Hintikka's Interrogative Model and a Logic of Discovery and Justification

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hintikka's Interrogative Model and a Logic of Discovery and Justification Hintikka’s InterrogativeActa Model Baltica and Historiaea Logic of et Discovery Philosophiae and JustificationScientiarum Vol. 3, No. 1 (Spring 2015) DOI : 10.11590/abhps.2015.1.02 Hintikka’s Interrogative Model and a Logic of Discovery and Justification Arto Mutanen Finnish National Defence University, Department of Education P.O. Box 7 (Kadettikouluntie 8), Helsinki FI-00861, Finland E-mail: [email protected] Abstract: The relationship between discovery and justification is not clear. According to a standard twentieth-century opinion, in the philosophy of science these two are understood as separate problems: how to recognize and conceptualize the object of study and how to find the justification for the conceptualized belief. How to study the logic of discovery? What kind of logic might such a logic be? The basic observation is that discoveries do not take place in a vacuum. They have to be localized into scientific inquiry processes: a discovery is a discovery only in the context of a scientific inquiry process. To do this we use a systematic logico-philosophical model called the interrogative model of inquiry, which was developed by Jaakko Hintikka. The interrogative model of inquiry allows us to consider the scientific inquiry process as a strategic, goal-tracking process which gives justification for the discovery. The model allows us to formulate a systematic logic of scientific discovery and justification. Keywords: discovery, interrogative model of inquiry, justification, strategic questioning Introduction A goal of scientific inquiry is to attain new knowledge. Moreover, in order to be the most humanly reliable way to acquire new knowledge, scientific inquiry has to be a systematic process. The systematicity needed has to be both institutional and theoretical. The institutional systematicity refers to organizations such Acta Baltica Historiae et Philosophiae Scientiarum 27 Vol. 3, No. 1 (Spring 2015) Arto Mutanen as universities, research institutions, and funding institutions. All these are needed; scientific inquiry or scientific discussion is an actual human practice which takes place in the social reality. Theoretical systematicity refers to the organization of knowledge into theories and to methodological orientation. Scientific knowledge cannot be merely an agglomeration of separate pieces of information. To be scientific, knowledge must be expressed in a systematic way. Nevertheless, what is key is not how the expression is formulated, as this can be either in a linguistic or model theoretic way. Ideally, the formulation should be in the form of a theory (in a strict logical sense). The methodology of scientific inquiry refers to the study of the strategies of acquisition of new knowledge. The topic of the methodology is to characterize the general orientation of inquiry. The structure of scientific theories has been studied extensively, especially by logical positivists. The theoretical background of the studies of logical positivists was the huge development of mathematical logic, as demonstrated in the monumental work Principia Mathematica, written by Russell and Whitehead. Mathematical logic was seen as a central tool in analyzing and expressing scientific theories. Mathematical logic made it possible to systematically study the linguistic structure of scientific theories, especially the axiomatization of theories, which was even recognized as the idealized form of a scientific theory by Aristotle. So, the development of mathematical logic meets the long-term desire of philosophers and scientists, or it seems to have been met. That is, “[t]he result was the original version of the Received View: A scientific theory is to be axiomatized in mathematical logic (first- order predicate calculus with equality). The terms of the logical axiomatization are to be divided into three: (1) logical and mathematical terms; (2) theoretical terms; and (3) observation terms which are given a phenomenal or observational interpretation” (Suppe, 1977, p. 12). Purely observational statements were understood as verifiable with certainty through direct observation. The problem was how to verify general statements that are not verifiable by direct observation. “By means of characterizing the latter, logical positivists attempted to develop