Replies to My Commentators

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Replies to My Commentators teorema Vol. XXX/1, 2011, pp. 115-144 ISSN: 0210-1602 [BIBLID 0210-1602 (2011) 30:1; pp. 115-144] Replies to My Commentators Hans-Johann Glock I am very grateful to Professor Luis Valdés for instigating and oversee- ing this project. It is a privilege to have a roster of such distinguished schol- ars pay attention to one’s work. Of course I am also grateful to the contributors. Whether by chance or design, between them they have raised what I take to be the most important and controversial ideas in the book, and without redundancy. Reading their comments was an enjoyable experience, if also an educational and sobering one. Almost all of the criticisms have been friendly and constructive, and I hope to be able to respond accordingly. Le- gitimate worries about the possibility of philosophical progress notwithstand- ing, it is at least tempting to feel confident that when it comes to the meta- philosophical and historical understanding of analytic philosophy, some pro- gress can be made. I have divided my responses according to topic rather than commentator, while also indicating in the headings whose contributions will be discussed. I. DEFINING ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY (DUMMETT, MARCONI, MONK) My stated ambition was to answer the question ‘What is Analytic Phi- losophy?’ I was therefore disappointed to read that Michael Dummett could not find ‘any such answer’ in the book. Fortunately my spirits were lifted when I remembered that my answer is explicitly and prominently stated at least three times in the text. It also features on the back cover, which Dummett must have read, since he refers to the generous blurb by David Stern: ‘analytic philosophy is a lose movement held together both by ties of influence and by various “fam- ily resemblances”’. My reasons for combining a family-resemblance and a ge- netic/historical account are developed at length in chapter 8 and summarized in the Introduction [pp. 19-20; see also pp. 223-4]1. On the one hand, merely rely- ing on family-resemblances would overshoot the acknowledged extension of the term, since overlapping strands relate analytic philosophers to some non- analytic philosophers no less than to each other. On the other hand, merely re- 115 116 Hans-Johann Glock lying on historical ties of influence leaves the problem that such ties extend be- yond the analytic tradition as commonly recognized, both backwards and for- wards, and there have even been notable cases of mutual influence. Curiously enough, Dummett himself quotes one of the plain formula- tions of the answer he purports not to have found [from p. 231]. His real gripe is that the book will not put a reader in a position to ‘recognise’ a piece of writing as belonging to analytic philosophy, ‘unless he were already famil- iar with some of the specimens of it that Glock refers to’. According to Dummett, a ‘skilful verbal characterisation of baroque art or architecture, without illustrations, should put the reader in a favourable position to make a good guess at whether a painting or building which he is shown does or does not exemplify that style. Similarly, a verbal characterisation of analytic phi- losophy should put the reader in a favourable position to make a good guess at whether or not something that he reads is a product of that philosophical school’. But this demand ignores one part of my account, according to which being a text of analytic philosophy depends partly on belonging to a histori- cal tradition. Such membership may not be evident from a philosophical text. And to the extent that it is, for instance through references to particular works, thinkers, schools or labelled problems or theories, my book will put attentive readers in a favourable position to tell. For it discusses at length how various figures and schools fit into that tradition according to various historical and philosophical parameters. Of course no characterisation, how- ever skilful, could put a reader in a position to know for certain whether an anonymous text bereft of historical references belongs to a certain genetic category. Incidentally, this holds just as much for the architectural categories Dummett invokes. In so far as they are genetic (as when we distinguish be- tween gothic and neo-gothic buildings), a mere description of a specimen will not put one in a position to assign it to one of them, and even visual acquaint- ance need not be sufficient to settle the matter. Dummett does take note of the second part of my account, yet com- plains that ‘[Glock] says very little of what the [family] resemblances are be- tween different examples of analytic philosophy and an archetypal instance of it’. This statement betokens a misunderstanding of the notion of family re- semblance, both as Wittgenstein develops it by reference to ‘game’ and as I clarify and