Concepts and Categorization

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Concepts and Categorization Weiner-Vol-4 c22.tex V3 - 08/10/2012 4:07pm Page 607 CHAPTER 22 Concepts and Categorization ROBERT L. GOLDSTONE, ALAN KERSTEN, AND PAULO F. CARVALHO INTRODUCTION 607 THEORIES 618 WHAT ARE CONCEPTS? 608 CONNECTING CONCEPTS 620 WHAT DO CONCEPTS DO FOR US? 609 THE FUTURE OF CONCEPTS AND HOW ARE CONCEPTS REPRESENTED? 611 CATEGORIZATION 624 CATEGORY BOUNDARIES 616 REFERENCES 625 INTRODUCTION principles that explain many or all acts of categorization. This assumption is controversial (see Medin, Lynch, & Issues related to concepts and categorization are nearly Solomon, 2000), but is perhaps justified by the poten- ubiquitous in psychology because of people’s natural tial pay-off of discovering common principles governing tendency to perceive a thing as something. We have a concepts in their diverse manifestations. powerful impulse to interpret our world. This act of inter- The desirability of a general account of concept learn- pretation, an act of “seeing something as X” rather than ing has led the field to focus its energy on what might be simply seeing it (Wittgenstein, 1953), is fundamentally an called “generic concepts.” Experiments typically involve act of categorization. artificial categories that are hopefully unfamiliar to the The attraction of research on concepts is that an subject. Formal models of concept learning and use are extremely wide variety of cognitive acts can be under- constructed to be able to handle any kind of concept irre- stood as categorizations (Murphy, 2002). Identifying the spective of its content. Although there are exceptions to person sitting across from you at the breakfast table this general trend (Malt, 1994; Ross & Murphy, 1999), involves categorizing something as your spouse. Diag- much of the mainstream empirical and theoretical work nosing the cause of someone’s illness involves a disease on concept learning is concerned not with explaining how categorization. Interpreting a painting as a Picasso, an arti- particular concepts are created but, rather, with how con- fact as Mayan, a geometry as non-Euclidean, a fugue as cepts in general are represented and processed. baroque, a conversationalist as charming, a wine as a Bor- One manifestation of this approach is that the mem- deaux, and a government as socialist are categorizations bers of a concept are often given an abstract symbolic at various levels of abstraction. The typically unspoken representation. For example, Table 22.1 shows a typical assumption of research on concepts is that these cogni- notation used to describe the stimuli seen by a subject tive acts have something in common. That is, there are in a psychological experiment or presented to a formal model of concept learning. Nine objects belong to two We are grateful to Alice Healy, Robert Proctor, Brian Rogosky, categories, and each object is defined by its value along and Irving Weiner for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this four binary dimensions. In this notation, objects from Cat- chapter. This research was funded by National Science Foun- egory A typically have values of 1 on each of the four dation REESE grant DRL-0910218, and Department of Educa- tion IES grant R305A1100060. Correspondence concerning this dimensions, whereas objects from Category B have values chapter should be addressed to [email protected] or Robert of 0. The dimensions are typically unrelated to each other, Goldstone, Psychology Department, Indiana University, Bloom- and assigning values of 0 and 1 to a dimension is arbitrary. ington, Indiana 47405. Further information about the laboratory For example, for a color dimension, red may be assigned a can be found at http://cognitrn.psych.indiana.edu value of 0 and blue a value 1. The exact category structure 607 Weiner-Vol-4 c22.tex V3 - 08/10/2012 4:07pm Page 608 608 Thought Processes TABLE 22.1 A Common Category Structure, Originally Used by categories or vice versa is an important foundational con- Medin and Schaffer (1978) troversy. If one assumes the primacy of external categories Dimension of entities, then one will tend to view concept learning Category Stimulus D1 D2 D3 D4 as the enterprise of inductively creating mental structures Category A A11110that predict these categories. One extreme version of this A21010view is the exemplar model of concept learning (Estes, A310111994; Medin & Schaffer, 1978; Nosofsky, 1984; see also A41101Capaldi & Martins, this volume), in which one’s inter- A50111nal representation for a concept is nothing more than the Category B B11100set of all the externally supplied examples of the concept B20110 to which one has been exposed. If one assumes the pri- B30001 B40000macy of internal mental concepts, then one tends to view external categories as the end product of applying these internal concepts to observed entities. An extreme version of Table 22.1 has been used in at least 30 studies (reviewed of this approach is to argue that the external world does by J. D. Smith & Minda, 