an inductive logic” (Suppe, 1977, p. 14). The inductive logic in the sense developed by logical positivism, as “inference from known to the unknown” (von Wright, 1965, p. 1), is something which differs from deductive reasoning. In particular, truth preservation characterizes deductive reasoning but not inductive reasoning. Hence, the problem of validity of inductive reasoning or justification of inductive inferences becomes a central problem. This problem of induction is 28 Acta Baltica Historiae et Philosophiae Scientiarum Vol. 3, No. 1 (Spring 2015) Hintikka’s Interrogative Model and a Logic of Discovery and Justification known as Hume’s problem. However, Hume’s problem is not a proper problem in actual scientific research: “Hume’s problem would play no role whatsoever in a serious theory of the scientific method and of the scientific process” (Hintikka, 1992, p. 25). That is, scientists undertaking actual inquiry do not worry about Hume’s problem, instead they mainly worry about the search for new scientific results. So, “[i]t remains to examine the crucial first question. Surely the first order of business of any genuine theory of knowledge—the most important task both theoretically and practically—is how new information is acquired, not merely how previously obtained information can be evaluated.” (Hintikka, 2007, p. 17) Methodology The ‘genuine theory of knowledge’ is closely related to the methodology of science, which studies the rationality of scientific inquiry in the most general sense. Methodological study includes both the general study of scientific inquiry and special case studies of scientific inquiry. Hence, in methodology we can find out that “there is much diversity of procedures and styles within science” (Feyerabend, 1975, p. 257). It seems quite plausible that science includes different kinds of procedures and styles; this happens between fields of sciences but also within a single field of science. Feyerabend has quite a strict procedure in mind when he speaks about methods in science: “The idea of a method that contains firm, unchanging, and absolutely binding principles for conducting the business of science meets considerable difficulty when confronted with the results of historical research.” In fact, there are no methodological rules which are not broken during actual scientific inquiry. Thus, in the philosophy of science the problem referred to by Feyerabend is only a minor problem, as Feyerabend himself also says, because this practice “is not just a fact of the history of science. It is both reasonable and absolutely necessary for the growth of knowledge.” (Feyerabend, 1975, p. 14.) Marcello Pera (1981, p. 141) says that the “expression ‘scientific method’ is a pollakôs legómenon” which “contains at least three different explicanda” which are (i) a procedure, (ii) a set of rules of conduct, and (iii) a conceptual or operational technique. It is extremely important to separate these different meanings of the notion of method. All of them have a role in the scientific inquiry; however, it is important to map all the different meanings of the notion of method onto Acta Baltica Historiae et Philosophiae Scientiarum 29 Vol. 3, No. 1 (Spring 2015) Arto Mutanen the landscape of inquiry. In this sense, Feyerabend’s basic idea seems to be very interesting: what kind of method does he have in his mind? Or, more generally, what kind of method is a method of discovery? In the philosophy of science, the central problem is not finding a single method, but rather characterizing a general methodological orientation of scientific inquiry, as the Peircean approach demonstrates. For example, general philosophical study explicates how the general demand of explicit argumentation and critical public discussion in scientific inquiry implies that the scientific method is also a self- correcting process (Niiniluoto, 1999). The other example, which is connected to the first, is the problem of scientific discovery. In this paper we consider the problem of discovery using Hintikka’s interrogative model of inquiry. The other approach to the problem of discovery is Peircean abductive logic (Paavola, 2006). Peircean abduction is closely connected to the interrogative model (Hintikka, 2006; 2007). According to the classical definition of knowledge, knowledge is a well-justified true belief. So, knowledge should be both true and justified, which are both very strong constraints which need to be further specified. In fact, inquiry starts