hooks opens Ain’t I a woman by distinguishing the specific forms of violence to which female slaves were exposed in the United States, and also by emphasizing slaves’ lack of legal freedom to marry, lack of parental rights, lack of secure private domestic spaces in which to enjoy intimacy and family bonds, exposure to sexual violence, dispossession of children, and the regulation of de facto unions.2 While this isn’t to forget, as hooks emphasizes, that in their do- mestic unions, enslaved women were also subject to gender subordination,3 pa- triarchal domination might not be the only or best means of understanding the forms of both power and resistance most salient to the home.
    [Show full text]
  • Friendship As a Non-Relative Virtue
    Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy https://doi.org/10.26556/jesp.v20i1.1263 Vol. 20, No. 1 · July 2021 © 2021 Author FRIENDSHIP AS A NON-RELATIVE VIRTUE Rachel Z. Friedman his article takes its bearings from Martha Nussbaum’s “Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach,” which argues that Aristotle’s ethics Tare grounded in fundamental and hence universal spheres of human func- tioning in which the various virtues are meant to represent excellent action.1 In calling attention to this important underlying feature of Aristotle’s account, Nussbaum articulates a promising approach to the virtues that can accommo- date cultural variations in their expression. The underlying spheres or “ground- ing experiences” that she identifies allow for the possibility of comparison among different accounts of what good action entails. Once such a sphere has been identified as the proper locus of the virtue in question, those who disagree about the appropriate ways of acting can be seen, not as talking past one another, but rather as “arguing about the same thing, and advancing competing specifi- cations of the same virtue.”2 A virtue ethics based on Aristotle’s structure can thus remain grounded in human experience while also critiquing local customs in the name of “a more inclusive account of the circumstances of human life.”3 The aim of this article is to explore what such an approach to the virtues might look like in practice. To that end, it takes up the case study of friendship, the pinnacle of Aristotle’s account of the ethical life. Friendship is a somewhat problematic virtue: Aristotle says it is a virtue or “involves virtue,” and there is a strong case to be made that both claims are true.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's 'Republic': an Introduction
    Plato’s Republic Plato’s Republic An Introduction An Introduction SEAN MCALEER SEAN MCALEER S EAN M This book is a lucid and accessible companion to Plato’s Republic, throwing light C upon the text’s arguments and main themes, placing them in the wider context A LEER of the text’s structure. In its illumina� on of the philosophical ideas underpinning the work, it provides readers with an understanding and apprecia� on of the P complexity and literary ar� stry of Plato’s Republic. McAleer not only unpacks the key overarching ques� ons of the text – What is just ce? And Is a just life happier than an unjust life? – but also highlights some fascina� ng, overlooked passages which contribute to our understanding of Plato’s philosophical thought. Plato’s ‘Republic’: An Introduct on off ers a rigorous and thought-provoking analysis of the text, helping readers navigate one of the world’s most infl uen� al works of LATO philosophy and poli� cal theory. With its approachable tone and clear presenta� on, it cons� tutes a welcome contribu� on to the fi eld, and will be an indispensable ’ S resource for philosophy students and teachers, as well as general readers new to, or returning to, the text. R EPUBLIC As with all Open Book publica� ons, this en� re book is available to read for free on the publisher’s website. Printed and digital edi� ons, together with supplementary digital material, can also be found at www.openbookpublishers.com Cover image: Anselm Feuerbach’s The Symposium (1871-1874).