2000), instantiated by stim- not inherently consist of rocks, dogs, and tables; these are uli as diverse as geometric forms, yearbook photographs, mental concepts that organize an otherwise unstructured cartoons of faces (Medin & Schaffer, 1978), and line external world (Lakoff, 1987). drawings of rocket ships. These researchers are not partic- ularly interested in the category structure of Table 22.1 and Equivalence Classes are certainly not interested in the categorization of rocket ships per se. Instead, they choose their structures and stim- Another important aspect of concepts is that they are uli so as to be (a) unfamiliar (so that learning is required), equivalence classes. In the classical notion of an equiva- (b) well controlled (dimensions are approximately equally lence class, distinguishable stimuli come to be treated as salient and independent), (c) diagnostic with respect to the same thing once they have been placed in the same theories, and (d) potentially generalizable to natural cate- category (Sidman, 1994). This kind of equivalence is too gories that people learn. Work on generic concepts is very strong when it comes to human concepts because, even valuable if it turns out that there are domain-general prin- when we place two objects into the same category, we ciples underlying human concepts that can be discovered. do not treat them as the same thing for all purposes. Still, there is no a priori reason to assume that all concepts Some researchers have stressed the intrinsic variability of will follow the same principles, or that we can generalize human concepts—variability that makes it unlikely that from generic concepts to naturally occurring concepts. a concept has the same sense or meaning each time it is used (Barsalou, 1987; Thelen & Smith, 1994). Still, the extent to which perceptually dissimilar things can be WHAT ARE CONCEPTS? treated equivalently given the appropriate conceptualiza- tion is impressive. To the biologist armed with a strong Concepts, Categories, and Internal Representations mammal concept, even whales and dogs may be treated as equivalent in many situations related to biochemistry, A good starting place is Edward Smith’s (1989) char- child rearing, and thermoregulation. acterization that a concept is “a mental representation Equivalence classes are relatively impervious to super- of a class or individual and deals with what is being ficial similarities. Once one has formed a concept that represented and how that information is typically used treats all skunks as equivalent for some purposes, irrel- during the categorization” (p. 502). It is common to distin- evant variations among skunks can be greatly deempha- guish between a concept and a category. A concept refers sized. When people are told a story in which scientists to a mentally possessed idea or notion, whereas a cate- discover that an animal that looks exactly like a raccoon gory refers to a set of entities that are grouped together. actually contains the internal organs of a skunk and has The concept dog is whatever psychological state signifies skunk parents and skunk children, they often categorize thoughts of dogs. The category dog consists of all the the animal as a skunk (Keil, 1989; Rips, 1989). People entities in the real world that are appropriately catego- may never be able to transcend superficial appearances rized as dogs. The question of whether concepts determine when categorizing objects (Goldstone, 1994a), nor is it Weiner-Vol-4 c22.tex V3 - 08/10/2012 4:07pm Page 609 Concepts and Categorization 609 clear that they would want to (Jones & Smith, 1993). or is it like fly paper but used to catch bison? Interpreta- Still, one of the most powerful aspects of concepts is tions of word combinations are often created by finding their ability to make superficially different things alike a relation that connects the two concepts. In Murphy’s (Sloman, 1996). If one has the concept “Things to remove (1988) concept-specialization model, one interprets noun- from a burning house,” even children and jewelry become noun combinations by finding a variable that the second similar (Barsalou, 1983). The spoken phonemes /d/ /o/ noun has that can be filled by the first noun. By this /g/, the French word chien, the written word dog, and account, a “Robin Snake” might be interpreted as a snake a picture of a dog can all trigger one’s concept of dog that eats robins once Robin is used to the fill the “eats” (Snodgrass, 1984), and although they may trigger slightly slot in the Snake concept. different representations, much of the core information In addition to promoting creative thought, the com- will be the same. Concepts are particularly useful when binatorial power of concepts is required for cognitive we need to make connections between things that have systematicity (Fodor & Pylyshyn, 1988). The notion of different apparent forms. systematicity is that a system’s ability to entertain com- plex thoughts is intrinsically connected to its ability to WHAT DO CONCEPTS DO FOR US? entertain the components of those thoughts.