from ignorance, and results in knowledge via the inquiry process. The inquiry process gives a justification for the knowledge; hence, it is a learning process which factually generates understanding about the object of inquiry (Hintikka, 2007; Hendricks & Hansen, 2014). This is closely connected toMeno’s problem (Kelly, 1996). Etymologically, ‘understanding’ means standing between differences. How can the inquiry process provide understanding? Unfortunately there are no guarantees of success; there is no method which gives a priori guarantees that the intended goal will be achieved. Scientific discovery is a process that involves a great deal of luck, and which occasionally takes place in science. Fortunately, minor discoveries are more conventional;
Recommended publications
  • Words and Objections Essays on the Work of W.V
    springer.com D. Davidson, Jaakko Hintikka (Eds.) Words and Objections Essays on the Work of W.V. Quine Series: Synthese Library It is gratifying to see that philosophers' continued interest in Words and Objections has been so strong as to motivate a paperback edition. This is gratifying because it vindicates the editors' belief in the permanent im• portance of Quine's philosophy and in the value of the papers com• menting on it which were collected in our volume. Apart from a couple of small corrections, only one change has been made. The list of Professor Quine's writings has been brought up to date. The editors cannot claim any credit for this improvement, however. We have not tried to imitate the Library of Living Philosophers volumes and to include Professor Quine's autobiography in this volume, but we are fortunate to publish here his brand-new auto bibliography. 1975 THE EDITORS TABLE OF CONTENTS V PREFACE 1 EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. 1. C. SMAR T / Quine's Philosophy of Science 3 GILBERT HARMAN / An Introduction to 'Translation and Meaning', Chapter Two of Word and Object 14 ERIK STENIUS / Beginning with Ordinary Things 27 NOAM CHOMSKY / Quine's Empirical Assumptions 53 1969, VIII, 373 p. 1AAKKO HINTIKKA / Behavioral Criteria of Radical Translation 69 BARRY STROUD / Conventionalism and the Indeterminacy of Translation 82 P. F. STRA WSON / Singular Terms Printed book and Predication 97 118 H. P. GRICE / Vacuous Names P. T. Hardcover 219,99 € | £199.99 | $279.99 [1]235,39 € (D) | 241,99 € (A) | CHF 259,50 Softcover 154,99 € | £139.99 | $199.99 [1]165,84 € (D) | 170,49 € (A) | CHF 183,00 eBook 128,39 € | £111.50 | $149.00 [2]128,39 € (D) | 128,39 € (A) | CHF 146,00 Available from your library or springer.com/shop MyCopy [3] Printed eBook for just € | $ 24.99 springer.com/mycopy Order online at springer.com / or for the Americas call (toll free) 1-800-SPRINGER / or email us at: [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • Annotated Bibliography of Jaakko Hintikka
    Annotated Bibliography of Jaakko Hintikka 1953 Books (a) Distributive Normal Forms in the Calculus of Predicates, Acta Philosophica Fennica 6, (1953), 71 pp. By distributing quantifiers deeper and deeper into the formulas of a finite first- order language, with or without identity, at the same time as truth-functions are transformed into a propositional normal form, we obtain a simple normal form for such formulas. This refutes the conjecture of Hilbert and Bernays that “a simply characterizable normal form is not obtainable in this way in general.” The basic properties of these distributive normal forms are established, including a set of suf- ficient conditions of inconsistency. Papers (a) “A New Approach to Sentential Logic”, Societas Scientiarum Fennica, Com- mentationes Physico-Mathematicae 17, no. 3, (1953), 13 pp. 1954 Papers (a) “An Application of Logic to Algebra”, Mathematica Scandinavia 2, (1954), 243–246. 1955 Books (a) Two Papers on Symbolic Logic, Acta Philosophica Fennica 8, (1955), 115 pp. (Includes “Form and Content in Quantification Theory”, 11–55, and “Reductions in the Theory of Types”, 57–115.) First paper: For a finite first-order language, the concept of a model set (m.s.) of formulas is defined by means of certain simple closure and compatibility conditions. Intuitively, a m.s. is a partial description of a possible world. A set of formulas is accordingly consistent if it can be embedded in some m.s. A simple proof procedure is obtained by considering rules for an attempt to embed the negation of a sentence © Springer International Publishing AG 2018 557 H. van Ditmarsch and G.
