From Political Eruptions to Climate Change

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

From Political Eruptions to Climate Change THE ETHOS OF THE EVENT: FROM POLITICAL ERUPTIONS TO CLIMATE CHANGE by Kellan Anfinson A dissertation submitted to Johns Hopkins University in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Baltimore, Maryland March, 2015 © Kellan Anfinson All Rights Reserved Abstract This project explores “the event” and its roles in political life, with a focus on articulating an ethos that better attunes us to an eventful world. Prominent among the unexpected events that punctuate political affairs, climate change drives and is driven by an acceleration of pace in several domains of contemporary life. The difficulty in engaging this event is revealed by the denials and deferrals we have faced in forging a political response to it. Thus the question that motivates this study: If an event is diffuse, complex, and elusive, what kind of ethos is needed to recognize, engage, and respond to it? We are in need of an ethos that attends to the kind of sensibility to be developed generally in a world punctuated by events and the existential-spiritual responses most appropriate when we actually encounter one. To forge such an understanding, I examine comparatively Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Schmitt, and Foucault. Each of these thinkers has worked through enigmatic, intense, and turbulent events such as the birth of Christ, the death of God, the rise of a fascist leader, and the collapse of a familiar mode of knowing. Climate change belongs to such an order of events. I argue for an experimental and supple ethos that moves beyond anthropocentrism through attunement to both micro- and macro-expressions of climate change. This study challenges political responses that use climate destabilization to seize power, as it deploys a history of previous eruptions to help us engage this one. Critically, climate responsiveness requires a spiritual resolve to dwell in uncertainty and discomfort, while being attached affirmatively to a world that contains tragic elements. ii Acknowledgements Thanks being due on a wider scale than custom and memory permit, I will limit myself to the strongest influences. I would like to thank William E. Connolly for the wise mentorship that gave me the intellectual space and time to work freely, and that imposed the necessary demands to make things cohere into a project the shape of which he often saw before I did. Jane Bennett’s intellectual generosity seems to be without bounds. She also bakes excellent bread. PJ Brendese, Andrea Krauss, and Naveeda Khan graciously read and gave invaluable comments on this project for the defense. Emma McGlennen, Derek Denman, Chitra Venkataramani, Troy Tower, and Tripp Rebrovick read a draft and contributed essential refinements for the final version. My colleagues across departments at Johns Hopkins have been a constant source of intellectual engagement, support, and conviviality. My intellectual guides at Macalester College—Frank Adler, Kiarina Kordela, and David Blaney—set me on this course in the first place. The Max Kade Center for Modern Thought at Johns Hopkins provided funding to conduct research for chapter three. It often seems that I am simply a node through which various influences have been able to interact. In this sense it also seems appropriate to thank chance. iii Table of Contents Introduction What is Happening? 2 Chapter One Passionate Transformations: Believing in the Event 14 Chapter Two Uncontrolled Experiments: Feeling an Eventful World 56 Chapter Three Risk or Security? Decisiveness and the Event 100 Chapter Four Foucault's Techniques of the Event 137 Chapter Five An Ethos for the Climate Event 189 iv One morning, We woke up in an alley. To the smell of urine, alcohol, Trash and gasoline, With a dim sense of a notion We'd held something in our hands, That was bigger than us or God, And we can never touch again. And we say that the world isn't dying. And we pray that the world isn't dying. And just maybe the world isn't dying. I've been looking at the symptoms for a while, Maybe she's heavy with child. -Jason Webley, Last Song “I think we will fail, but I don’t know we will fail.” – Kevin Anderson, climate scientist 1 Introduction What is Happening? As a man divinely abstracted and self-absorbed into whose ears the bell has just drummed the twelve strokes of noon will suddenly awake with a start and ask himself what hour has actually struck, we sometimes rub our ears after the event and ask ourselves, astonished and at a loss, “What have we really experienced”—or rather, “Who are we, really?” And we recount the twelve tremulous strokes of our experience, our life, our being, but unfortunately count wrong.1 In these opening lines to the Genealogy of Morals, Nietzsche uses the event to question the terms of our existence. Unlike many theories of the event, Nietzsche emphasizes how we might miss it, left