Risk, Uncertainty and Catastrophe Scenarios

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Risk, Uncertainty and Catastrophe Scenarios Climate Ethics and Climate Economics: Risk, Uncertainty and Catastrophe Scenarios Conveners Simon Beard (Centre for the Study of Existential Risk) Kai Speikerman (London School of Economics) th th May 8 – 10 2017 Workshop Report 1 Contents Workshop Summary 2 Summaries of Papers Presented 2 Summaries of Public Lectures 6 Should we Care about the Worst-Case Scenario When it Comes to Climate Change? 7 Workshop Summary Kieran Marray (Oxford) examined high-stakes decision making with limited information. Mariam Economic analyses of the effects of global Thalos (Utah) discussed under which warming often focus on the scenarios analysts circumstances precautionary policy is appropriate believe are most likely to materialize. However, in rather than the maximization of expected utility, recent years, both economists and moral and Iñaki San Pedro (University of the Basque philosophers have paid increasing attention to the Country) addressed the problem of motivation in possibility that climate change could prove much dealing with catastrophic risks. Tina Sikka worse than we expect. However, it is not clear (Newcastle) related feminist epistemology to just how likely such possibilities are. Analysts and scientific uncertainty, and Eike Düvel (Graz) decision makers thus confront the problem of examined moral and political problems connected decision not only under risk, but under with stranded carbon assets. uncertainty. How should we respond? Coupled with the workshop were two public One keynote speaker—Hilary Greaves (Oxford lectures by our keynote speakers. Opening the University) addressed the problem of conference, Doyne Farmer argued that compared ‘cluelessness’ about the consequences of our with the study of natural processes like climate actions, and its implications for the effective change, we actually have a poor understanding of altruism movement. The other, Doyne Farmer our collective effects on our own societies, and (Oxford), discussed the prediction of the effects of that greater resources could and should be future forms of technology. John Halstead devoted to understanding it. At its close, Hilary (Oxford) and Matthew Rendall (Nottingham) Greaves examined the connection between presented papers on decision making when we population growth and climate change, and are uncertain which empirical or moral theories argued that while it may well be a problem, the are true, while Elizabeth Baldwin (Oxford) and relationship is not a simple or linear one. Summaries of papers presented terms of this taxonomy, the majority of the Full versions of many of these papers can be existing literature on cluelessness focusses on downloaded from the simple sources. I argue, contra James http://www.nottingham.ac.uk/climateethicsecono Lenman in particular, that these would-be sources mics/papers/workshop-5.aspx of cluelessness are unproblematic, on the grounds that indifference-based reasoning is far Keynote: Hilary Greaves (University of Oxford) – less problematic than Lenman (along with many Cluelessness others) supposes. Decisions, whether moral or prudential, should be However, there does seem to be a genuine guided at least in part by considerations of the phenomenon of cluelessness associated with the consequences that would result from the various ‘complex’ sources; here, indifference-based available actions. For any given action, however, reasoning is inapplicable by anyone’s lights. This the majority of its consequences are ‘complex problem of cluelessness’ is vivid and unpredictable at the time of decision. Many have pressing, in particular, in the context of Effective worried that this leaves us, in some important Altruism. This motivates a more thorough sense, clueless. examination of the precise nature of cluelessness, and the precise source of the In this paper, I distinguish between ‘simple’ and associated phenomenology of discomfort in ‘complex’ possible sources of cluelessness. In forced-choice situations. The latter parts of the 2 paper make some initial explorations in those One of Weitzman’s arguments, which has directions. received very little attention in the literature, appears to run as follows: Keynote: Doyne Farmer (Oxford Martin School) - 1. The Empirical Claim and the Moral Claim How Predictable is Future Technology? entail that strong action on climate change has extremely high, perhaps infinite, Recently it has become clear that many expected utility, whereas rival reasonable technologies follow a generalized version of theories entail its expected utility is Moore’s law, i.e. costs tend to drop exponentially, bounded and much lower. at different rates that depend on the technology. 