The Moral Footprint of Animal Products
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Agric Hum Values DOI 10.1007/s10460-012-9402-x The moral footprint of animal products Krzysztof Saja Accepted: 31 July 2012 Ó The Author(s) 2012. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract Most ethical discussions about diet are focused Keywords Animals Á Animal products Á Animal on the justification of specific kinds of products rather than welfarists Á Animal rights Á Ethics of killing Á an individual assessment of the moral footprint of eating Vegetarianism Á Veganism products of certain animal species. This way of thinking is represented in the typical division of four dietary attitudes. There are vegans, vegetarians, welfarists and ordinary Introduction meat-eaters. However, the common ‘‘all or nothing’’ dis- cussions between meat-eaters, vegans and vegetarians Most ethical discussions about diet are focused on the bypass very important factors in assessing dietary habits. I justification of specific kinds of products rather than on an argue that if we want to discover a properly assessed moral individual moral assessment of eating products of certain footprint of animal products, we should take into consid- animal species, which I refer to as the moral footprint of eration not only life quality of animals during farming or animal products. While many animal protectionists or violation of their rights—as is typically done—but, most of abolitionists argue that at least people from developed all, their body weight, life time in farms and time efficiency countries should abandon meat eating or even the use of in animal products acquisition. Without these factors, an any animal products, their opponents criticize this claim assessment of animal products is much too simplified. If we and defend the common view of animals as producers of assume some easily accepted premises, we can justify a many goods for people. These ways of arguing are repre- thesis that, regardless of the treatment of animals during sented in the typical division into four dietary attitudes. farming and slaughtering, for example, eating chicken can There are vegans who refuse to use any animal products; be 163 times morally worse than eating beef, drinking milk vegetarians who do not accept eating any meat but con- can be 58 times morally better than eating eggs, and eating sume other animal products such as eggs, milk, or honey; some types of fish can be even 501 times worse than eating animal welfarists who do not condemn using animals, but beef. In order to justify such a thesis there is no need to try to minimize unnecessary suffering in farming; and the reform common morality by, for example, criticizing its huge mass of ordinary people who eat without remorse speciesism. The thesis that some animal products are much everything permissible by law. However, these common worse than others can be justified on common moral ‘‘all or nothing’’ discussions between meat-eaters, vegans, grounds. and vegetarians bypass some very important factors in assessing dietary habits. What I argue and what I don’t & K. Saja ( ) There are many philosophical disputes about the strength, Department of Philosophy, University of Szczecin, ul. Krakowska 61/69, 71-017 Szczecin, Poland justification, and content of animal rights. Animal activists e-mail: [email protected] and philosophers give different reasons why animals have 123 K. Saja moral status and should be treated properly. The most common premises we should accept that there are very common and important justifications for abandoning or important moral differences between animal products from carefully selecting animal products lie in condemnation of different animal species due to animal body weight and life unjustified killing of animals, using them merely as a duration in farms. means or causing suffering during farming. For these rea- sons, vegetarians refuse to eat meat and many animal welfarists fight for farming methods that increase respect The philosophical premises of the argument for animal rights or their standard of life. It is widely assumed that the animal well-being is an The first important premise of the argument is the platitude important moral factor. However, I argue that if we want to of common morality and the minimal claim of all animal discover a properly assessed moral footprint of animal activists. Roughly speaking, it says that animals are not products, we need to take into consideration not only the stones and for that reason they have at least some minimal life quality of animals during farming or violation of their rights. I hope that only someone who believes that animals rights—as is typically the case—but also their body weight do not have any moral rights or that their suffering or and life duration in farms. If we consider such commonly killing is morally irrelevant would not accept it. However, I neglected factors and assume some described in the next do not know anybody who defends such a view. Most section premises, we can show that regardless of the people (at least in the USA) admit that there are morally treatment of animals during farming and slaughtering, for better and worse ways of treating animals.1 The common example eating 1 kg of chicken can be preliminarily 163 belief that animals should have at least some minimal times morally worse than eating 1 kg of beef, drinking 1 moral protection can be specified in different ways due to average daily portion of milk can be 58 times morally different reasons for moral status of animals or badness of better than eating 1 average daily portion of eggs, and harming and killing. If someone believes that animals have eating 1 kg of carp can be 501 times worse than 1 kg of at least the right not to be killed without a good reason, she beef. Such conclusions undermine not only the common should accept the first version of the argument and the ‘‘all or nothing’’ discussion about animal products con- following simple premise: sumption, but also have very important practical implica- A1. It is morally wrong to kill sentient animals without tions for a state policy of minimizing animal harm, which I important justification. sketch later in the paper. The thesis that animal products from some animal spe- Different people can give different reasons to support cies are worse than others due to animal body weight and the above claim. Many just think—especially non-philos- life duration in farms will be justified regardless of the ophers—that unjustified killing is bad as a simple, intuitive, reason for enhancing animal rights or the assumed ethics of unanalyzable moral fact that does not need any further killing. In order to broaden my argument, I show that my explanation or justification. This fact is sometimes stated in conclusions follow regardless of which particular ethics of terms of a moral right to life: killing is bad for the same protecting animals is considered. Therefore, I am not going reason that it is bad to violate a right to life without to argue that one is sounder than any other. Instead, I important justification (e.g., self-defense). Some other present the argument in three different versions depending people may claim that the badness of killing lies in the on the three most common answers to the question ‘‘What death that it brings. In this case, killing is wrong because it are the main reasons to stop using animal products?’’ These steals a life and cannot be analyzed or reduced to the loss versions are entirely independent. In fact, I propose three of possible future goods or preferences satisfaction. Such a different arguments of the same structure but treat them as belief is sometimes associated with the thesis about the one and explain jointly. Thus, for example, if we consider sanctity of life. the first version of the argument we should take into account premises A1, B1, C, D1, E1, F1, the second ver- 1 In a 2004 survey conducted by researchers at The Ohio State sion premises A2, B2, C, D2, E2, F2, and the third version University, 92 % of Ohio residents agreed that it is important that premises A3, B3, C, D3, E3, F3. It is important to farm animals are well cared for, and 81 % said the well-being of farm remember that the premises with the same letter (e.g., A1, animals is just as important as the well-being of pets (Rauch and Sharp 2005). Furthermore, 95 % of respondents to a nationwide A2, A3) are not different expressions of one and the same telephone survey conducted by Oklahoma State University agreed claim but rather different claims that play the same role in with the statement: ‘‘It is important to me that animals on farms are the paper. To fully justify all of them individually is well cared for’’ (Lusk et al. 2007). In a 2005 survey of Michigan beyond my scope. Therefore, I will present only a basic residents conducted by researchers at Michigan State University, 92 % of respondents rated ‘‘humane animal treatment’’ as ‘‘very argument for their validity. The main thesis of the paper is important’’ or ‘‘somewhat important’’ as a factor when purchasing only a conceptual claim, mainly that if we assume such animal products (Conner et al. 2008). 123 The moral footprint The second version of the argument is based on a dif- A3. It is morally wrong to cause suffering to animals ferent type of ethics of killing because, even if we agree without important justification. that it is morally wrong to kill sentient animals without Every animal activist defends at least one of the above important justification, we can give other reasons for that assumptions. However, there is no need to be a moral thesis.