apply it to ‘analytic philosophy’. The idea is not that there are re- semblances radiating out from a central archetypal instance, but that there are overlapping features running through some but not all of the instances. In any event, the complaint that I have said very little about the features shared by many though not all analytic philosophers is quite wrong. On page 218 there is a prominent diagram showing the degree to which archetypal specimens of analytic philosophy form a family on account of sharing certain pertinent fea- tures. While there may be a need to add further features, all of the ones listed are discussed at great length in the preceding parts of the book. And so are Replies to My Commentators 117 additional thinkers or schools that help to determine the contours of analytic philosophy, including not just paradigmatic specimens but also borderline cases [e.g. pp. 15-6, pp. 214-9, pp. 224-30]. Extending the open-ended category ‘analytic philosophy’ to novel texts would indeed be greatly facilitated by familiarity with specimens of analytic writing. But why shouldn’t it be? The same holds true for taxonomic classifi- cations in art and architecture. Furthermore, even my descriptions of the overlapping features shared by many though not all analytic authors will help to assign a text by Frege, Moore, Carnap, Ryle, Austin, Quine or Lewis to analytic philosophy. Unlike Dummett, both Diego Marconi and Ray Monk recognize not just my answer to the title question, but also the reasons that lie behind it. They are even minded to accept it as correct. At the same time, there are also points on which they agree with Dummett. My answer is not as helpful (Marconi) or substantial (Monk) as I seem to believe. Marconi regards my answer as ‘extensionally accurate’, yet fears that it is insufficiently ‘vivid’ or ‘physiognomic’ [this issue, pp. 23-24]. He pro- poses an ‘extensionally equivalent’ but ‘perhaps more vivid’ alternative. It amounts to an interesting variant of what I called the rationalist conception. I shall attend to that proposal below. At this juncture I should merely like to grant that this characterization would be easier to apply than mine, since it omits historical factors and focuses on a narrower range of descriptive fea- tures. I hope, however, that my account is not quite as cumbersome and arti- ficial as Marconi would have it. He doubts the wisdom of explaining to a layperson what an analytic philosopher is by telling her that it is someone who was influenced by at least one of its emblematic figures and satisfies a sufficient subset of features from my list of family-resemblances. But even if this casts me in a dreadful light, I confess that I would have no compunction about answering the question somewhat as follows: analytic philosophy is the most influential philosophical tradition of contempo- rary Western philosophy. It predominates in Anglophone countries, and is the single most important movement in continental Europe… Analytic philosophy emerged around the turn of the nineteenth century in the work of Frege, Moore, and Russell, work that mainly concerned the formal and philosophical aspects of logic, semantics and metaphysics. It then took a linguistic turn through the early Wittgenstein and the logical positivists. Two distinctive branches emerged in the 1930s, logical constructionism on the one hand, conceptual analysis on the other…. Analytic philosophy is a highly diverse movement. Nevertheless there are some overlapping doctrinal, methodological and stylistic features that are shared by many – though not all – analytic philosophers from its inception to the present day. These include… 118 Hans-Johann Glock Properly done, this would indeed ‘require some time and quite a few exam- ples’, as Marconi notes. I think it would be time well spent. According to Monk, I have not really provided even a non-analytic definition of the kind that I promise. He is kind enough, however, to regard this is ‘a strength rather than a weakness’. Monk shares Wittgenstein’s dislike for ‘What is X?’ questions, let alone the attempt to answer them through a definition. My account, despite my ‘stated aims in producing it, does justice to that fluidity [of our notion of analytic philosophy]’. Yet it does so only be- cause in effect it amounts to a Wittgensteinian answer. ‘First one enumerates a list of things that are correctly called “analytic philosophy” (Glock’s ge- netic conception), then one adds “and similar things” (his family resemblance conception)’ [this issue, p. 39]. In some ways, my account plainly goes be- yond this. It states a rationale for why some things count as generally ac- cepted specimen of analytic philosophy – namely membership in a historical tradition. I also indicate pertinent respects in which things can be similar; and I state reasons for thinking that these amount not to necessary and sufficient conditions, but only to family resemblances.