2. Rational policymakers ought to have non- Here we formulate Moore’s aw as a correlated negligible credence in the Empirical Claim geometric random walk with drift, and apply it to and the Moral Claim. historical data on 53 technologies. We derive a 3. Rational choice is a function of the degree closed form expression approximating the of credence one has in different normative distribution of forecast errors as a function of theories, and the stakes of the choice time. Based on hind-casting experiments we according to the theories in which one has show that this works well, making it possible to credence. collapse he forecast errors for many different 4. Therefore, rational climate change policy technologies at different time horizons onto the should be guided by the Empirical Claim same universal distribution. This is valuable and the Moral Claim, rather than by because it allows us to make forecasts for any reasonable rival theories. given technology with a clear understanding of Call this the Metanormative Climate Change the quality of the forecasts. As a practical Argument (MCC). demonstration we make distributional forecasts at different time horizons for solar photovoltaic The question of how it is rational to act in the face modules, and show how our method can be used of moral uncertainty has only recently received to estimate the probability that a given technology significant attention. My aim is assess the will outperform another technology at a given soundness of the MCC. If it is sound, the MCC point in the future. shows that some of the arguments made by opponents of tail risk-based arguments for strong John Halstead (University of Oxford) - Moral action on climate change face an insurmountable Uncertainty and Climate Change burden of proof. However, it remains very unclear whether the MCC succeeds because many of its Some climate economists, most notably Martin premises are questionable. It is unclear whether Weitzman, have argued for strong action against metanormativism is true, unclear whether MITE is climate change on the basis that unmitigated true, and unclear whether the requisite empirical climate change brings a non-negligible probability assumptions about climate policy hold. of a catastrophic outcome. Those who ignore these catastrophic tail risks and focus instead on Matthew Rendall (University of Nottingham) - the costs of the most likely levels of warming will Betting on Theories: The Nordhaus-Weitzman tend to advocate for more moderate action on Debate climate change. Many of those especially worried about the tail risks of climate change make some Martin Weitzman’s (2009) paper ‘On Modelling variant of the following claims: and Interpreting the Economics of Catastrophic • Empirical Claim: The probability of Climate Change’ prompted a high-profile debate extreme global warming sufficient to with William Nordhaus. Weitzman had estimated destroy, or otherwise undermine the long- a roughly five percent chance of more than ten run potential of, human civilisation is degrees of warming in the next two centuries >~1%. without strong action, and about a one percent • Moral Claim: Destroying, or otherwise chance of more than twenty. Nordhaus argued undermining the long-run potential of, that for such a catastrophe to materialize, the human civilisation would be extremely, climate would have to prove improbably sensitive perhaps infinitely, bad; the costs would to greenhouse gas emissions, the damages from swamp many times over all levels of climate change would have to be improbably warming that would not destroy, or high, and scientists and governments would have undermine the long-run future of, human to remain improbably complacent in the face of civilisation. danger signs. Weitzman’s reply was noteworthy. Suppose, he wrote, that a policymaker found his claims or another economist’s less alarming ones 3 equally credible. The policy maker should accord Kieran Marray (University of Oxford) - Dealing his conclusions greater weight in decision with Uncertainty in Ethical Calculations of making, because the consequences of ignoring Existential Risk his