    [Show full text]
  • The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History
    The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History 1960 FIRST COLLOQUIUM Wilfrid Sellars, "On Looking at Something and Seeing it" Ronald Hepburn, "God and Ambiguity" Comments: Dennis O'Brien Kurt Baier, "Itching and Scratching" Comments: David Falk/Bruce Aune Annette Baier, "Motives" Comments: Jerome Schneewind 1961 SECOND COLLOQUIUM W.D. Falk, "Hegel, Hare and the Existential Malady" Richard Cartwright, "Propositions" Comments: Ruth Barcan Marcus D.A.T. Casking, "Avowals" Comments: Martin Lean Zeno Vendler, "Consequences, Effects and Results" Comments: William Dray/Sylvan Bromberger PUBLISHED: Analytical Philosophy, First Series, R.J. Butler (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell's, 1962. 1962 THIRD COLLOQUIUM C.J. Warnock, "Truth" Arthur Prior, "Some Exercises in Epistemic Logic" Newton Garver, "Criteria" Comments: Carl Ginet/Paul Ziff Hector-Neri Castenada, "The Private Language Argument" Comments: Vere Chappell/James Thomson John Searle, "Meaning and Speech Acts" Comments: Paul Benacerraf/Zeno Vendler PUBLISHED: Knowledge and Experience, C.D. Rollins (ed.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1964. 1963 FOURTH COLLOQUIUM Michael Scriven, "Insanity" Frederick Will, "The Preferability of Probable Beliefs" Norman Malcolm, "Criteria" Comments: Peter Geach/George Pitcher Terrence Penelhum, "Pleasure and Falsity" Comments: William Kennick/Arnold Isenberg 1964 FIFTH COLLOQUIUM Stephen Korner, "Some Remarks on Deductivism" J.J.C. Smart, "Nonsense" Joel Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions" Comments: Keith Donnellan/Keith Lehrer Nicholas Rescher, "Evaluative Metaphysics" Comments: Lewis W. Beck/Thomas E. Patton Herbert Hochberg, "Qualities" Comments: Richard Severens/J.M. Shorter PUBLISHED: Metaphysics and Explanation, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966. 1965 SIXTH COLLOQUIUM Patrick Nowell-Smith, "Acts and Locutions" George Nakhnikian, "St. Anselm's Four Ontological Arguments" Hilary Putnam, "Psychological Predicates" Comments: Bruce Aune/U.T.
    [Show full text]
  • Annotated Bibliography of Jaakko Hintikka
    ANNOTATED BIBLIOGRAPHY OF JAAKKO HINTIKKA 1953 Books (a) Distributive Normal Forms in the Calculus of Predicates, Acta Philosophica Fennica 6, (1953), 71pp. By distributing quantifiers deeper and deeper into the formulas of a finite first-order language, with or without identity, at the same time as truth-functions are transformed into a propositional normal form, we obtain a simple normal form for such formulas. This refutes the conjecture of Hilbert and Bernays that “a simply characterizable normal form is not obtainable in this way in general.” The basic properties of these distributive normal forms are established, including a set of sufficient conditions of inconsistency. Papers (a) “A New Approach to Sentential Logic”, Societas Scientiarum Fennica, Commentationes Physico-Mathematicae 17, no. 3, (1953), 13pp. 1954 Papers (a) “An Application of Logic to Algebra”, Mathematica Scandinavia 2, (1954), 243-246. 1955 Books (a) Two Papers on Symbolic Logic, Acta Philosophica Fennica 8, (1955), 115pp. (Includes “Form and Content in Quantification Theory”, 11-55, and “Reductions in the Theory of Types”, 57-115.) First paper: For a finite first-order language, the concept of a model set (m.s.) of formulas is defined by means of certain simple closure and compatibility conditions. Intuitively, a m.s. is a partial description of a possible world. A set of formulas is accordingly consistent if it can be embedded in some m.s.. A simple proof procedure is obtained by considering rules for an attempt to embed the negation of a sentence S in a m.s.. If such an attempt fails in all directions, a proof is obtained for S.