only to assemble a few pieces of ourselves in its aftermath. Indeed, the original German text does not reference the event directly; it allows it to slip by the inattentive reader unheeded, with the word “afterward” as the sign of its occurrence. The reverberations of an event can help us think about our relation to it and how our existence is constituted. But such investigations are inadequate. Rather than merely trying to retroactively unearth connections between existence and the event, events also need to be proactively probed, shaped, and forged. Thus the question that motivates this study: If the event is diffuse, ineffable, or elusive, what kind of ethos is necessary to recognize, engage, and respond to the event? But since, as Nietzsche points out, this is a historical question, it concerns the contemporary situation. Just as Nietzsche uses the event to sound out the subject after God, this study examines climate destabilization to sound out the subject in the Anthropocene. The event is an important concept for modernity and interest in it has grown in recent decades.2 Part of its appeal seems to lie in its ability to stand in as a transcendental 1 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy and The Genealogy of Morals, trans. Francis Golffing (Garden City N.Y.: Doubleday, 1956), 147. 2 The event has even spread to popular analyses. See for example Naomi Klein's Shock Doctrine (New York: Picador, 2007) and Nicolas Nassim Taleb's The Black Swan (New York: Random House, 2010). For a more academic and theoretically provocative consideration of the latter in terms of the event, see Elie Ayache's 2 element in a philosophical system. In this way it can carry out a unifying function, often negatively, that God no longer can. But this take tends to freeze the event, making it unwieldy for both thought and politics. Indeed, the problem is that many thinkers of the event grant it a degree of independence, necessity, and even (anti-)metaphysical fortitude, which it may not have. A short survey of some important thinkers of the event will show this. Michael Marder effectively summarizes some primary insights and connections between Heidegger's and Derrida's theories of the event. Heidegger's event of appropriation “does not grasp something definitively present but performatively creates the second beginning of philosophy in the 'inceptual' leap that, instead of landing on an already formed terrain, finds a new grounding in itself.”3 Appropriation of the event is thus a philosophical movement which un-grounds experience only to conceptually reground it and, in so doing, draws out what is constitutive but unexamined in experience. In contrast to this, Derrida's event is expropriative, approaching Heidegger's notion from the other side. For Derrida, the act of appropriation that makes experience one's own is so singular as to be impossible, abyssally so. “Ereignis in abyss...seduces with 'the allure of the inappropriable event...' that indefinitely defers the situation, in which one would find oneself in absolute proximity to oneself, the situation every metaphysics of presence counts upon.”4 Though Heidegger tries to ground experience in an evental leap of appropriation, Derrida expropriates that movement, arguing that experience is itself inappropriable. A person never manages to fully secure their subjectivity because of the “sheer uniqueness and utter generality”5 of it. The elements that constitute experience are both unique in themselves (and thus potentially so The Blank Swan (Chichester, West Sussex: John Wiley & Sons, 2010). 3 Michael Marder Groundless Existence: The Political Ontology of Carl Schmitt (New York: Continuum, 2010), 62. 4 Ibid., 62. 5 Ibid., 62. 3 for each individual) but also generalizable to everyone's experience. For we all experience events. The event of securing the subject thus becomes an impossible yet alluring task, whose very instability is more appropriate to the shape of experience. Heidegger and Derrida both develop concepts of the event that bring out some of the texture of experience, but their notions remain limited. For them, the event emerges only through rigorous thought, which controls and limits the interruptive force of the event. Furthermore, it seems unlikely that experience is structured solely on a spectrum between appropriation and expropriation. In his essay “Writing the Event,” Roland Barthes analyzes May '68 in France to outline “the traces which constitute the event”6 with particular attention to the way that an event destabilizes existing systems and the potential transformations that it enables. Drawing on Derrida, he makes the distinction between speech that tries to lay claim to the event and has some revolutionary potential, and writing, which is “the dizzying break with the old symbolic system, the mutation of a whole range of language.”7 If an event is to produce novelty, it cannot be approached through a process of “decoding” which would speak to its true nature.
