Three Defences of Socrates: Relative Chronology, Politics and Religion*

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Three Defences of Socrates: Relative Chronology, Politics and Religion* chapter seven THREE DEFENCES OF SOCRATES: RELATIVE CHRONOLOGY, POLITICS AND RELIGION* †Michael Stokes This paper aimed originally to rm up from further reading and reection the tentative conclusions on the relative chronology of PA, XA, and XM1 reached in the Introduction to Stokes (1997).2 It has now become in the rst instance a defence of that chronology in the light of some subsequent schol- arly work. The argument inevitably falls short of absolute proof, but the con- clusion eventually reached is that the works by Plato and Xenophon were indeed produced in the order just stated (PA, XA, XM), and that a fourth work, Polycrates’ lost pamphlet Accusation of Socrates, appeared between XA and XM. Along the way the paper may help to convince people that Xenophon’s methods of work were in places a trie slipshod. By his ‘meth- ods of work’ is meant the way in which he treats other writers’ texts in cases of intertextuality. This may lead to a deeper understanding of Xenophon as a creative writer. A nal corollary will contribute to the debate on the ques- tion why Socrates was tried and condemned. In this contribution religious issues are highlighted. The corollary (I confess) seems to me more important than the chronological detail. We must start the chronology from a passage of the orator Isocrates referring to Polycrates’ Accusation of Socrates. Isocrates Busiris 4–5 In the proem to his Busiris, Isocrates suggests that Polycrates is especially proud of his defence of Busiris and his Accusation of Socrates. He points out, however, that Polycrates was far wide of the mark in both these pamphlets. * Gabriel Danzig read critically successive drafts of this paper: my warmest thanks to him. He is not responsible for errors and omissions; I am. 1 I thus abbreviate Plato’s and Xenophon’s Apologies of Socrates and Xenophon’s Memo- rabilia Socratis. 2 Stokes 1997: 3–4. 244 michael stokes A defence or praise, Isocrates says, should reveal more good qualities than the subject actually possessed. An attack should show the victim as having fewer good qualities. Polycrates has not done this; far from it. In defence of Busiris he has not just freed him from many slurs; he has also added to his qualities the worst lawlessness one could think of. Others trying to attack Busiris have said he sacri ced strangers; Polycrates says he ate them. By contrast, in his attempt to attack Socrates Polycrates gave Socrates Alcibiades as a pupil, presumably hitherto not known as such. Isocrates characterizes Alcibiades as one whose superiority all Greeks would admit. Socrates, the orator says, would be grateful for this change, whereas Busiris would be angry at the slur on him. It would be all too easy to dismiss this as a mere rhetorical ourish, deserving no credence.3 However, it deserves discussion, and now more discussion than ever, as an anonymous reader drew my attention to Niall Livingstone’s valuable 1999 commentary on Busiris. That commentary deals at length with (among other things) the date of the work and in particular with the point of the passage under discussion. Many people (including me) have taken this passage for granted as evidence for the dating of the works here discussed. That is no longer possible. Livingstone has raised questions about the date of the Busiris and about the seriousness of the work of Polycrates to which it refers. These questions need answers, if possible, and in any case deserve discussion. Livingstone’s arguments are not uniformly strong. First, a speci c date: Polycrates’ Accusation of Socrates, referred to in Isocrates’ Busiris, must be dated after 393–392, mentioning as it did the rebuilding of the Long Walls of Athens. How long after is debatable. Busiris also refers, in its idealised account of ancient Egypt, to several ideas forming central political themes of Plato’s Republíc. Livingstone dates it accordingly after the Republic, and hence in the 370s.4 It would, however, 3 Water eld 2009 pays no attention to Isocrates at all; in the present volume he does use Isocrates as evidence for what Polycrates actually said. He does cite another orator, Aeschin. 1. 173, writing some 50 years later and probably acquainted directly or indirectly with Polycrates’ work. Macleod 2008: 13 devotes a few sentences to the reference in the Busiris. He suggests that Isocrates here ‘sounds like a rival sophist speaking’. This seems subjective, and raises the question how far one sophist could go in falsehood about another. He cites a suggestion from M.M. Willcock to the efect that the topic of Alcibiades ‘was avoided as a weak link in the defence’. On that view see below. Macleod also thinks the politics of reference to Alcibiades and Critias may have been left to Meletus’ supporter Anytus, himself a politician of some distinction. However, there were other political topics for Anytus to talk about. See further below. 4 Livingstone 1999: 48–56..