    [Show full text]
  • Review of "Bertrand Russell's Early Philosophy
    New work on Russell's early philosophy by Nicholas Griffin Bertrand Russell's Early Philosophy, Part n. Edited by Jaakko Hintikka. Synthese, vol. 46, no. 2 (Feb. 1981). Pp. 136. US$23.o0. THE SECOND PART ofSynthese's special "early Russell" number contains seven papers: by Pears ("The Function of Acquaintance in Russell's Philosophy"), Hintikka ("On Denoting What?"), Cappio ("Russell's Philosophical Development"), Lycan ("Logical Atomism and Ontologi­ cal Atoms"), Clark ("Acquaintance"), Coffa ("Russell and Kant") and Grandy ("Forms of Belief"), together with a reply to Coffa's paper by Hintikka. The papers in this volume all belong to the field of general philosophy (metaphysics, epistemology), compared with those pub­ lished in Part I, which tend to concentrate on philosophy of logic and mathematics. The concept of acquaintance figures prominently-two of the papers are explicitly on the topic and in four more it is treated inter alia. The only real exception to this wave of interest in acquaintance is Coffa's paper which deals with the nature of Russell's logicism and its alleged refutation of Kant's philosophy of mathematics. The volume is both useful and extremely interesting. Most of the papers are very well done, though some of the interpretations stray far from the texts. In this review I shall concentrate on some issues concerning semantics and acquaintance, and offer some critici3ms of Coffa's account of Russell's early (19°3) logicism. Needless to say, much of interest will have to be left unnoticed. 1. Semantics and ontology The title ofCappio's paper is seriously misleading since the paper deals essentially with the durability in Russell's thought of the semantical theory of The Principles ofMathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Hintikka Vs. Frege on the "Logic of Being"
    1 HINTIKKA VS. FREGE ON THE "LOGIC OF BEING" Ignacio Angelelli 0. INTRODUCTION* Hintikka blames Frege and Russell for having established in the tradition of modern logic the "dogma" of the ambiguity of "is" between existence, predication, identity, and class- inclusion. The affirmation of this multiple ambiguity is called by Hintikka the "Frege-Russell thesis". Hintikka's criticism of the Frege-Russell thesis is (as emphasized by Hintikka himself in Self- Profile 1987a) twofold: theoretical (English does not have and does not need the distinction of meanings of "is") and historiographical (pre-Fregean texts, to be properly understood, do not need the retrospective projection of that distinction). Frege is the real culprit, rather than Russell. Hintikka views his dispute with Frege as pertaining to "the logic of being" (a phrase apparently coined by him; cf 1979, end of section 10: "Game-theoretical semantics is thus much closer to Aristotle's views on the logic of being than is the received view [Frege's]", emphasis mine, but the theoretical and historiographical opposition to Frege concerning the meaning of "is", is only a part of a more general "revolt against Frege" (Hintikka 1981b) undertaken by Hintikka. The aim of this paper is to evaluate the success of Hintikka's "revolt" against Frege in the particular issue of the ambiguity of "is". In section (l) I describe the thesis of the ambiguity of "is" attributed to Frege by Hintikka and Haaparanta. In (2) I examine Hintikka's reasons for rejecting the thesis of the ambiguity of "is". Section (3) is devoted to an analysis of the historiographical campaign as presented in the volume The Logic of Being.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy and Computers
    NEWSLETTER | The American Philosophical Association Philosophy and Computers FALL 2013 VOLUME 13 | NUMBER 1 FROM THE EDITOR Peter Boltuc FROM THE CHAIR Dan Kolak FROM THE INCOMING CHAIR Thomas M. Powers ARTICLES John Barker Truth and Inconsistent Concepts Jaakko Hintikka Function Logic and the Theory of Computability Keith W. Miller and David Larson Measuring a Distance: Humans, Cyborgs, Robots John Basl The Ethics of Creating Artificial Consciousness Christophe Menant Turing Test, Chinese Room Argument, Symbol Grounding Problem: Meanings in Artificial Agents Linda Sebek Assistive Environment: The Why and What Juan M. Durán A Brief Overview of the Philosophical Study of Computer Simulations VOLUME 13 | NUMBER 1 FALL 2013 © 2013 BY THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIatION ISSN 2155-9708 APA NEWSLETTER ON Philosophy and Computers PETER BOLTUC, EDITOR VOLUME 13 | NUMBER 1 | FALL 2013 philosophical issues in the context of AI. We are also glad to FROM THE EDITOR have two outstanding papers created when the authors were still graduate students; both were written for a seminar by Peter Boltuc Gordana Dodig-Crnkovic. Linda Sebek provides a hands-on UNIVERSITy of illinois–springfield evaluation of various features of assistive environments while Juan Durán discusses philosophical studies of computer We are lucky, and for more than one reason. First, we simulation. I would like to encourage other educators in were able to secure an important article, one of the most the broad, and necessarily somewhat nebulous, area of serious defenses of the inconsistency theory of truth. philosophy and computers to also highlight the best work of It is so far the main paper that came out of John Barker’s their students and younger colleagues.