Recommended publications
  • Patterns in Spiritual Awakening: a Study of Augustine, Coleridge and Eliot
    American University in Cairo AUC Knowledge Fountain Theses and Dissertations 6-1-2017 Patterns in spiritual awakening: A study of Augustine, Coleridge and Eliot Lucy Shafik Follow this and additional works at: https://fount.aucegypt.edu/etds Recommended Citation APA Citation Shafik, L. (2017).Patterns in spiritual awakening: A study of Augustine, Coleridge and Eliot [Master’s thesis, the American University in Cairo]. AUC Knowledge Fountain. https://fount.aucegypt.edu/etds/1366 MLA Citation Shafik, ucyL . Patterns in spiritual awakening: A study of Augustine, Coleridge and Eliot. 2017. American University in Cairo, Master's thesis. AUC Knowledge Fountain. https://fount.aucegypt.edu/etds/1366 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by AUC Knowledge Fountain. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of AUC Knowledge Fountain. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The American University in Cairo School of Humanities and Social Sciences Patterns in Spiritual Awakening: A Study of Augustine, Coleridge and Eliot A Thesis Submitted to The Department of English and Comparative Literature In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts Lucy Shafik Under the supervision of Dr. William Melaney May 2017 The American University in Cairo Patterns in Spiritual Awakening: A Study of Augustine, Coleridge and Eliot A Thesis Submitted by Lucy Shafik To the Department of English and Comparative Literature May 2017 In partial fulfillment of the requirements for The degree of Master of Arts Has been approved by Dr. William Melaney Thesis Committee Advisor____________________________________________ Affiliation_________________________________________________________ Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Reconsidering the Theoretical/Practical Divide: the Philosophy of Nishida Kitarō
    University of Mississippi eGrove Electronic Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 2013 Reconsidering The Theoretical/Practical Divide: The Philosophy Of Nishida Kitarō Lockland Vance Tyler University of Mississippi Follow this and additional works at: https://egrove.olemiss.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Tyler, Lockland Vance, "Reconsidering The Theoretical/Practical Divide: The Philosophy Of Nishida Kitarō" (2013). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. 752. https://egrove.olemiss.edu/etd/752 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at eGrove. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of eGrove. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RECONSIDERING THE THEORETICAL/PRACTICAL DIVIDE: THE PHILOSOPHY OF NISHIDA KITARŌ A Thesis presented in partial fulfillment of requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the Department of Philosophy University of Mississippi by LOCKLAND V. TYLER APRIL 2013 Copyright Lockland V. Tyler 2013 ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ABSTRACT Over the years professional philosophy has undergone a number of significant changes. One of these changes corresponds to an increased emphasis on objectivity among philosophers. In light of new discoveries in logic and science, contemporary analytic philosophy seeks to establish the most objective methods and answers possible to advance philosophical progress in an unambiguous way. By doing so, we are able to more precisely analyze concepts, but the increased emphasis on precision has also been accompanied by some negative consequences. These consequences, unfortunately, are much larger and problematic than many may even realize. What we have eventually arrived in at in contemporary Anglo-American analytic philosophy is a complete repression of humanistic concerns.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Risks of Approaching a Philosophical Movement Outside of Philosophy
    doi: 10.12957/childphilo.2017.29954 on the risks of approaching a philosophical movement outside of philosophy walter omar kohan1 state university of rio de janeiro, brasil david knowles kennedy2 montclair state university, united states of america abstract Biesta states at the beginning of his intervention that he will speak “as an educationalist,” outside not only of “philosophical work with children” but “outside of philosophy.” What are the implications of these assumptions in terms of “what is philosophy?” and “what is education?” Can we really speak about “philosophical work with children” outside philosophy? What are the consequences of taking this position? From this initial questioning, in this response some other questions are offered to Biesta’s presentation: is philosophical work with children about asking better questions or asking questions better, as he states in his presentation? Finally, risks of philosophy for children as presented by Biesta are examined: a) of being reduced to critical thinking, i.e., “to keeping a clear head”; b) that, even extended to creative and caring thinking, it could “stay in the head” and “not touch the soul”; c) that through the building of communities of inquiry in the classroom, we establish a kind of artificial setting where “we end up living in an idea about the world rather than the world”. Our response ends with a last reference to Biesta’s approach to education in terms of “growing” and existence in terms of a “grown-up way” of being in the world. keywords: philosophy with children; critical thinking; risks; dogmatic image of thinking sobre os riscos de se abordar um movimento filosófico fora da filosofia resumo Biesta declara no começo de sua intervenção que ele falará “como um experto educacional” de fora não somente do “trabalho filosófico com crianças” mas também “de fora da filosofia”.