Recommended publications
  • De Theognide Megarensi. Nietzsche on Theognis of Megara. a Bilingual Edition
    FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE De Theognide Megarensi Nietzsche on Theognis of Megara – A Bilingual Edition – Translated by R. M. Kerr THE NIETZSCHE CHANNEL Friedrich Nietzsche De Theognide Megarensi Nietzsche on Theognis of Megara A bilingual edition Translated by R. M. Kerr ☙ editio electronica ❧ _________________________________________ THE N E T ! " # H E # H A N N E $ % MM&' Copyright © Proprietas interpretatoris Roberti Martini Kerrii anno 2015 Omnia proprietatis iura reservantur et vindicantur. Imitatio prohibita sine auctoris permissione. Non licet pecuniam expetere pro aliquo, quod partem horum verborum continet; liber pro omnibus semper gratuitus erat et manet. Sic rerum summa novatur semper, et inter se mortales mutua vivunt. augescunt aliae gentes, aliae invuntur, inque brevi spatio mutantur saecla animantum et quasi cursores vitai lampada tradiunt. - Lucretius - - de Rerum Natura, II 5-! - PR"#$CE %e &or' presente( here is a trans)ation o* #rie(rich Nietzsche-s aledi!tionsarbeit ./schoo) e0it-thesis12 *or the "andesschule #$orta in 3chu)p*orta .3axony-$nhalt) presente( on 3epte4ber th 15678 It has hitherto )arge)y gone unnotice(, especial)y in anglophone Nietzsche stu(- ies8 $t the ti4e though, the &or' he)pe( to estab)ish the reputation o* the then twenty year o)( Nietzsche and consi(erab)y *aci)itate( his )ater acade4ic career8 9y a)) accounts, it &as a consi(erab)e achie:e4ent, especial)y consi(ering &hen it &as &ri;en: it entai)e( an e0pert 'no&)e(ge, not =ust o* c)assical-phi)o)ogical )iterature, but also o* co(ico)ogy8 %e recent =u(ge4ent by >"+3"+ .2017<!!2< “It is a piece that, ha( Nietzsche ne:er &ri;en another &or(, &ou)( ha:e assure( his p)ace, albeit @uite a s4a)) one, in the history o* Ger4an phi)o)ogyB su4s the 4atter up quite e)o@uently8 +ietzsche )ater continue( his %eognis stu(ies, the sub=ect o* his Crst scho)ar)y artic)e, as a stu(ent at Leip,ig, in 156 D to so4e e0tent a su44ary o* the present &or' D a critical re:ie& in 156!, as &e)) as @uotes in se:eral )e;ers *ro4 1567 on.
    [Show full text]
  • Politics and Policy in Corinth 421-336 B.C. Dissertation
    POLITICS AND POLICY IN CORINTH 421-336 B.C. DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University by DONALD KAGAN, B.A., A.M. The Ohio State University 1958 Approved by: Adviser Department of History TABLE OF CONTENTS Page FOREWORD ................................................. 1 CHAPTER I THE LEGACY OF ARCHAIC C O R I N T H ....................7 II CORINTHIAN DIPLOMACY AFTER THE PEACE OF NICIAS . 31 III THE DECLINE OF CORINTHIAN P O W E R .................58 IV REVOLUTION AND UNION WITH ARGOS , ................ 78 V ARISTOCRACY, TYRANNY AND THE END OF CORINTHIAN INDEPENDENCE ............... 100 APPENDIXES .............................................. 135 INDEX OF PERSONAL N A M E S ................................. 143 BIBLIOGRAPHY ........................................... 145 AUTOBIOGRAPHY ........................................... 149 11 FOREWORD When one considers the important role played by Corinth in Greek affairs from the earliest times to the end of Greek freedom it is remarkable to note the paucity of monographic literature on this key city. This is particular­ ly true for the classical period wnere the sources are few and scattered. For the archaic period the situation has been somewhat better. One of the first attempts toward the study of Corinthian 1 history was made in 1876 by Ernst Curtius. This brief art­ icle had no pretensions to a thorough investigation of the subject, merely suggesting lines of inquiry and stressing the importance of numisihatic evidence. A contribution of 2 similar score was undertaken by Erich Wilisch in a brief discussion suggesting some of the problems and possible solutions. This was followed by a second brief discussion 3 by the same author.