    [Show full text]
  • Reasoning About Knowledge in Philosophy; the Paradigm of Epistemic Logic
    REASONING ABOUT KNOWLEDGE IN PHILOSOPHY; THE PARADIGM OF EPISTEMIC LOGIC Jaakko Hintikka Department of Philosophy Florida State University Tallahassee, FL 32306 ABSTRACT Theories of knowledge representation and reasoning about knowledge in philosophy are considered from the vantage point of epistemic logic. This logic is primarily a logic of knowing that, and its semantics can be considered an explication of the well-known idea that "information means elimination of uncertainty". A number of other theories are discussed as further developments of epistemic logic. They include: (1) theory of questions and answers. (2) interplay of quantifiers and epistemic concepts. (3) representations of other kinds of knowledge than knowing that, especially those expressed by knows + an indirect wh-question and by knows + direct grammatical object: (4) the problem of cross-identification; the coexistence of different cross-identification methods. (5) the problem of logical omniscience. {6) informational independence in epistemic logic and its manifestations, including the de dicto - de re contrast and wh-questions with outside quantifiers. (7) an interrogative model of inquiry and its applications, especially the conceptualization of tacit knowledge and of range of attention. 63 64 SESSION2 Epistemic logic as a vehicle of knowledge representation The main vehicle of speaking a~d reasoning about knowledge in philosophy has recently been epistemic logic° Even though epistemic logic is not the only relevant language-game in town, it offers a useful perspective here, for certain other approaches can be thought of as improvements on epistemic logic. In its axiomatic-deductive forms, epistetnic logic is normally considered a branch of modal logic, and its semantics is usually subsumed under the misleading heading of "possible-worlds semantics".
    [Show full text]
  • Jaakko HINTIKKA and Jack KULAS: (G
    225 Jaakko HINTIKKA and Jack KULAS: (G. 3) The game G(3xS(.{)) begins with a Anaphora and Definite Descriptions. Tho choice by Myself of an individual from do Applications of Game-Theoretical Sem­ (M), i.e. the domain of a model which antics. DordrechtiBostoniLancaster: G(3xS(x) is played on. If "b" is the name D. Reidel 1985 (Synthese Language of this individual either in L or in an Library 26), XIV + 250. extension L(l) of L, then the game in question is continued with respect to S(b), This is an original and ambitious book where S(b) is the result of replacing every that gives a new theory of definite descrip­ free occurence of "x" in S(x) by "b". tions and anaphora phenomena via game­ theoretical semantics. (G. V) The game G(VxS(x) begins like­ The book is divided into three parts. wise as the game G(.FlxS(x), except that the Part I, the shortest of all, presents an individual is chosen by Nature, and is overview of game-theoretical semantics continued likewise. (GTS) as a basis for further considerations on definite descriptions and anaphoric The authors state that any G(S) is finite, pronouns. GTS invented by Hintikka in i.e. it "will come to an end after a finite early 70's and subsequently developed by number of moves" (p. 5). Moreover, they himself and his students is a sort of truth­ sketch a proof that GTS for first-order conditional semantics. Its basic concept is language is equivalent with Tarski-type that of the semantic game.