advice would be far more serious if it proved to be right. Weitzman was effectively advocating Taking Bostrom’s definition of existential risk, this Pascalian wagering in response to expert paper will argue that either we are not able to disagreement. make guesses from our temporal perspective as to the certainty of things which we predict, or the This paper explores how to conduct such current approach to assessing the gravity of wagering. Policy analyses often implicitly follow existential risk needs qualification. the ‘maxiprobability method’. The analyst selects the theory she believes most credible, and Firstly, the paper looks at the current approach of recommends the policies optimal if it is right. This using expected-value utility as a guide to ranking
Recommended publications
  • Effective Altruism William Macaskill and Theron Pummer
    1 Effective Altruism William MacAskill and Theron Pummer Climate change is on course to cause millions of deaths and cost the world economy trillions of dollars. Nearly a billion people live in extreme poverty, millions of them dying each year of easily preventable diseases. Just a small fraction of the thousands of nuclear weapons on hair‐trigger alert could easily bring about global catastrophe. New technologies like synthetic biology and artificial intelligence bring unprece­ dented risks. Meanwhile, year after year billions and billions of factory‐farmed ani­ mals live and die in misery. Given the number of severe problems facing the world today, and the resources required to solve them, we may feel at a loss as to where to even begin. The good news is that we can improve things with the right use of money, time, talent, and effort. These resources can bring about a great deal of improvement, or very little, depending on how they are allocated. The effective altruism movement consists of a growing global community of peo­ ple who use reason and evidence to assess how to do as much good as possible, and who take action on this basis. Launched in 2011, the movement now has thousands of members, as well as influence over billions of dollars. The movement has substan­ tially increased awareness of the fact that some altruistic activities are much more cost‐effective than others, in the sense that they do much more good than others per unit of resource expended. According to the nonprofit organization GiveWell, it costs around $3,500 to prevent someone from dying of malaria by distributing bed­ nets.
    [Show full text]
  • GPI's Research Agenda
    A RESEARCH AGENDA FOR THE GLOBAL PRIORITIES INSTITUTE Hilary Greaves, William MacAskill, Rossa O’Keeffe-O’Donovan and Philip Trammell February 2019 (minor changes July 2019) We acknowledge Pablo Stafforini, Aron Vallinder, James Aung, the Global Priorities Institute Advisory Board, and numerous colleagues at the Future of Humanity Institute, the Centre for Effective Altruism, and elsewhere for their invaluable assistance in composing this agenda. 1 Table of Contents Introduction 3 GPI’s vision and mission 3 GPI’s research agenda 4 1. The longtermism paradigm 6 1.1 Articulation and evaluation of longtermism 6 1.2 Sign of the value of the continued existence of humanity 8 1.3 Mitigating catastrophic risk 10 1.4 Other ways of leveraging the size of the future 12 1.5 Intergenerational governance 14 1.6 Economic indices for longtermists 16 1.7 Moral uncertainty for longtermists 18 1.8 Longtermist status of interventions that score highly on short-term metrics 19 2. General issues in global prioritisation 21 2.1 Decision-theoretic issues 21 2.2 Epistemological issues 23 2.3 Discounting 24 2.4 Diversification and hedging 28 2.5 Distributions of cost-effectiveness 30 2.6 Modelling altruism 32 2.7 Altruistic coordination 33 2.8 Individual vs institutional actors 35 Bibliography 38 Appendix A. Research areas for future engagement 46 A.1 Animal welfare 46 A.2 The scope of welfare maximisation 48 Appendix B. Closely related areas of existing academic research 51 B.1 Methodology of cost-benefit analysis and cost-effectiveness analysis 51 B.2 Multidimensional economic indices 51 B.3 Infinite ethics and intergenerational equity 53 B.4 Epistemology of disagreement 53 B.5 Demandingness 54 B.6 Forecasting 54 B.7 Population ethics 55 B.8 Risk aversion and ambiguity aversion 55 B.9 Moral uncertainty 57 1 B.10 Value of information 58 B.11 Harnessing and combining evidence 59 B.12 The psychology of altruistic decision-making 60 Appendix C.