Recommended publications
  • The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play, and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2012 The idea of mimesis: Semblance, play, and critique in the works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno Joseph Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Joseph, "The idea of mimesis: Semblance, play, and critique in the works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno" (2012). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 125. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/125 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play, and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno A Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy October, 2011 By Joseph Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Sciences DePaul University Chicago, Illinois 2 ABSTRACT Joseph Weiss Title: The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno Critical Theory demands that its forms of critique express resistance to the socially necessary illusions of a given historical period. Yet theorists have seldom discussed just how much it is the case that, for Walter Benjamin and Theodor W.
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Resistance Nietzschean French Philosophy Is Without Equal
    Hoy 4/22/04 7:01 AM Page 1 “Hoy’s penetrating and multifaceted account of theories of resistance in post- Critical Resistance Nietzschean French philosophy is without equal. His analyses of genealogical From Poststructuralism to Post-Critique and deconstructionist modes of critique and his elaboration of the notion of David Couzens Hoy ‘critical resistance’ consistently evince the mastery we have come to expect from him. There is no better guide through the thickets of poststructualism This book serves as both an introduction to the and its aftermath.” concept of resistance in poststructuralist thought —Thomas McCarthy, Northwestern University Critical Critical Resistance and an original contribution to the continuing philosophical discussion of this topic. How can a “Critical Resistance offers fresh consideration of persistently vexing questions body of thought that mistrusts universal principles posed by poststructuralist philosophy: How is it possible to do away with explain the possibility of critical resistance? grounded norms and universal principles and at the same time offer a com- Without appeals to abstract norms, how can eman- pelling theoretical critique of the existing order of things? How can thinking cipatory resistance be distinguished from domina- practices that call all normativity into question also generate possibilities for From Poststructuralism tion? Can there be a poststructuralist ethics? David resistance to perceived domination or injustice? Indeed, how can such prac- Resistance Hoy explores these crucial questions
    [Show full text]
  • From Ressentiment to Resentment As a Tertiary Emotion
    Review of European Studies; Vol. 10, No. 4; 2018 ISSN 1918-7173 E-ISSN 1918-7181 Published by Canadian Center of Science and Education From Ressentiment to Resentment as a Tertiary Emotion Warren D. TenHouten1 1 Department of Sociology, University of California, Los Angeles, California, USA Correspondence: Warren D. TenHouten, Department of Sociology, 264 Haines Hall, UCLA, 405 Hilgard Avenue, Los Angeles, CA 90095–1551, USA. Received: May 14, 2018 Accepted: June 28, 2018 Online Published: September 5, 2018 doi:10.5539/res.v10n4p49 URL: https://doi.org/10.5539/res.v10n4p49 Abstract Resentment is a noxious emotion that can exist in sublimated form as a result of being subjected to inferiorization, stigmazation, or violence. In its active form, resentment can be a forceful response to acts that have created unjustified and meaningless suffering. We consider sociomoral conceptualizations of resentment by Adam Smith, Hume, and Lévinas. Nietzsche and Scheler developed the broader notion of ressentiment, a generalized form of resentment arising out of powerlessness and the experience of brutalization neither forgotten nor forgiven. Resentment is seen historically as a sentiment that is saturated with frustration, contempt, outrage, and malevolence. Marshall described oppositional class-consciousness as permeated with resentment and anger, but resentment also contains the basic emotions of surprise and disgust. Resentment is linked to the concept of relative deprivation. A partial classification of emotions is used to further analyze resentment as containing three secondary-level emotions: contempt (anger & disgust), shock (surprise & disgust), and outrage (surprise & anger). Thus, resentment is conceptualized as a tertiary-level emotion, containing three primary and three secondary emotions.