Recommended publications
  • Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Library Philosophy and Practice (e-journal) Libraries at University of Nebraska-Lincoln July 2005 Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information Ken R. Herold Hamilton College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/libphilprac Part of the Library and Information Science Commons Herold, Ken R., "Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information" (2005). Library Philosophy and Practice (e-journal). 27. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/libphilprac/27 Library Philosophy and Practice Vol. 3, No. 2 (Spring 2001) (www.uidaho.edu/~mbolin/lppv3n2.htm) ISSN 1522-0222 Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information Ken R. Herold Systems Manager Burke Library Hamilton College Clinton, NY 13323 “My purpose is to tell of bodies which have been transformed into shapes of a different kind.” Ovid, Metamorphoses Part I. Library Philosophy Provocation Information seems to be ubiquitous, diaphanous, a-categorical, discrete, a- dimensional, and knowing. · Ubiquitous. Information is ever-present and pervasive in our technology and beyond in our thinking about the world, appearing to be a generic ‘thing’ arising from all of our contacts with each other and our environment, whether thought of in terms of communication or cognition. For librarians information is a universal concept, at its greatest extent total in content and comprehensive in scope, even though we may not agree that all information is library information. · Diaphanous. Due to its virtuality, the manner in which information has the capacity to make an effect, information is freedom. In many aspects it exhibits a transparent quality, a window-like clarity as between source and patron in an ideal interface or a perfect exchange without bias.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Download
    MARINA BASU Book Review A review of The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experi- ence, by Francisco J. Varela, Evan Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch, 1991. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 308pp. ISBN 0262720213. $30.00 USD. Reviewed by: MARINA BASU Louisiana State University Cognitive scientist Francisco J. Varela, philosopher Evan Thompson, and psychologist Eleanor Rosch in their book The Embodied Mind: Cognitive sci- ence and human experience seek to reconcile traditional understandings of the self as a grounded and unified subject with cognitive science that posits a more fragmented and situated view of the self. The authors base their radical conceptualization within phenomenology and Buddhist philosophy. Though the focus is on cognitive science, the authors’ criticism of the mecha- nistic and representational assumptions in early cognitive science formula- tions as well as their emphasis on emergence are in line with recent ap- proaches taken in complexity theory.1 Several authors have studied the field of cognitive science from differ- ent perspectives. One notable example is Hayles’ (1999) discussion of cy- bernetics and artificial intelligence. Despite the growing complexity-related literature base, The Embodied Mind, although written in 1991, still moves beyond many contemporary theoretical approaches and draws on mind- fulness/awareness meditation to resolve the dissonance between science and personal experience. In a recent study, Auyang (2000) explores similar issues when she addresses the “binding problem” of cognitive scientists through an investigation into everyday experience. While fundamental con- cepts like consciousness or life itself have been the subject of investigation,2 Complicity: An International Journal of Complexity and Education Volume 1, Number 1 • pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Laws Work Pretty Well, but Not Great: Words and Rules in Legal Intrepretation Lawrence Solan