    [Show full text]
  • The Definition of Effective Altruism
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 19/08/19, SPi 1 The Definition of Effective Altruism William MacAskill There are many problems in the world today. Over 750 million people live on less than $1.90 per day (at purchasing power parity).1 Around 6 million children die each year of easily preventable causes such as malaria, diarrhea, or pneumonia.2 Climate change is set to wreak environmental havoc and cost the economy tril- lions of dollars.3 A third of women worldwide have suffered from sexual or other physical violence in their lives.4 More than 3,000 nuclear warheads are in high-alert ready-to-launch status around the globe.5 Bacteria are becoming antibiotic- resistant.6 Partisanship is increasing, and democracy may be in decline.7 Given that the world has so many problems, and that these problems are so severe, surely we have a responsibility to do something about them. But what? There are countless problems that we could be addressing, and many different ways of addressing each of those problems. Moreover, our resources are scarce, so as individuals and even as a globe we can’t solve all these problems at once. So we must make decisions about how to allocate the resources we have. But on what basis should we make such decisions? The effective altruism movement has pioneered one approach. Those in this movement try to figure out, of all the different uses of our resources, which uses will do the most good, impartially considered. This movement is gathering con- siderable steam. There are now thousands of people around the world who have chosen
    [Show full text]
  • Population Axiology
    Population axiology Hilary Greaves This is the pre-peer reviewed version of this article. The final version is forthcoming in Philosophy Compass; please cite the published version. This ar- ticle may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance with Wiley Terms and Conditions for Self-Archiving. Abstract Population axiology is the study of the conditions under which one state of affairs is better than another, when the states of affairs in ques- tion may differ over the numbers and the identities of the persons who ever live. Extant theories include totalism, averagism, variable value theories, critical level theories, and \person-affecting” theories. Each of these the- ories is open to objections that are at least prima facie serious. A series of impossibility theorems shows that this is no coincidence: it can be proved, for various sets of prima facie intuitively compelling desiderata, that no axiology can simultaneously satisfy all the desiderata on the list. One's choice of population axiology appears to be a choice of which intuition one is least unwilling to give up. 1 Population ethics and population axiology: The basic questions In many decision situations, at least in expectation, an agent's decision has no effect on the numbers and identities of persons born. For those situations, fixed-population ethics is adequate. But in many other decision situations, this condition does not hold. Should one have an additional child? How should life-saving resources be prioritised between the young (who might go on to have children) and the old (who are past reproductive age)? How much should one do to prevent climate change from reducing the number of persons the Earth is able to sustain in the future? Should one fund condom distribution in the developing world? In all these cases, one's actions can affect both who is born and how many people are (ever) born.
    [Show full text]
  • Sharing the World with Digital Minds1
    Sharing the World with Digital Minds1 (2020). Draft. Version 1.8 Carl Shulman† & Nick Bostrom† [in Clarke, S. & Savulescu, J. (eds.): Rethinking Moral Status (Oxford University Press, forthcoming)] Abstract The minds of biological creatures occupy a small corner of a much larger space of possible minds that could be created once we master the technology of artificial intelligence. Yet many of our moral intuitions and practices are based on assumptions about human nature that need not hold for digital minds. This points to the need for moral reflection as we approach the era of advanced machine intelligence. Here we focus on one set of issues, which arise from the prospect of digital minds with superhumanly strong claims to resources and influence. These could arise from the vast collective benefits that mass-produced digital minds could derive from relatively small amounts of resources. Alternatively, they could arise from individual digital minds with superhuman moral status or ability to benefit from resources. Such beings could contribute immense value to the world, and failing to respect their interests could produce a moral catastrophe, while a naive way of respecting them could be disastrous for humanity. A sensible approach requires reforms of our moral norms and institutions along with advance planning regarding what kinds of digital minds we bring into existence. 1. Introduction Human biological nature imposes many practical limits on what can be done to promote somebody’s welfare. We can only live so long, feel so much joy, have so many children, and benefit so much from additional support and resources. Meanwhile, we require, in order to flourish, that a complex set of physical, psychological, and social conditions be met.