    [Show full text]
  • Towards a Phenomenology of Liberation: a Critical Theory of Race and the Fate of Democracy in Latin America”
    APA Newsletters NEWSLETTER ON HISPANIC/LATINO ISSUES IN PHILOSOPHY Volume 10, Number 1 Fall 2010 FROM THE EDITOR, BERNIE J. CANTEÑS ARTICLES CARLOS ALBERTO SANCHEZ “Against Values: Culture and Phenomenology in Jorge Portilla and Max Scheler” ALEJANDRO A. VALLEGA “Philosophy Beyond Pernicious Knowledge, from a Latin American Perspective” NYTHAMAR DE OLIVEIRA “Towards a Phenomenology of Liberation: A Critical Theory of Race and the Fate of Democracy in Latin America” BOOK REVIEW Enrique Dussel, Eduardo Mendieta, Carmen Bohórquez, Eds.: El pensamiento filósofico latinoamericano, del Caribe y “latino” [1300-2000]: Historia, Temas, Filósofos REVIEWED BY GRANT SILVA SUBMISSIONS CONTRIBUTORS © 2010 by The American Philosophical Association ISSN 2155-9708 APA NEWSLETTER ON Hispanic/Latino Issues in Philosophy Bernie J. Canteñs, Editor Fall 2010 Volume 10, Number 1 phenomenology.” De Oliveira’s thesis is developed in three ROM THE DITOR parts: (1) Philosophy of Race, (2) Liberation Philosophy, and F E (3) Critical Theory. According to de Oliveira, this new social phenomenology will avoid the “objectivist claims of Marxism” and “subjectivist ‘representations’ of postcolonial and cultural Bernie Canteñs studies.” De Oliveira adopts a “weak social constructionist” Moravian College conception of race. He understands that any account of race in Latin America will be intertwined with political and social The fall 2010 issue of the Newsletter contains Carlos Alberto psychology, and his philosophy of race intends to deconstruct Sanchez’s “Against Values: Culture and Phenomenology in racial democracy myths or scientific and historical conceptions Jorge Portilla and Max Scheler.” Sanchez’s essay compares of race, and Eurocentric myths of liberation such as democracy, the “European crisis of value” with the “Mexican crisis of liberalism, and socialism.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel: Three Studies I Theodor W
    Hegel Three Studies · I Hegel Three Studies Theodor W. Adorno. translated by Shierry Weber Nicholsen with an introduction by Shierry Weber Nicholsen and Jeremy]. Shapiro \\Imi\�\\�\i\il\"t�m .� . 39001101483082 The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, and London, England ·" '.�. This edition © 1993 Massachusetts Institute of Technology This work originally appeared in German under the title Drei Studien zu Hegel, © 1963, 1971 Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main, Germany. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any fo rm or by any electronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or information storage and retrieval) without permission in writing from the publisher. This book was set in Baskerville by The Maple-Vail Book Manufacturing Group and was printed and bound in the United States of America. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Adorno, Theodor W., 1903-1969. [Drei Studien zu Hegel. English] Hegel: three studies I Theodor W. Adorno ; translated by Shierry Weber Nicholsen ; with an introduction by Shierry Weber Nicholsen and Jeremy J. Shapiro. p. cm.-(Studies in contemporary German social thought) Translation of: Drei Studien zu Hegel. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-262-01131-X 1. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 1770- 1831. 1. Title. 11. Series. B2948.A3213 1993 193----dc20 92-23161 CIP ..�. •. , ......... ..,..·...",...,..'''_''e ... • 11�. I },i . :-::" 7.�� <,f,' · '�: · : :-:- ;;· �:<" For Karl Heinz Haag 337389 Contents Introduction by Shierry Weber Nicholsen and IX Jeremy J. Shapiro Preface XXXv A Note on the Text xxxvii Editorial Remarks from the German Edition XXXIX Aspects of Hegel's Philosophy 1 The Experiential Content of Hegel's Philosophy 53 Skoteinos, or How to Read Hegel 89 Notes 149 Name Index 159 Introduction Shierry Weber Nicholsen Jeremy J.