    Brooklyn Law School BrooklynWorks Faculty Scholarship 2001 Why Laws Work Pretty Well, But Not Great: Words and Rules in Legal Intrepretation Lawrence Solan Follow this and additional works at: https://brooklynworks.brooklaw.edu/faculty Part of the Criminal Law Commons, and the Other Law Commons Recommended Citation 26 Law & Soc. Inquiry 243 (2001) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by BrooklynWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of BrooklynWorks. Why Laws Work Pretty Well, but Not Great: Words and Rules in Legal Interpretation Lawrence M. Solan STEVEN PINKER. Words and Rules: The Ingredients of Language. New York: Basic Books, 1999. Pp. xi + 348. I. INTRODUCTION: TWO KINDS OF PROBLEMS IN LEGAL INTERPRETATION Words and Rules is Steven Pinker's third "popular" book about linguis- tics and cognitive psychology.1 It is not about the law. In fact, it barely even mentions the law. Words and Rules is a book about how we form plurals of nouns and past tenses of verbs. According to Pinker, the words for irregular plurals and past tenses, like children and went, are learned from experience and stored in our minds as separate words. We remember them individually and relate them to their singular or present tense forms, child and go. In contrast, regular forms, like books and rained, are rule governed. Although we might remember them individually, we need not do so, because we routinely apply regular rules of pluralization (adding the sound s or z or iz depending on the final sound of the word being pluralized) and of past tense formation (adding the sound t Lawrence M.
    [Show full text]
  • Studying Professional Learning from the Perspective Of
    STUDYING PROFESSIONAL LEARNING FROM THE PERSPECTIVE OF WITTGENSTEIN’S PICTURE OF LANGUAGE AND MEANING JOSEPH SAMUEL GARDNER A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY GRADUATE PROGRAM IN EDUCATION YORK UNIVERSITY TORONTO, ONTARIO March 2019 © Joseph Sam Gardner, 2019 Abstract My own experience working with professionals is that while ongoing professional learning is valued, in most cases there is little that is done well to support such learning. The dominant foci in both practice and the relevant academic fields tend more towards issues connected to linear features of dissemination, to the development of programmatic change approaches, and to scientism. My perception is that these fields are wedded to outdated and problematic foundational metaphors such as ‘trajectories,’ ‘impacts,’ and ‘outcomes,’ to the quantification of learning processes and outcomes, and to the idea of knowledge and research as things that are somehow “transferable.” The aim of this dissertation is, therefore, to find a grounding way to think and talk about professionals’ learning in situ. In turning to Wittgenstein I shift the fundamentals underlying our talk about professional learning towards a picture of language and meaning. I draw a picture of professional learning based on Wittgenstein’s picture of language and meaning, emphasizing Wittgenstein’s notion of a ‘picture,’ versus a ‘theory’ (i.e., a hypothetical, causal explanatory account), of language. Wittgenstein’s picture of language and meaning can be seen as a reaction to the representationalist (cognitivist, intellectualist) approach to language and meaning initiated mainly by Frege. Wittgenstein sketches a picture of language and meaning consisting of the interrelated parts of ‘language-games,’ ‘grammar,’ and ‘rules,’ focused around the ‘use’ of signs.