    [Show full text]
  • THE EMOTIONS in HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY the New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy
    THE EMOTIONS IN HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY The New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy VOLUME46 Managing Editor: SIMO KNUUTIILA, University ofHelsinki Associate Editors: DANffiL ELLIOT GARBER, University ofChicago RICHARD SORABJI, University ofLondon Editorial Consultants: JAN A. AERTSEN, Thomas-lnstitut, Universität zu Köln, Germany ROGER ARIEW, Virginia Polyrechnie Institute E. JENNIFER ASHWORTH, University ofWaterloo MICHAEL AYERS, Wadharn College, Oxford GAIL FINE, Cornell University R. J. HANKINSON, University ofTexas JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University, Finnish Academy PAUL HOFFMAN, University ofCalifornia, Riverside DAVID KONSTAN, Brown University RICHARD H. KRAUT, University ofIllinois, Chicago ALAIN DE LIBERA, Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes, Sorbonne JOHN E. MURDOCH, Harvard University DAVID FATENORTON, McGill University LUCA ÜBERTELLO, Universita degli Studi di Genova ELEONORE STUMP, St. Louis University ALLEN Wooo, Cornell University THE EMOTIONS IN HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY Edited by JUHA SIHVOLA University of Helsinki, Finland and TROELS ENGBERG-PEDERSEN University ofCopenhagen, Denmark SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. A C.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-90-481-5123-3 ISBN 978-94-015-9082-2 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-015-9082-2 Printed on acid-free paper Ali Rights Reserved © 1998 Springer SciencetBusiness Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1998 Softcover reprint of the hardcover I st edition 1998 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner CONTENTS INTRODUCTION vii SIMO KNUUTTll..A and JUHA SlliVOLA I How the Philosophical Analysis of the Emotions was Introduced 1 TAD BRENNAN I The Old Stoic Theory of Emotions 21 JOHN M.
    [Show full text]
  • I Am You Synthese Library
    I AM YOU SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Editor-in-Chief: VINCENT F. HENDRICKS, Roskilde University, Roskilde, Denmark JOHN SYMONS, University of Texas at El Paso, U.S.A. Honorary Editor: JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University, U.S.A. Editors: DIRK VAN DALEN, University of Utrecht, The Netherlands THEO A.F. KUIPERS, University of Groningen, The Netherlands TEDDY SEIDENFELD, Carnegie Mellon University, U.S.A. PATRICK SUPPES, Stanford University, California, U.S.A. JAN WOLEN´SKI, Jagiellonian University, Kraków, Poland VOLUME 325 I AM YOU The Metaphysical Foundations for Global Ethics By DANIEL KOLAK William Paterson University of New Jersey, Wayne, NJ, U.S.A. A C.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 1-4020-2999-3 (HB) ISBN 1-4020-3014-2 (e-book) Published by Springer, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, The Netherlands. Sold and distributed in North, Central and South America by Springer, 101 Philip Drive, Norwell, MA 02061, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Springer, P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, The Netherlands. Printed on acid-free paper All Rights Reserved © 2004 Springer No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work.
    [Show full text]
  • NEW CATEGORIES for FORMAL ONTOLOGY Peter SIMONS
    NEW CATEGORIES FOR FORMAL ONTOLOGY Peter SIMONS Universität Salzburg What is at first small is often extremely large in the end. And so it happens that whoever deviates only a little from truth in the begin­ ning is led farther and farther afield in the sequel, and to errors that are a thousand times larger. Pranz Brentano, On the Several Senses of Being in Aristotle, p. 1. 1. The Several Sources of Categories One of the more instructive characteristics of Jaakko Hintikka's philosophy is the way in which he uses modern methods and results to throw light on classical philosophical themes. One which is of particular interest for an ontologist is his account of categories. I Hintikka's investigations, as he is well aware, have many historical precedents. When Aristotle elaborated his kategoriai it was in terms both of most general words (predicaments, as the medievals called them), that can be said of individual things, and also as different basic kinds of things, corresponding to different ways in which something may be said to be or exist. 2 Several of Aristotle's cate­ gories are given using question-words functioning like the English 1. See Hintikka 1983, eh. 8, Hintikka 1986. As will be evident to those even casually acquainted with the many philosophical concems of Jaakko Hintikka, this essay crosses his tracks in several places apart from that of categories. for example in issues of free logic, modality, analyticity, and history of philosophy. I intend to take up some of these issues at greater length elsewhere. 2. The idea of categories as predicaments can be found in the book Categories, the idea of categories as ways something can be said to be in the Topics and Metaphysics.
    [Show full text]