    [Show full text]
  • Albert Camus' Dialogue with Nietzsche and Dostoevsky Sean Derek Illing Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected]
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 2014 Between nihilism and transcendence : Albert Camus' dialogue with Nietzsche and Dostoevsky Sean Derek Illing Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Illing, Sean Derek, "Between nihilism and transcendence : Albert Camus' dialogue with Nietzsche and Dostoevsky" (2014). LSU Doctoral Dissertations. 1393. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations/1393 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please [email protected]. BETWEEN NIHILISM AND TRANSCENDENCE: ALBERT CAMUS’ DIALOGUE WITH NIETZSCHE AND DOSTOEVSKY A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Political Science by Sean D. Illing B.A., Louisiana State University, 2007 M.A., University of West Florida, 2009 May 2014 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This dissertation is the product of many supportive individuals. I am especially grateful for Dr. Cecil Eubank’s guidance. As a teacher, one can do no better than Professor Eubanks. Although his Socratic glare can be terrifying, there is always love and wisdom in his instruction. It is no exaggeration to say that this work would not exist without his support. At every step, he helped me along as I struggled to articulate my thoughts.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 7-1-2018 Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology (07/18). DOI. © 2018 Oxford University Press. Used with permission. Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Sebastian Luft The Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology Edited by Dan Zahavi Print Publication Date: Jun 2018 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind, History of Western Philosophy (Post-Classical) Online Publication Date: Jul 2018 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198755340.013.5 Abstract and Keywords This chapter offers a reassessment of the relationship between Kant, the Kantian tradi­ tion, and phenomenology, here focusing mainly on Husserl and Heidegger. Part of this re­ assessment concerns those philosophers who, during the lives of Husserl and Heidegger, sought to defend an updated version of Kant’s philosophy, the neo-Kantians. The chapter shows where the phenomenologists were able to benefit from some of the insights on the part of Kant and the neo-Kantians, but also clearly points to the differences. The aim of this chapter is to offer a fair evaluation of the relation of the main phenomenologists to Kant and to what was at the time the most powerful philosophical movement in Europe. Keywords: Immanuel Kant, neo-Kantianism, Edmund Husserl, Martin Heidegger, Marburg School of neo-Kantian­ ism 3.1 Introduction THE relation between phenomenology, Kant, and Kantian philosophizing broadly con­ strued (historically and systematically), has been a mainstay in phenomenological re­ search.1 This mutual testing of both philosophies is hardly surprising given phenomenology’s promise to provide a wholly novel type of philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Enrique Dussel's Ethics of Liberation
    Enrique Dussel’s Ethics of Liberation “Felicito y agradezco el tiempo de su vida que Frederick Mills se ha tomado en introducir una flosofía elaborada en el desconocido Sur global, como práctica de un diálogo Norte-Sur, que vaya descolonizando la flosofía eurocéntrica y la abra al horizonte mundial que está lentamente surgiendo en nuestro planeta glo- balizado, que enfrenta el riesgo de un eminente suicidio colectivo ecológico de la modernidad.” —Enrique Dussel, Ciudad de México “Frederick Mills’s Enrique Dussel’s Ethics of Liberation: An Introduction is a very clearly written, comprehensive presentation of the ethics of liberation philos- opher Enrique Dussel. Mills provides a biography of Dussel and expounds his work, dealing with its Levinasian origins, the analectical methodology, the basic liberation principles of his monumental Ética de la Liberación, the implications of Dussel’s corpus for politics and economics, and its potential for the development of a planetary humanism. Mills is thoroughly acquainted with the massive litera- ture on liberation philosophy, and he never loses sight of the victims of Western instrumental rationality on behalf of whom this work, as well as Dussel’s philoso- phy of liberation, is written.” —Michael Barber, author of Ethical Hermeneutics: Rationality in Enrique Dussel’s Philosophy of Liberation (1998) “Dr. Frederick Mills’s new work, Enrique Dussel’s Ethics of Liberation, is a phil- osophically masterful exploration of, and lucidly insightful commentary on the work of a Latin American thinker who is possibly the most distinguished living philosopher of liberation. Focusing radical humanist and liberatory ethics, MIlls’s book shows not only penetrating insight.