    [Show full text]
  • Self- Knowledge
    SELF- KNOWLEDGE Engelsberg Ironworks April 25 2019 a seminar arranged by axel and margaret ax:son johnson foundation SELF-KNOWLEDGE Thursday April 25th 2019 A Seminar Arranged by Axel and Margaret Ax:son Johnson Foundation The unexamined life is not worth living, Socrates says in Plato’s Apology. In this seminar we will examine the meaning of self-knowledge, in the eyes of ancient and medieval thinkers, mystics and philosophers. Our focus might be on ancient Greece, from Heraclitus, the Greek Mystery-schools to Socrates and Aristoteles, but we will also rise above that and take a look at later Chris- tian, Jewish and Islamic thought on self-knowledge. And we will also listen to ancient voices from China and India, telling us about self and non-self, unity and an incomprehensible simultaneous difference. What self-knowledge means varies from time, culture and thinker. But one also finds some common ground. One such is mors mystica, the self has to die and be reborn to become a truer self. Superficial self-knowledge is not enough. Egocentricity doesn’t belong to the realm of deeper self-knowledge. Meister Eckhart, influential fourteenth century Dominican, sums this up neatly when he says: Examine yourself. And whenever you find yourself, take leave of yourself. PROGRAMME 13:00 Kurt Almqvist, President, Ax:son Johnson Foundation 13:05 Moderator: Ulf Wickbom Self-Knowledge in Greek Thought 13:10 Christopher Moore: Heraclitus and Socrates on Knowing Oneself 13:25 Jan N. Bremmer: Did the Mysteries Produce Self-Knowledge? 13:40 Terence Irwin: Why We Need Friends for Self-Knowledge 13:55 Discussion 14:10 Coffee Break Self-Knowledge in Classical China and India 14:30 Michael Puett: Making and Unmaking the Self 14:45 Antoon Geels: Self and No Self in Buddhism 15:00 Ravi M.
    [Show full text]
  • The Record 2007 (Pdf)
    The Record 2007 Adrian Swayne Hollis, B.Phil., MA Fellow and Tutor in Classics 1967–2007, Honorary D.Litt., St Andrews. photograph by Eric Purchase Photography The Record 2007 Contents The Life of the College Letter from the Warden 5 Professor Michael Frede 8 Fellows’ Work in Progress 8 Fellows’ Publications 16 Sports and Games 23 Clubs and Societies 27 The Chapel 28 Financial Review 30 The College at Large Old Members at Work 34 Keble Parishes 38 Year Groups 38 Gifts and Bequests 39 Obituaries 47 The Keble Association 63 The London Dinner 64 Keble College 2006–7 The Fellowship 65 College Elections and Appointments 70 Undergraduate Scholarships 70 Matriculation 2006–7 72 College Awards and Prizes 77 Honours and Distinctions 83 Supplement News of Old Members 2 Forthcoming events 2007–8 12 Keble College: The Record 2007 4 The Life of the College Letter from the Warden It is hard to believe that this is the thirteenth Letter I have written for the College Record. Unlike its appearance and presentation, the format of The Record has not changed dramatically in that time. It is still important to have a publication literally of record, which documents what has been happening in the College during the past year, although now we include more news of old members, and of course we also have the brick, a parallel but very different publication. Perhaps this balance may change somewhat in the future, and we will certainly need a fuller and more formal annual report when, like all the colleges and the University itself, we come to register with the Charity Commission.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE RICHARD BETT Department of Philosophy
    CURRICULUM VITAE RICHARD BETT Department of Philosophy The Johns Hopkins University Citizen of U.K. Baltimore, MD 21218-2686 Permanent Resident of U.S. Phone: (410) 516-6863 Fax: (410) 516-6848 e-mail: <[email protected]> EDUCATION B.A. Oxford University, 1980, Literae Humaniores (Classics and Philosophy). First Class Honours, Final Examinations, 1980; First Class Honours, Honour Moderations in Greek & Latin Literature, 1978 Ph.D. University of California, Berkeley, 1986, Philosophy. Dissertation Title: “Moral Scepticism: Why Ask ‘Why Should I be Moral?’” CURRENT POSITION Professor and Chair of Philosophy, The Johns Hopkins University; secondary appointment in Classics PREVIOUS POSITIONS Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Texas at Arlington, 1986-1991 Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, Jan.-June 1991 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, 1991-1994 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, 1994-2000; secondary appointment in Classics, 1996-2000 Acting Executive Director, The American Philosophical Association, Jan. 2000-June 2001 PUBLICATIONS a) Books Sextus Empiricus, Against the Ethicists (Adversus Mathematicos XI): Introduction, Translation and Commentary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997, paperback 2000). Pp. xxxiv + 302 Pyrrho, his Antecedents and his Legacy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000, paperback 2003). Pp. xi + 264 Sextus Empiricus, Against the Logicians (Adversus Mathematicos VII-VIII): Introduction, Translation and Notes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005). Pp. xliv
    [Show full text]