    [Show full text]
  • Misunderstanding Davidson by Martin Clifford Rule
    MISUNDERSTANDING DAVIDSON BY MARTIN CLIFFORD RULE Submitted to the graduate degree program in Philosophy and the Graduate Faculty of the University of Kansas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. _________________________________ Chairperson Dr. John Bricke, Professor of Philosophy Emeritus. _________________________________ Ben Eggleston, Professor. _________________________________ Eileen Nutting, Assistant Professor. _________________________________ Clifton L. Pye, Associate Professor. _________________________________ John Symons, Professor. Date Defended: 07/12/2016 ii The Dissertation Committee for Martin Clifford Rule Certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: MISUNDERSTANDING DAVIDSON ________________________________ Chairperson Dr. John Bricke, Professor of Philosophy Emeritus. Date approved: 07/12/2016 iii ABSTRACT The main aim of this dissertation is to offer, and to defend, an interpretation of Donald Davidson’s classic paper “Mental Events” which interpretation I take to be identical to Davidson’s intended interpretation. My contention is that many readers misunderstand this paper. My method for showing this will be, first, to give a brief summary of the surface structure, and the core concepts, of “Mental Events”. I will then begin to canvas exemplars of the main lines of (alleged) objection to what “Mental Events” has been supposed to contend. I intend to argue that these objections misunderstand either Davidson’s conclusions, or his arguments, or they require material additional to the position that Davidson actually lays out and argues for in “Mental Events” in order to follow. In the latter case I shall attempt to show that these additions are not contentions which Davidson shares by referencing further materials from Davidson’s work.
    [Show full text]
  • Dual Categorization and the Role of Aristotle's Categories
    Dual Categorization and the Role of Aristotle's Categories Mark Ressler August 6, 2008 Abstract In the Categories, Aristotle addresses two different cases of dual cat- egorization, cases in which the same thing might appear in two different categories: relatives and secondary substances in the first case, qualities and relatives in the second. His treatment of these two cases is markedly different. Ackrill thinks dual categorization poses a dilemma for Aris- totle's project as a whole, but I argue that there is a dilemma only on particular understandings of Aristotle's purpose in compiling the list of categories. I investigate various interpretations of the categories to find one that explains Aristotle's reactions to dual categorization, and sug- gest an interpretation of the peculiar four-fold system of classification in Chapter 2. Can one thing appear in two separate categories? It seems to me that this question cannot be answered without determining the purpose for which the categories are established. If such dual categorization causes no problems ac- cording to the intended purpose of the categorial scheme, then there seems to be no reason for complaint. This is the approach that I take with regard to Aris- totle's categorial scheme in the Categories. In this work, Aristotle addresses two separate instances of dual categorization with regard to his list of ten cate- gories, but his reaction in these cases is surprisingly different, taking great pains to avoid dual categorization in one case, but showing a marked lack of concern in the other case. This indifference in the second case leads John Ackrill to criticize Aristotle's categorial project in general; however, it seems to me that if Aristotle's reaction to dual categorization in one case seems contrary to some conception of Aristotle's purpose in developing the categorial scheme, then per- haps that conception of the purpose of the Categories may not be a conception that Aristotle himself held.
    [Show full text]
  • The Importance of Categorization
    CHAPTER 1 The Importance of Categorization Many readers, I suspect, will take the title of this book as suggesting that women, fire , and dangerous things have something in common-say, that women are fiery and dangerous. Most feminists I've mentioned it to have loved the title for that reason, though some have hated it for the same rea­ son. But the chain of inference-from conjunction to categorization to commonality-is the norm. The inference is based on the common idea of what it means to be in the same category: things are categorized together on the basis of what they have in common. The idea that categories are defined by common properties is not only our everyday folk theory of what a category is , it is also the principaltechnicaltheory-one that has been with us for more than two thousand years . The classical view that categories are based on shared properties is not entirely wrong. We often do categorize things on that basis. But that is only a small part of the story. In recent years it has become clear that categorization is far more complex than thaI. A new theory of categoriza­ tion, called prototype theory, has emerged. It shows that human categori­ zation is based on principles that extend far beyond those envisioned in the classical theory. One of our goals is to survey the complexities of the way people really categorize. For example, the title of this book was in­ spired by the Australian aboriginal language Dyirbal, which haS a cate­ gory, balan, that actually includes women, fire , and dangerous things.