    [Show full text]
  • A New Philosophical Movement from the Twentieth Century and One of Its Founders
    University of Texas at El Paso ScholarWorks@UTEP Departmental Papers (Philosophy) Philosophy 9-2020 A New Philosophical Movement from the Twentieth Century and one of its Founders Reyes Espinoza Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.utep.edu/phil_papers Part of the Philosophy Commons Comments: This is a pre-print of an article published in The Journal of Value Inquiry. The final authenticated version is available online at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-020-09767-w Title: “A New Philosophical Movement from the Twentieth Century and one of its Founders,” Book review of A Philosophy of Struggle: The Leonard Harris Reader (2020), London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2020 This is a pre-print of an article published in The Journal of Value Inquiry. The final authenticated version is available online at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-020-09767-w (The DOI may be inactive until publication) Journal: The Journal of Value Inquiry DOI (may be inactive until publication): 10.1007/s10790-020-09767-w Title: “A New Philosophical Movement from the Twentieth Century and one of its Founders,” Book review of A Philosophy of Struggle: The Leonard Harris Reader (2020), London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2020, ISBN: 978-1-3500- 841-6, $21.99, ePDF Written by Dr. Reyes Espinoza (Lecturer 2020-2021 at The University of Texas at El Paso (UTEP). Doctoral degree from Purdue University, Department of Philosophy. Bachelor of Arts from UTEP in Theatre performance and Philosophy) (Forthcoming) Pre-Print A Philosophy of Struggle: The Leonard Harris Reader is a book of axiology, ethics, and metaphilosophy. I recommend this book to any group of English-speaking graduate students and professors in philosophy departments, anywhere on the planet.
    [Show full text]
  • "Immanuel Kant", and "Kantian Ethics"
    Butler University Digital Commons @ Butler University Scholarship and Professional Work - LAS College of Liberal Arts & Sciences 2004 "Immigration," "Immanuel Kant", and "Kantian Ethics" Harry van der Linden Butler University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.butler.edu/facsch_papers Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation van der Linden, Harry, ""Immigration," "Immanuel Kant", and "Kantian Ethics"" Ethics, revised Edition / (2004): -. Available at https://digitalcommons.butler.edu/facsch_papers/62 This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts & Sciences at Digital Commons @ Butler University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Scholarship and Professional Work - LAS by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Butler University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Permission to post this publication in our archive was granted by the copyright holder, Salem Press. This copy should be used for educational and research purposes only. The original publications appeared at: "Immigration," published in Ethics, Revised Edition, pages 715-17, reprinted (or reproduced) by permission of the publisher Salem Press. Copyright, ©, 2004 by Salem Press. "Immanuel Kant," published in Ethics, Revised Edition, pages 804-06, reprinted (or reproduced) by permission of the publisher Salem Press. Copyright, ©, 2004 by Salem Press. "Kantian Ethics," published in Ethics, Revised Edition, pages 806-08, reprinted (or reproduced) by permission of the publisher Salem Press. Copyright, ©, 2004 by Salem Press. Ethics IMMIGRATION these concepts, health care will be called upon to mit­ communal self-determination, but critics argue igate every problem society has, not only the enor­ that they often violate the individual right to free­ mous number it is traditionally expected to solve.