    [Show full text]
  • Isocrates and the Rhetorical Creation of Europe: the Medium As
    Isocrates & Europe - 1 Isocrates and the Rhetorical Creation of Europe: The Medium as Message I. Introduction: Overview The idea that Isocrates helped create the concept of transnationalism that fostered Europe both as an idea and as an eventual political union is common fare in rhetorical studies. De Romilly (1992) writes that “Isocrates was perhaps the first in antiquity to focus his political theories on the idea of Europe” (p. 2). Isocrates anticipated “the idea of Europe” (Hariman, 2004, p. 231) and used the words Europen and Europes 13 times in his essays. But, to date, critical exploration of Isocrates’ role in developing the idea of Europe has primarily dealt with the content of his works – with his eloquent and relentless focus on panhellenism and the related conflict between Europe and Asia. This paper, however, will focus on medium rather than message. It will focus on Isocrates’ pioneering use of a new medium – written documents/syggrammata – and the role that the new rhetorical medium played in forming Europe. The most famous passage in the Isocratean canon, the so-called Hymn to Logos (Jaeger, 1944/1971), which first appeared in Nicocles (5-9) and was repeated in Antidosis (253-257), holds that speech/logos is a civic and political unifier, by means of which “we have come together and founded cities and made laws and invented arts” (Nicocles 6). Yet before Isocrates, who was “the first individual who could be termed a ‘writer’ in the modern sense of the term” (Lentz, 1989), logos and its community-building powers Isocrates & Europe - 2 traveled primarily orally: Cities, alliances, arts, and laws were built through face-to-face communication.
    [Show full text]
  • 4 Men and Books in Fourth-Century BC Athens
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Archivio istituzionale della ricerca - Università di Bari 4 Men and books in fourth-century BC Athens pasquale massimo pinto The cultural background Between the last quarter of the fifth and the beginning of the fourth cen- tury BC a major change appears to have taken place in Athenian culture. Despite differences of opinion over specific problems, today scholars tend to agree that the textual and archaeological evidence together allows us to reconstruct an age in which literacy became more widespread and a “book culture” gradually gained ground.1 We may observe the spread of a new culturalmedium,thebook,inthelifeofthepolis and also infer that this change took place not only in everyday life but also in people’s minds. The papyrus roll, introduced into Greece from Egypt during the preceding centuries, proved to be an effective medium for preserving writing and an easy and versatile means of written communication. It was employed to preserve regulations governing the lives of citizens of the polis;tocirculate political programmes and cultural polemics; to advertise a victory won in the law courts through publication of the successful speech; and as an aid to study and entertainment both for individuals and for groups of listen- ers and readers.2 In addition, there is another aspect which must be taken into consideration when dealing with Greek written culture of this period, namely the development of the genres of prose. By the fourth century, prose had partly replaced poetry and drama as a means of communicating social and political values and ideas.3 It is against the background of these developments that this chapter deals with the emerging practice of preserving and collecting books, and 1 The 1952 paper of Eric Turner, Athenian Books in the Fifth and Fourth Centuries B.C.,canstill serve as a valid point of departure for those who want to carry on research on this subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Download/View PDF (GK)
    GREEK In the Department of Classics The Classics Department offers courses listed in this catalogue under “Classics,” “Greek,” and “Latin.” Course Offerings [GK111] Introductory Greek An introduction to the ancient Greek language as spoken and written at Athens during the 5th and 4th centuries BCE. The first of a two-semester sequence in which students learn to read authors such as Homer, Sophocles, and Plato. Careful attention to grammar, syntax, and vocabulary forms the foundation of the course. Four credit hours. GK111Jj Introductory Greek An introduction to the ancient Greek language as spoken and written at Athens during the 5th and 4th centuries BCE. The first of a two-semester sequence in which students learn to read authors such as Homer, Sophocles, and Plato. Careful attention to