    [Show full text]
  • Explaining Postmodernism
    SUB Hamburg Explaining Postmodernism Skepticism and Socialism from Rousseau to Foucault Expanded Edition Stephen R. C. Hicks Ockham's Razor Publishing Contents Thesis: The failure of epistemology made postmodernism possible, and the failure of socialism made postmodernism necessary. List of Tables and Charts v Chapter One: What Postmodernism Is The postmodern vanguard 1 Foucault, Lyotard, Derrida, Rorty Modem and postmodern 5 Modernism and the Enlightenment 7 Postmodernism versus the Enlightenment 14 Postmodern academic themes 15 Postmodern cultural themes 18 Why postmodernism? 20 Chapter Two: The Counter-Enlightenment Attack on Reason Enlightenment reason, liberalism, and science 23 The beginnings of the Counter-Enlightenment 24 Kant's skeptical conclusion 27 Kant's problematic from empiricism and-rationalism 29 Kant's essential argument 32 Identifying Kant's key assumptions 36 Why Kant is the turning point 39 After Kant: reality or reason but not both 42 Metaphysical solutions to Kant: from Hegel to Nietzsche 44 Dialectic and saving religion 46 Hegel's contribution to postmodernism 50 Epistemological solutions to Kant: irrationalism from Kierkegaard 51 to Nietzsche Summary of irrationalist themes 56 ii Chapter Three: The Twentieth-Century Collapse of Reason Heidegger's synthesis of the Continental tradition 58 Setting aside reason and logic 61 Emotions as revelatory 62 Heidegger and postmodernism 65 Positivism and Analytic philosophy: from Europe to America 67 From Positivism to Analysis 70 Recasting philosophy's function 72 Perception,
    [Show full text]
  • Kierkegaard and Nietzsche on Resentment Daniel Conway Texas A&M University
    Konturen VII (2015) 132 “The Happiness of ‘Slight Superiority’”: Kierkegaard and Nietzsche on Resentment Daniel Conway Texas A&M University My aim in this essay is to pair Kierkegaard with the German-born philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900). I am particularly concerned to juxtapose their complementary investigations into the etiology and operation of resentment, which both thinkers identified as exerting a powerfully retardant force within the bourgeois societies of late modern European culture. Indeed, both were concerned to demonstrate the extent to which the corrosive power of resentment had transformed the religious injunction to “love thy neighbor” into a culturally sponsored program to “beggar thy neighbor.” The result of this pairing, or so I hope to demonstrate, is a productive division of philosophical labor: From Nietzsche, on the one hand, Kierkegaard’s readers may gain a clear sense of how a community founded on ressentiment may accommodate “healthy” expressions of comparative advantage and relative superiority. Even when exaggerated and amplified, however, these expressions pose no threat to the conservative, contractionary structure of the ethical life of the community in question. In particular, as we shall see, Nietzsche’s account of ressentiment may explain that, and why, the seemingly daring meditation conducted by Johannes de silentio in Fear and Trembling yields such a muddled and unsatisfying conclusion. Daniel Conway received his BA in Philosophy and Economics from Tulane University and his PhD in Philosophy from the University of California, San Diego. He has held faculty appointments at Stanford University, Harvard University, Penn State University, and, since 2006, Texas A&M University, where he is Professor of Philosophy and Humanities and Affiliate Professor of Religious Studies and Film Studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Untitled Remarks from “Köln, 30
    Jewish Philosophical Politics in Germany, 1789–1848 the tauber institute series for the study of european jewry Jehuda Reinharz, General Editor Sylvia Fuks Fried, Associate Editor Eugene R. Sheppard, Associate Editor The Tauber Institute Series is dedicated to publishing compelling and innovative approaches to the study of modern European Jewish history, thought, culture, and society. The series features scholarly works related to the Enlightenment, modern Judaism and the struggle for emancipation, the rise of nationalism and the spread of antisemitism, the Holocaust and its aftermath, as well as the contemporary Jewish experience. The series is published under the auspices of the Tauber Institute for the Study of European Jewry— established by a gift to Brandeis University from Dr. Laszlo N. Tauber—and is supported, in part, by the Tauber