    [Show full text]
  • What Buddhist Meditation Has to Tell Psychology About the Mind1 1
    What Buddhist Meditation has to Tell Psychology About the Mind1 1 Eleanor Rosch Department of Psychology, University of California, Berkeley Some of what we classify as religious experience can be directly relevant to science, par- ticularly to psychology. The discoveries of Buddhist meditation indicate that much of present psychological methods and assumptions are based on one particular limited form of knowing while other levels of knowing reveal a different portrait of the human mind and its capabilities. The knowing revealed by such deeper awareness includes: an nonjudgmental form of knowing that appears to pacify mental disturbances, an expans- ive panoramic knowing that reveals the interdependence of phenomena, an open and free knowing that releases, a timeless direct knowing, and an unconditional knowing not separate from a sense of inherent value. Such forms of knowing are traditionally under- stood to give rise to intelligent compassionate actions. The progressive development of these forms of knowing is illustrated by examples from the autobiography of a noted martial artist. One of the best-kept secrets of the last several centuries may be that some of what we classify as religious experience can make a fundamental contribution to scientific psy- chology. One hundred years ago William James suggested this radical idea in his classic The Varieties of Religious Experience, yet today mainstream psychology is no closer to con- sidering the idea than it was in 1902. Surely one root of this recalcitrance is the way in which the categories and imagery of our society envisage an otherworldly religion and a naturalistic psychology which are on different planes of existence altogether and cannot communicate with one another.
    [Show full text]
  • This Article Appeared in a Journal Published by Elsevier. the Attached
    This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and education use, including for instruction at the authors institution and sharing with colleagues. Other uses, including reproduction and distribution, or selling or licensing copies, or posting to personal, institutional or third party websites are prohibited. In most cases authors are permitted to post their version of the article (e.g. in Word or Tex form) to their personal website or institutional repository. Authors requiring further information regarding Elsevier’s archiving and manuscript policies are encouraged to visit: http://www.elsevier.com/copyright Author's personal copy Behavioural Processes 85 (2010) 246–251 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Behavioural Processes journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/behavproc Functional relationships for determining similarities and differences in comparative cognition Anthony A. Wright ∗ Department of Neurobiology and Anatomy, Medical School, University of Texas Health Center at Houston, P.O. Box 20708, Houston, TX 77225, United States article info abstract Article history: Pigeons, capuchin monkeys and rhesus monkeys were trained in nearly identical same/different tasks Received 6 May 2010 with an expanding 8-item training set and showed qualitatively similar functional relationships: increas- Received in revised form 22 July 2010 ing novel-stimulus transfer (i.e., concept learning) as a function of the training-set size and the level of Accepted 30 July 2010 transfer eventually becoming equivalent to baseline training performance. There were also some quan- titative functional differences: pigeon transfer increases were more gradual and baseline-equivalent Keywords: transfer occurred at a larger set size (256 items) than for monkeys (128 items).