grammar, syntax, and vocabulary forms the foundation of the course. Three credit hours. MILLER GK112s Intermediate Greek The second of a two-semester sequence in which students learn to read the ancient Greek of classical Athens. Careful attention to grammar, syntax, and vocabulary forms the foundation of the course. Prerequisite: Greek 111. Four credit hours. MILLER GK131f Introduction to Greek Literature Introduction to reading original ancient Greek texts, coupled with a review of grammar and syntax. Texts vary from year to year and may include poetry and/or prose. Prerequisite: Greek 112. Four credit hours. L. BARRETT [GK235] Plato: Apology of Socrates In 399 BCE, Socrates was charged with impiety and put on trial. Plato's Apology presents Socrates' defense speech in which he explains himself and his unusual way of life as a lover of wisdom.
    [Show full text]
  • Link to PDF File
    THE ORIGIN OF ALEXANDER THE GREAT AND THE MACEDONIANS DOCUMENTATION ACCORDING TO ANCIENT GREEK LITERARY TEXTS Herodotus, Thucydides, Plutarchus, Arrian, Demosthenes, Polybius, Isocrates, Strabo, Hesiod INTRODUCTION This survey is written to prove historical facts that are actually indisputable and beyond the shadow of any doubt. However, since today there is on-going discourse on the self- evident, it might be useful that we should remain and explore these issues for a while. One of my recent studies on the origin of Alexander and the Macedonians, based on the works of great authors of ancient Greece has led to the documentation of the –more or less known- arguments on the issue. And since the semiotic value of the word is a far more serious issue that one could assume, and even more significantly when it concerns an historic and highly controversial word as Macedonia, it is essential to take a close look on what is recorded by the historians of antiquity1. Ι. THUCYDIDES (464 – 395 BC) Starting from the beginnings of the references on the term Hellenes/Greeks we see that Thucydides, one of the greatest historians and political philosophers of all times reports that before the Trojan War, there is no mention of the term Hellenes and that the first time we meet the term is in Homer as a definition of those from Fthiotis under Achilles who participated in the expedition against Troy – “the first Hellenes”2. In Homer, Thucydides continues, the Hellenes are referred to in the same sense as the Achaeans, Argaei (from Argos), Danaäns. It should be pointed out that the term “barbarians” is not met in the Homeric epics since the term “Hellenes” had not yet been singled out (and later established) “as the exact opposite definition” to distinguish Hellenes from ‘barbarians’3, as the great historian concludes.
    [Show full text]
  • Atack  August   Carol Atack
    Histos () – THE DISCOURSE OF KINGSHIP IN CLASSICAL ATHENIAN THOUGHT Abstract: Athenian foundation myth includes stories of kings, retold in different genres to pursue distinct political agendas and to reshape the Athenian political imaginary. This article explores the transition from drama to history as a vehicle for these stories, and the exploitation of this transition in Isocrates’ political rhetoric, conflating myth and history. While Euripides’ democratic king Theseus represented an idealised active citizen, Isocra- tes retold Athenian myth to show that the good qualities of Athenian democracy depend on their origins in the city’s political foundation by Theseus, and that citizens should achieve the good life through imitating virtuous monarchs . Keywords: Athens, kingship, Atthidography, Isocrates, Theseus ven within the context of Athenian democracy, the figure of the king provided a powerful image with which a range of political ideas Ecould be explored and arguments made. Athenian political thinkers and speakers could draw on a rich heritage of Greek mythology and founda- tion legend, including those specific to Attica, to explore and develop ideas about good citizenship and leadership, analogise characters to present-day politicians, or propose solutions to political problems. The reworking of kingship myth for political ends was a feature of several genres of Athenian literature across the fifth and fourth centuries BCE . Both Isocrates and Ly- curgus cited kingship myths for novel political and propaganda purposes, drawing on both tragic and historical accounts of the city’s distant past. Their texts show the uses to which the ideal of the king as super-citizen and holder of a superior understanding of the polis , inherited from Euripidean tragedy, could be put; they also position the kings they use in a curious space between myth and history.