    [Show full text]
  • A R E S E a R C H Agenda
    Cooperation, Conflict, and Transformative Artificial Intelligence — A RESEARCH AGENDA Jesse Clifton — LONGTERMRISK.ORG March 2020 First draft: December 2019 Contents 1 Introduction 2 1.1 Cooperation failure: models and examples . .3 1.2 Outline of the agenda . .5 2 AI strategy and governance 8 2.1 Polarity and transition scenarios . .8 2.2 Commitment and transparency . .8 2.3 AI misalignment scenarios . 10 2.4 Other directions . 10 2.5 Potential downsides of research on cooperation failures . 11 3 Credibility 12 3.1 Commitment capabilities . 13 3.2 Open-source game theory . 13 4 Peaceful bargaining mechanisms 16 4.1 Rational crisis bargaining . 16 4.2 Surrogate goals . 18 5 Contemporary AI architectures 21 5.1 Learning to solve social dilemmas . 21 5.2 Multi-agent training . 24 5.3 Decision theory . 25 6 Humans in the loop 27 6.1 Behavioral game theory . 27 6.2 AI delegates . 28 7 Foundations of rational agency 30 7.1 Bounded decision theory . 30 7.2 Acausal reasoning . 31 8 Acknowledgements 35 1 1 Introduction Transformative artificial intelligence (TAI) may be a key factor in the long-run trajec- tory of civilization. A growing interdisciplinary community has begun to study how the development of TAI can be made safe and beneficial to sentient life (Bostrom, 2014; Russell et al., 2015; OpenAI, 2018; Ortega and Maini, 2018; Dafoe, 2018). We present a research agenda for advancing a critical component of this effort: preventing catastrophic failures of cooperation among TAI systems. By cooperation failures we refer to a broad class of potentially-catastrophic inefficiencies in interactions among TAI-enabled actors.
    [Show full text]
  • Effective Altruism and Transformative Experience
    Effective Altruism and Transformative Experience Effective Altruism: Philosophical Issues Hilary Greaves and Theron Pummer Print publication date: 2019 Print ISBN-13: 9780198841364 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: October 2019 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198841364.001.0001 Effective Altruism and Transformative Experience Jeff Sebo Laurie Paul DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198841364.003.0004 Abstract and Keywords In this chapter, Jeff Sebo and L.A. Paul investigate the phenomenon of experiences that transform the experiencer, either epistemically, personally, or both. The possibility of such experiences, Sebo and Paul argue, frequently complicates the practice of rational decision-making. First, in transformative cases in which your own experience is a relevant part of the outcome to be evaluated, one cannot make well-evidenced predictions of the value of the outcome at the time of decision. Second, in cases in which one foresees that one’s preferences would change following the decision, there are issues about whether rational decision-making should be based only on one’s ex ante preferences, or should also incorporate some element of deference to foreseen future preferences. While these issues arise quite generally, Paul and Sebo suggest that they are especially pressing in the context of effective altruism. Keywords: transformative experience, cost–benefit analysis, peer disagreement, decision theory, collective agency, authenticity, narrative self 1. Introduction Effective altruists try to use evidence and reason to do the most good possible. However, some choices involve transformative experiences, which change what we care about in ways that we cannot fully anticipate. This limits our ability to make informed, rational, and authentic plans individually as well as collectively.