Foundation and the Valya and Robert Shapiro Endowment. For the complete list of books that are available in this series, please see www.upne.com Sven-Erik Rose Jewish Philosophical Politics in Germany, 1789–1848 ChaeRan Y. Freeze and Jay M. Harris, editors Everyday Jewish Life in Imperial Russia: Select Documents, 1772–1914 David N. Myers and Alexander Kaye, editors The Faith of Fallen Jews: Yosef Hayim Yerushalmi and the Writing of Jewish History Federica K. Clementi Holocaust Mothers and Daughters: Family, History, and Trauma *Ulrich Sieg Germany’s Prophet: Paul de Lagarde and the Origins of Modern Antisemitism David G. Roskies and Naomi Diamant Holocaust Literature: A History and Guide *Mordechai
    [Show full text]
  • Debord, Ressentiment, Ft Re'7o Lutio11ary Anarchism
    Debord, Ressentiment, ft Re'7olutio11ary Anarchism Notes on Debord, Ressentiment & Revolutionary Anarchism by Aragorn! Why does the Situationist International continue to be such a rich source of inspiration for anarchist thinkers and activity today? They were a decidedly not­ anarchist group whose ostensible leader Guy Debord's ideas resonated much more with Marx, Korsh, and Adorno than Bakunin or Kropotkin. Naturally much of the influence of the SI is based on the theory that the general strike in France in May of 1968 represents the highest form of struggle against the dominant order in this historical period. This theory isn't necessarily supported by other social struggles of the past 30 years1 but does correspond nicely to an anarchist frameworkof what social transformation should look like. Therein lies the tension and rationale forthe continuing interest in the SI and Guy's work in particular. If the SI were represented by one book it would be Debord's Society of the Spectacle. If one portion of that book concerns anarchists and particularly anar­ chist self-knowledge it would be chapter four-The Proletariat as Subject and Representation. Debord damns anarchists' historical failure to theorize or accom­ plish that goal especially in those times when anarchists were best equipped and positioned to do exactly that. These critiques deserve further examination. In this context we will use the newest translation from Ken Knabb. Aphorism 91 The First International's initial successes enabled it to free itself from the confused influences of the dominant ideology that had survived within it. But the defeat and repression that it soon encountered brought to the surface a conflict between two different conceptions of proletarian revo­ lution, each of which contained an authoritarian aspect that amounted to abandoning the conscious self-emancipation of the working class.
    [Show full text]
  • Alex Betley PHIL278 9 May 2016 Beyond Ethical Egoism: A
    Alex Betley PHIL278 9 May 2016 Beyond Ethical Egoism: A Clarification of the Nietzschean Noble Soul While it is true that James Rachels concludes his essay “Ethical Egoism” with the line, “It is this realization, that we are on a par with one another, that is the deepest reason why our morality must include some recognition of the needs of others, and why, then, Ethical Egoism fails as a moral theory,” he also prefaces this statement with a conveniently sly caveat: “Any moral doctrine that assigns greater importance to the interests of one group than to those of another is unacceptably arbitrary unless there is some difference between the members of the ​ groups that justifies treating them differently” (Rachels 199, emphasis added). It is precisely the ​ italicized text where a Nietzschean philosophy departs from Rachels. Nietzsche argues that there are differences between members of two groups or classes that, in fact, do make one class “so ​ special,” to use Rachels’s wording and emphasis (Rachels 199). Contrarily, Rachels sees no ​ fundamental difference between groups of human beings because they all have similar desires. This, he claims, is why we should care about the interests of other people: “their needs and desires are comparable to our own” (Rachels 199). I will argue in this paper that Rachels’ attack on ethical egoism is primarily an attack on an unsophisticated and possessive driven materialist philosophy1. This philosophy, propounded by the likes of Ayn Rand, and hijacked from a more thorough, persuasive, and comprehensible Nietzschean philosophy of the soul, erroneously replaces Nietzsche’s “noble” with a simplistic “self-interest.” 1 What I mean by materialist in this sense is not the same materialism of Marx.