    [Show full text]
  • Sparta, Athens, and the Surprising Roots of Common Schooling Avi I
    Avi I. Mintz 105 Sparta, Athens, and the Surprising Roots of Common Schooling Avi I. Mintz University of Tulsa INTRODUCTION When Plato and Aristotle advocated common schooling in antiquity, they referred regularly to Sparta. They may have been critical of some aspects of Spartan education, but each conceded that Sparta was the preeminent model of common education designed, administered, and preserved by a political community. When Plato has an Athenian Visitor discuss the outlines of a well-governed polis in Laws – and education is taken to be central to cultivating virtue among citizens and, hence creating a virtuous political regime – he sets the conversation among an Athenian, a Spartan and Cretan.1 In Politics, when Aristotle warns against individualistic, private education and calls for common education, he singles out Sparta for credit: “One might well praise the Spartans for this: they most of all pay serious attention to their children, and do so in common.”2 In the Nicomachean Ethics, the same claim appears: “in the city of the Spartans alone, or among few others, does the lawgiver seem to have taken care for upbringing and exercises, while in most cities they have been utterly careless about such things, and each person lives the way he wants.”3 Indeed, there is a long tradition of admiration for Sparta’s prioritization of education. For example, Plutarch says that Lycurgus, the quasi-mythical founder of Sparta, declared that education is “the greatest and noblest task of the law-giver.”4 While Spartans were celebrated for creating the most impressive sys- tem of common education in Greece, they were simultaneously regarded as the least cultured, the least sophisticated, and the least educated of all Greeks.
    [Show full text]
  • Greeks, Barbarians and Alexander the Great: the Formula for an Empire
    Athens Journal of History - Volume 5, Issue 3 – Pages 209-224 Greeks, Barbarians and Alexander the Great: The Formula for an Empire By Irina Frasin Under the leadership of Alexander the Great the Greeks reached far into Asia. This extraordinary enterprise was made possible not only by his well- equipped and trained army but also by his revolutionary way of thinking. What facilitated the creation of such a vast empire, apart from his military genius, was his attitude towards the Others, his incredible openness and curiosity towards the difference and the different. This made his relatively short reign have colossal influence in both eastern and western worlds. My paper analyses this moment of meeting between cultures, focusing on the construction of the image of the Other, the different, the barbarian, the enemy and the impact of this ideology upon shaping the empire that Alexander the Great built. Introduction Under the leadership of Alexander the Great, the Macedonians and their Greek allies from the League of Corinth, conquered the East. This extraordinary adventure, that took them far into the heart of Asia and close to the allegedly believed end of the Earth, was made possible by both the strategic and military genius of Alexander (together with the well-equipped and trained army he inherited from his father, King Phillip II) and the Greek thought and philosophy. The Greeks were firm believers in their superiority over barbarians1. They imagined that their freedom, their reason and their sense of measure could and should transform them into the leaders of the barbarians, who, in the eyes of Aristotle, were "slaves by nature"2.