    [Show full text]
  • Effective Animal Advocacy
    Effective Animal Advocacy Jeff Sebo New York University 1. Introduction Imagine that you are a doctor, volunteering your time to save people in the aftermath of a natural disaster. There are many more people who need help than you have ability to help. How should you approach your work? Many people find it natural to say that you should triage. That is, you should try to do the most good possible with your limited resources. If you have to choose between treating two people, one of whom has a major injury and the other of whom has a minor injury, then you should prioritize the person with the major injury, all else being equal. Similarly, if you have to choose between treating two people, one of whom requires relatively few scarce resources and the other of whom requires relatively many scarce resources, then you should prioritize the person who requires relatively few scarce resources, all else being equal. Granted, it might seem callous to prioritize lives this way. But in a state of emergency, we naturally understand that triage is an expression of compassion, not callousness. If we want to save the most lives possible or relieve the most suffering possible, then we need to think carefully about how best to use our limited resources so that we can achieve this aim. However, as MacAskill (2015), Singer (2015), and many others have noted, many people seem to forget this point when it comes to addressing other, more chronic problems.1 For example, when we make choices about advocacy and philanthropy, many of us do what feels personally meaningful rather than think carefully about how to save the most lives possible or relieve the most suffering possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Whether and Where to Give1 (Forthcoming in Philosophy and Public Affairs)
    1 Whether and Where to Give1 (Forthcoming in Philosophy and Public Affairs) Theron Pummer University of St Andrews 1. The Ethics of Giving and Effective Altruism The ethics of giving has traditionally focused on whether, and how much, to give to charities helping people in extreme poverty.2 In more recent years, the discussion has increasingly focused on where to give, spurred by an appreciation of the substantial differences in cost- effectiveness between charities. According to a commonly cited example, $40,000 can be used either to help 1 blind person by training a seeing-eye dog in the United States or to help 2,000 blind people by providing surgeries reversing the effects of trachoma in Africa.3 Effective altruists recommend that we give large sums to charity, but by far their more central message is that we give effectively, i.e., to whatever charities would do the most good per dollar donated.4 In this paper, I’ll assume that it’s not wrong not to give bigger, but will explore to what extent it may well nonetheless be wrong not to give better. The main claim I’ll argue for here is that in many cases it would be wrong of you to give a sum of money to charities that do less good than others you could have given to instead, even if 1 I am extremely grateful to Derek Parfit, Roger Crisp, Jeff McMahan, and Peter Singer for extremely helpful feedback and encouragement. I am also very grateful to Johann Frick, Ulla Wessels, William MacAskill, Richard Arneson, Brian McElwee, Hilary Greaves, Elizabeth Ashford, Justin Snedegar, Ben Sachs, Sarah Broadie, Andreas Mogensen, Gulzaar Barn, Iason Gabriel, Carissa Véliz, Larry Temkin, Toby Ord, Teru Thomas, Owen Schaefer, Michelle Hutchinson, Caleb Ontiveros, Jesse Tomalty, Tom Ash, Kevin Wong, Caley Anderson, Tim Campbell, Farbod Akhlaghi-Ghaffarokh, Paul Woodruff, Ben Lange, Tina Rulli, Luc Bovens, Thomas Pogge, Francesca Minerva, Alberto Giubilini, Seth Lazar, Christian Barry, Felix Pinkert, Julian Savulescu, and the editors and two anonymous readers at Philosophy and Public Affairs for very helpful comments.
    [Show full text]
  • Effective Altruism and Extreme Poverty