    [Show full text]
  • Concept Learning for Robot Intelligence Justus Piater, University of Innsbruck
    Concept Learning For Robot Intelligence Justus Piater, University of Innsbruck Abstract Current robot learning, and machine learning in general, requires carefully- engineered setups (environments, objective functions, training data, etc.) for learning to succeed. Perception and action spaces are specially crafted to meet the requirements of the learning objective, which is specified in advance. How can we construct robot learning systems that can learn in an open-ended fashion, acquire skills not foreseen by its designers, and scale up to virtually unlimited levels of complexity? I argue that a key to achieving this lies in the robot's ability to learn abstract concepts that can be reused as a basis for future learning, both in autonomous exploration and for teaching by humans. Table of Contents 1. Preface ..................................................................................... 1 2. Skill Learning Using Stacked Classifiers .......................................... 4 3. Skill Learning Using Projective Simulation ...................................... 7 4. Search Space Management ......................................................... 11 5. Conclusions ............................................................................. 13 1. Preface 1.1. Classical Machine Learning [Image1 from New Scientist2] [From my LinkedIn page] [Source3] [Image4 from The Next Web5] 1 https://d1o50x50snmhul.cloudfront.net/wp-content/uploads/2017/05/23120156/ rexfeatures_8828108ac1.jpg 2 https://www.newscientist.com/article/2132086-deepminds-ai-beats-worlds-best-go-player-in- latest-face-off/ 3 http://5.imimg.com/data5/YN/EU/MY-54329049/face-detection-and-recognition-500x500.jpg 4 https://cdn0.tnwcdn.com/wp-content/blogs.dir/1/files/2016/09/SwiftKey-neural-networks- hed-796x398.jpg 5 https://thenextweb.com/apps/2016/09/16/swiftkey-improves-its-android-keyboard-predictions- with-neural-networks/ 1 Preface 1.2. Autonomous Airshow Apprenticeship Learning Via Inverse Reinforcement Learning [Abbeel et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Dharmakirti, Davidson, and Knowing Reality
    Comparative Philosophy Volume 3, No. 1 (2012): 30-57 Open Access / ISSN 2151-6014 www.comparativephilosophy.org DHARMAKĪRTI, DAVIDSON, AND KNOWING REALITY LAJOS L. BRONS ABSTRACT: If we distinguish phenomenal effects from their noumenal causes, the former being our conceptual(ized) experiences, the latter their grounds or causes in reality ‘as it is’ independent of our experience, then two contradictory positions with regards to the relationship between these two can be distinguished: either phenomena are identical with their noumenal causes, or they are not. Davidson is among the most influential modern defenders of the former position, metaphysical non-dualism. Dharmakīrti’s strict distinction between ultimate and conventional reality, on the other hand, may be one of the most rigorously elaborated theories of the opposite position, metaphysical dualism. Despite this fundamental difference, their theories about the connection between phenomena and their noumenal causes are surprisingly similar in important respects. Both Dharmakīrti in his theory of ‘apoha’ and Davidson in his theory of ‘triangulation’ argued that the content of words or concepts depends on a process involving at least two communicating beings and shared noumenal stimuli. The main point of divergence is the nature of classification, but ultimately Dharmakīrti’s and Davidson’s conclusions on the noumenal-phenomenal relationship turn out to be complementary more than contradictory, and an integrative reconstruction suggests a ‘middle path’ between dualism and non-dualism. Keywords: Dharmakīrti, Donald Davidson, apoha, triangulation, reality, meta-ontology, subjectivity, metaphysical dualism 1. INTRODUCTION What can we know about reality? If two communicating beings are both aware of a certain black queen chess piece as evidenced by their reference(s) to that black queen chess piece in their communication, does that imply that there ‘really’ is (something that is) that black queen chess piece? At least there must be something causing the shared awareness.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception and Representation in Leibniz
    PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ by Stephen Montague Puryear B.S., Mechanical Engineering, North Carolina State University, 1994 M.A., Philosophy, Texas A&M University, 2000 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2004 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2006 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY This dissertation was presented by Stephen Montague Puryear It was defended on December 5, 2005 and approved by Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy Robert B. Brandom Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy Stephen Engstrom Associate Professor of Philosophy J. E. McGuire Professor of History and Philosophy of Science Dissertation Director: Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy ii Copyright °c by Stephen Montague Puryear 2006 iii PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ Stephen Montague Puryear, Ph.D. University of Pittsburgh, 2006 Though Leibniz’s views about perception and representation go to the heart of his philosophy, they have received surprisingly little attention over the years and in many ways continue to be poorly understood. I aim to redress these shortcomings. The body of the work begins with an exploration of Leibniz’s proposed analysis of representation (Chapter 2). Here I argue that on this analysis representation consists in a kind of structural correspondence— roughly an isomorphism—between representation and thing represented. Special attention is given to the application of this analysis to the challenging cases of linguistic and mental representation. The next two chapters concern what I take to be the central issue of the work: the nature of distinct perception.
    [Show full text]