    [Show full text]
  • Science Beyond Enchantment Revisiting the Paradigm of Re-Enchantment As an Explanatory Framework for New Age Science
    INSTITUTIONEN FÖR LITTERATUR, IDÉHISTORIA OCH RELIGION Science Beyond Enchantment Revisiting the Paradigm of Re-enchantment as an Explanatory Framework for New Age Science Kristel Torgrimsson Termin VT-17 Kurs: RKT 250, 30 hp Nivå: Master Handledare: Jessica Moberg Abstract A common understanding of scientists within the New Age movement is that they are manifesting a form of re-enchantment and that their ideas should be addressed as natural theologies. This understanding often takes as its reference point, the re-entanglement of science and religion whose original separation, in this case, is often the working definition of disenchantment. This essay argues that many contemporary scientists who are both popular references and active participants on New Age conferences cannot fully be accounted for by this paradigm. Among these scientists and more particularly those interested in quantum physics, there are many who wish to extend the quantum phenomena not only to support questions of religious character, but to develop theories on physical reality and human nature. Their ambitions are not solely about merging science and religion but also about suggesting new scientific solutions and discussing scientific dilemmas. The purpose of this essay has therefore been to find a viable alternative to the re-enchantment paradigm that offers a more detailed description of their ideas. By opting instead for a radically revised re-enchantment paradigm and an anthropological suggestion for studying minor sciences, this essay has found that a more precise definition of popular New Age scientists could be as (1) “problematic” to the epistemological and ontological underpinnings of the disenchantment of the world, where the problem is not necessarily restricted to the separation of religion and science, and (2) as being a minor science, which entails a critique and challenge to state science, albeit not necessarily in terms of imposing religion on the grounds of science.
    [Show full text]
  • 29.Philosophy of Liberation.Pdf
    CONTENTS Preface viii Chapter 1 HISTORY 1.1 Geopolitics and Philosophy 1 1.2 Philosophy of Liberation ofthe Periphery 9 Chapter 2 FROM PHENOMENOLOGY TO LIBERATION 2.1 Proximity 16 2.2 Tota1ity 21 2.3 Mediation 29 2.4 Exteriority 39 2.5 Alienation 49 2.6 Liberation 58 Chapter 3 FROM POLITICS TO ANTIFETISHISM 3.1 Politics 67 3.2 Erotics 78 3.3 Pedagogics 87 3.4 Antifetishism 95 Chapter 4 FROM NATURE TO ECONOMICS 4.1 Nature 106 4.2 Semiotics 117 4.3 Poietics 126 4.4 Economics 140 vi Chapter 5 FROM SCIENCE TO PHILOSOPHY OF LIBERATION 5.1 Science 153 5.2 Dialectic 156 5.3 The Analectical Moment 158 5.4 Practice 160 5.5 Poietics 163 5.6 Human Sciences 165 5.7 Ideological Methods 167 5.8 Critical Methods 169 5.9 Philosophy of Liberation 170 Appendix PHILOSOPHY AND PRAXIS A. Philosophy and Ideology 181 B. Dialectic between Philosophy and Praxis 183 C. Exigencies for a Philosophy of Liberation 188 D. Toward an International Division of Philosophical Labor 195 Notes 197 Glossary of Concepts 201 Glossary of Non-English Terms 213 vii PREFACE What follows is addressed to neophytes in philosophy of libera- tion. It does not claim to be an exhaustive exposition. It is a discourse that proceeds by elaborating one thesis after another, using its own categories and its own method. It is a provisional theoretical philosophical framework. Except in the Appendix, this work has few footnotes and no bibliography. Writing in the sorrow of exile (in Mexico), I did not have access to my personal library (in Argentina).