    A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of PhD at the University of Warwick Permanent WRAP URL: http://wrap.warwick.ac.uk/154359 Copyright and reuse: This thesis is made available online and is protected by original copyright. Please scroll down to view the document itself. Please refer to the repository record for this item for information to help you to cite it. Our policy information is available from the repository home page. For more information, please contact the WRAP Team at: [email protected] warwick.ac.uk/lib-publications Effective Altruism and Extreme Poverty by Fırat Akova A thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Warwick September 2020 Table of Contents Acknowledgments vi Declaration viii Abstract ix Introduction 1 What is effective altruism? 1 What are the premises of effective altruism? 4 The aims of this thesis and effective altruism as a field of philosophical study 11 Chapter 1 13 The Badness of Extreme Poverty and Hedonistic Utilitarianism 1.1 Introduction 13 1.2 Suffering caused by extreme poverty 15 1.3 The repugnant conclusions of hedonistic utilitarianism 17 1.3.1 Hedonistic utilitarianism can morally justify extreme poverty if it is without suffering 19 1.3.2 Hedonistic utilitarianism can morally justify the secret killing of the extremely poor 22 1.4 Agency and dignity: morally significant reasons other than suffering 29 1.5 Conclusion 35 ii Chapter 2 37 The Moral Obligation to Alleviate Extreme Poverty 2.1 Introduction
    [Show full text]
  • Foundations of Effective Altruism Frank Arntzenius and Hilary Greaves Hilary Term 2017 Week 1: Introduction
    Foundations of Effective Altruism Frank Arntzenius and Hilary Greaves Hilary Term 2017 Week 1: Introduction Logistics This course has a Weblearn site. Reading lists, together with core readings, will be posted at least a week in advance. Please read the assigned ‘core readings’ before attending each class. Here is a provisional schedule of topics for this term: Week 1: Introduction; Singer’s argument Week 2: Pogge’s argument Week 3: Making a difference Week 4: Career choice Week 5: Identified vs statistical lives Week 6: Conditional obligations Week 7: Existential risk and population ethics Week 8: Cluelessness and indirect effects If there is sufficient interest, we may continue the course into Trinity term. This course focusses on academic moral philosophy topics that are relevant to the EA movement. If you are unfamiliar with the EA movement itself, a good non-academic introduction is Will MacAskill’s Doing Good Better. Background: The effective altruism (EA) movement 1. A (very) brief history of EA a. 1972: Peter Singer published ‘Famine, Affluence and Morality’ b. 2007: Holden Karnofsky and Elie Hassenfeld started GiveWell: evaluating charities for effectiveness with a view to advising philanthropic donors (esp. small donors). Most early recommendations were in the field of poor-country health. c. Meta-research on other possible recipients for charitable giving i. Research on cost-effective philanthropic policy interventions: Open Philanthropy Project (2012), OpenBorders.info (2012) ii. Animal welfare interventions: Sentience Politics (2013), Animal Charity Evaluators (2013) d. Movement growth activities i. Encouraging small donors to give more and to give effectively: Giving What We Can (2009), The Life You Can Save (2013), Charity Science (2013) ii.
    [Show full text]
  • William Macaskill –
    Emmanuel College Cambridge CB2 3AP B [email protected] William MacAskill Í www.williammacaskill.com Areas AOS Ethics AOC Political Philosophy, Decision Theory, Philosophy and Economics Employment Aug Associate Professor & Tutorial Fellow, Lincoln College, University of Oxford. 2015-present Permanent position. Sep 2014-Jul Research Fellow, Emmanuel College, University of Cambridge. 2015 Three-year research position. Education 2010–April D.Phil., University of Oxford. 2014 Title: Normative Uncertainty Supervisors: John Broome, Krister Bykvist 2012–2013 Visiting Student Research Collaborator, Princeton University. Spring 2012 Visiting Scholar, New York University. 2008–2010 B.Phil., University of Oxford, Distinction. Ranked 2nd out of a class of 27. 2005–2008 B.A.(Hons.), University of Cambridge, First Class. Ranked 2nd out of a class of 60. Articles forthcoming Smokers, Psychos, and Decision-Theoretic Uncertainty, Journal of Philosophy. forthcoming Normative Uncertainty as a Voting Problem, Mind. 2013 The Infectiousness of Nihilism, Ethics. 2013 Replaceability, Career Choice, and Making a Difference, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. Books Under Moral Uncertainty, Oxford University Press. Contract First author; co-authored with Toby Ord and Krister Bykvist. Expected publication: Feb 2017. 2014 Doing Good Better, Penguin Random House (USA); Guardian Faber (UK). Work in Progress Why We Should Normalize Moral Theories at their Variance, Under review. Equal co-authorship with Owen Cotton-Barratt and Toby Ord. How to Make Intertheoretic Value Comparisons, Under review. What’s the Value of Moral Philosophy?. Human Extinction, Asymmetry, and Option Value. Moral Caution and Moral Compromise. Effective Altruism. Honors and Awards 2013–2014 Society for Applied Philosophy Doctoral Scholarship, Oxford. Maintenance award. 2012–2013 Fulbright Postgraduate Award, Princeton.
    [Show full text]