    [Show full text]
  • The Theory of Greek Democracy Before Aristotle
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1943 The Theory of Greek Democracy Before Aristotle Edmund P. Burke Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Burke, Edmund P., "The Theory of Greek Democracy Before Aristotle" (1943). Master's Theses. 77. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/77 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1943 Edmund P. Burke THE THEORY OF GREEK DEMOCRACY BEFORE ARISTOTLE • BY EDMUND P. BURKE, S.J. A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL li'ULFIT.IMENT OF THE REQ,UIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN LOYOLA UNIVERSITY JULY 1943, VITA Edmund P. Burke, S.J., was born in Chicago, Illinois, on August 4, 1916. He moved to Oak Park, Illinois, and graduated from Ascension Grammar School in 1930. The following three years, from 1930 to 1933, he attended ~uigley Preparatory Seminary, Chicago, Illinois. He graduated from St. Ignatius High School in that city in 1934. In September of that year he entered the Milford Novitiate of the Society of Jesus, attending the Arts College of Xavier Univer­ sity, Cincinnati, Ohio, from 1934 to 1938. In 1938 he transferred to West Baden College of Loyola University, where he received his degree of Bachelor of Arts in 1939.
    [Show full text]
  • Publication of Political Oratory As an Instrument of Historical Revisionism
    CHAPTER NINE GETTING THE LAST WORD: PUBLICATION OF POLITICAL ORATORY AS AN INSTRUMENT OF HISTORICAL REVISIONISM THOMAS HUBBARD Most students of Attic oratory make the automatic assumption that the 150-odd speeches we have extant accurately preserve the techniques and actual words used by the orators in oral delivery before the original au- dience. Of course, everyone acknowledges a few exceptions, such as the Tetralogies of Antiphon and the epideictic speeches of Isocrates, but even these speeches carefully maintain a fiction of actual delivery, in some cases before a very specific audience. Antiphon’s Tetralogies and perhaps even his other speeches were mainly intended to provide text- book models.1 Epideictic speeches like the Erotikoi logoi attributed to Lysias and Demosthenes were clearly literary exercises, and even more serious works like the longer epideictic orations of Isocrates were pub- lished to serve as political pamphlets advancing the author’s views to all of Greece.2 Neither Isocrates’ weak voice nor the elaborate Kunstprosa of these orations was well suited to oral delivery. Wilamowitz, Eduard Meyer, and more recently Mogens Herman Hansen have suggested that even Demosthenes’ symbouleutic speeches should perhaps also be considered political pamphlets: out of the many thousands of symbouleutic speeches delivered in fourth-century Athens, and even among the dozens of such speeches that Demosthenes himself doubtless delivered, only a handful were ever published, judging from those extant as well as the fragments and testimonia.3 One can well ————— 1 On the intended audience of the Tetralogies, see Gagarin (2002: 103-6). 2 For the political and educational functions of Isocrates’ published work, see Mathieu (1925), Bringmann (1965), Masaracchia (1995: 81-149), and Poulakos (1997).
    [Show full text]
  • Photius on the Ten Orators , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 33:2 (1992:Summer) P.159
    SMITH, REBEKAH M., Photius on the Ten Orators , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 33:2 (1992:Summer) p.159 Photius on the Ten Orators Rebekah M. Smith liE DIffERENCES between the two survIving versions of T The Lives of the Ten Orators have given rise to various explanations for the history of the treatise. The original work of that title is no. 55 of Plutarch's Moralia (832B-52c: hereafter 'Ps.-Plutarch'), and a second version is presented in codices 259-68 of Photius' Bibliotheca. The differences be­ tween the two, some major, some minor, are many. In the Bibliotheca, for example, most of the lives have been rearranged to present a more chronological flow of narrative. The pinax in which Photius lists the works contained in the Bibliotheca gives the ten orators' lives in the traditional order, by birth, in which they occur in the Moralia. In the codices themselves, however, Isocrates appears second, not fourth, Lycurgus has been moved from seventh place to tenth, I and almost every life shows minor deletions and additions when compared with the corresponding life as given by Ps.-Plutarch. Four of the lives, however, are prefaced by extensive stylistic criticisms. These range from collections of brief comments to a twenty-five-line quotation of Caecilius of Calcacte on Antiphon's use of figures (485B 14-40). 1 I have found no other example of such reordering. Whether or not it was Photius who reorganized this material, it is more likely that someone rearranging an already written work would put less organized items into better order than that the process of transmission could produce as many changes for the worse as these lives show.
    [Show full text]