    [Show full text]
  • Re-Thinking Ressentiment on the Limits of Criticism and the Limits of Its Critics
    2016-04-21 16-30-26 --- Projekt: transcript.anzeigen / Dokument: FAX ID 0148427641680892|(S. 1- 2) VOR2128.p 427641680900 From: Jeanne Riou, Mary Gallagher (eds.) Re-thinking Ressentiment On the Limits of Criticism and the Limits of its Critics May 2016, 220 p., 28,99 €, ISBN 978-3-8376-2128-0 The charge of »Ressentiment« can in today’s world – less from traditionally conserva- tive quarters than from the neo-positivist discourses of particular forms of liberalism – be used to undermine the argumentative credibility of political opponents, dissidents and those who call for greater »justice«. The essays in this volume draw on the broad spectrum of cultural discourse on »Ressentiment«, both in historical and contempora- ry contexts. Starting with its conceptual genesis, the essays also show contemporary nuances of »Ressentiment« as well as its influence on literary discourse and philoso- phical discourse in the 20th century. Jeanne Riou lectures in German Studies at University College Dublin. Mary Gallagher lectures in French and Francophone Studies at University College Dublin. For further information: www.transcript-verlag.de/978-3-8376-2128-0 © 2016 transcript Verlag, Bielefeld 2016-04-21 16-30-26 --- Projekt: transcript.anzeigen / Dokument: FAX ID 0148427641680892|(S. 1- 2) VOR2128.p 427641680900 Contents Acknowledgements | vi Introduction: Towards a History of Ressentiment Jeanne Riou | 1 Introduction: The Critical Focus of Re-thinking Ressentiment Mary Gallagher | 24 The Question of Resentment in Western and Confucian Philosophy Eric S. Nelson | 33 Ressentiment as Moral Imperative: Jean Améry’s Nietzschean Revaluation of Victim Morality Victoria Fareld | 53 Ressentiment beyond Nietzsche and Améry: H.
    [Show full text]
  • Redeeming Resentment
    American Dialectic, Vol. 3, No. 2/3, 2013 (118-147) Redeeming Resentment: Nietzsche’s Affirmative Ripostes Grace Hunt here seems to be one standard concern about resentment: T namely, that even in its most mundane forms, resentment amounts to a form of petty backbiting that wants and hates what it can't have. Seen as a debilitating fixation on the past, resentment amplifies one's sense of injury alongside a desire for revenge. It is with these negative associations in mind that I suggest resentment is nonetheless a valuable critical resource for combating oppressive moral and religious norms. Of course, my defense of resentment needs to hold up against Nietzsche's contempt, since his Genealogy of Morals presents to this day the most scathing critique of the backward-looking emotion's legitimacy. I want to challenge this all too human view within philosophy that resentment is always already governed by the same underlying desire that governs ressentiment: namely revenge.1 Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morals attributes the historical and psychological lineage of Christian morality to the development of ressentiment: the chronic internalization of envy, cruelty, hatred, and resentment characteristic of disempowered people. Nietzsche’s infamous genealogy, in other words, articulates Christian morality as developing out of the internalization of a desire for revenge and its attendant emotions and provides a new moral psychology 1 Whereas I understand ressentiment as deriving from the internalization of a variety of affects according to a desire for revenge, Ruth Abbey understands ressentiment to be rooted in vanity ["The Roots of Ressentiment," New Nietzsche Studies 3, no.
    [Show full text]