    [Show full text]
  • On Reading St. Augustine's Confessions1
    [Expositions 2.1 (2008) 059–082] Expositions (print) ISSN 1747-5368 doi:10.1558/expo.v2i1.059 Expositions (online) ISSN 1747-5376 On Reading St. Augustine’s Confessions1 TODD BREYFOGLE The Aspen Institute This essay is intended as a guide for beginning readers of Augustine, for teachers charged with helping these readers understand Augustine, and for those interested in a problem that confronted Augustine first as a reader and eventually as an author: how does a book help us understand ourselves even as we understand its author? A famously dysfunctional reader, Don Quix- ote de la Mancha, opens the essay as an example of a soul imprisoned by books because it is subject to slavish imitation. With this caution firmly in view, I offer a series of tips on how readers of theConfessions can approach the work with appropriate freshness, developing strategies for reading not only Augustine but other great authors as well. I stress especially the dialogi- cal character of Confessions and, with it, Augustine’s qualified continuity with the Platonic-Socratic tradition of text-as-conversation. In so doing, I emphasize Augustine’s emerging pedagogy based on his understanding of the function of signs and the affective character of the poetic imagination. In this way, Augustine translates the Socratic tradition into a distinctively Christian idiom while providing a prospective antidote to Quixote’s mis- placed flights of intellectual and moral fancy, inviting the reader to begin his or her own independent spiritual journey. Introduction Augustine was a North African of the fourth and early fifth centuries but our journey begins in sixteenth century Spain, with the escapades of Cervantes’ fictional adventurer, Don Quixote.
    [Show full text]
  • 2.2 Glock Et Al
    Journal for the History of Book Symposium: Analytical Philosophy Hans-Johann Glock, What is Analytic Philosophy? Volume 2, Number 2 Introduction Hans-Johann Glock..................... 1 Editor in Chief Mark Textor, King’s College London Commentaries Guest Editor Leila Haaparanta......................... 2 Mirja Hartimo, University of Helsinki Christopher Pincock....................6 Editorial Board Panu Raatikainen........................11 Juliet Floyd, Boston University Graham Stevens.......................... 28 Greg Frost-Arnold, Hobart and William Smith Colleges Ryan Hickerson, University of Western Oregon Replies Henry Jackman, York University Hans-Johann Glock..................... 36 Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University Chris Pincock, Ohio State University Richard Zach, University of Calgary Production Editor Ryan Hickerson Editorial Assistant Daniel Harris, CUNY Graduate Center Design Douglas Patterson and Daniel Harris ©2013 The Authors What is Analytic Philosophy? shall not be able to respond to all of the noteworthy criticisms and questions of my commentators. I have divided my responses ac- Hans-Johann Glock cording to commentator rather than topic, while also indicating some connections between their ideas where appropriate. Let me start by thanking the Journal for the History of Analytical Phi- losophy for offering me this opportunity to discuss my book What is Analytical Philosophy? (Cambridge, 2008). I am also very grateful Hans-Johann Glock for the valuable feedback from the contributors. And I thank both University of Zurich the journal and the contributors for their patience in waiting for [email protected] my replies. I was pleased to discover that all of my commentators express a certain sympathy with the central contention of my book, namely that analytic philosophy is an intellectual movement of the twentieth-century (with roots in the nineteenth and offshoots in the twenty-first), held together by family-resemblances on the one hand, ties of historical influence on the other.
    [Show full text]