Inductions, Red Herrings, and the Best Explanation for the Mixed Record of Science

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Inductions, Red Herrings, and the Best Explanation for the Mixed Record of Science University at Albany, State University of New York Scholars Archive Philosophy Faculty Scholarship Philosophy 6-2010 Inductions, red herrings, and the best explanation for the mixed record of science P.D. Magnus University at Albany, State University of New York, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsarchive.library.albany.edu/cas_philosophy_scholar Part of the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Magnus, P.D., "Inductions, red herrings, and the best explanation for the mixed record of science" (2010). Philosophy Faculty Scholarship. 49. https://scholarsarchive.library.albany.edu/cas_philosophy_scholar/49 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Scholars Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholars Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Inductions, red herrings, and the best explanation for the mixed record of science P.D. Magnus∗ December 22, 2009 This is the author's final draft of a paper forthcoming The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. e-mail: pmagnus(at)fecundity.com web: http://www.fecundity.com/job Abstract Kyle Stanford has recently claimed to offer a new challenge to sci- entific realism. Taking his inspiration from the familiar Pessimistic In- duction (PI), Stanford proposes a New Induction (NI). Contra Anjan Chakravartty's suggestion that the NI is a \red herring", I argue that it reveals something deep and important about science. The Problem of Unconceived Alternatives, which lies at the heart of the NI, yields a richer anti-realism than the PI. It explains why science falls short when it falls short, and so it might figure in the most coherent account of scientific practice. However, this best account will be antirealist in some respects and about some theories. It will not be a sweeping antirealism about all or most of science. Kyle Stanford [Sta01][Sta06] claims to mount a new challenge to scientific realism. Taking his inspiration from the familiar Pessimistic Induction (PI), Stanford proposes a New Induction (NI). Anjan Chakravartty [Cha08, p. 153] has recently called the NI a \red herring", arguing that it poses no new prob- lem for realism. Patrick Enfield suggests similarly that \Stanford might deny it, but. what really does the work in this argument are `historical' claims associ- ated with the pessimistic induction" [Enf08, p. 883]. I argue that this charge is unjustified. Moreover, the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives | which lies at the heart of the NI | yields a richer anti-realism than the PI. It explains why science falls short when it falls short, and so it might figure in the most coherent ∗This paper grew out of a seminar at the University at Albany, SUNY. I want to thank all the participants, especially John Milanese and Elizabeth Gray. Thanks to Anjan Chakravartty, Gregory Frost-Arnold, Kyle Stanford, and anonymous referees for feedback on earlier drafts. 1 account of scientific practice. This antirealist element in our best explanatory account of science may ultimately be galling to realists, but it won't be all wine and roses for antirealists either. In x1, I review the familiar Pessimistic Induction. In x2{x3, I discuss how best to understand Stanford's New Induction. In x4, I consider the objection that the NI is a red herring. I argue that it is not. In x5, I suggest that the challenge Stanford mounts to realism leads to a richer account of science than previous arguments like the PI. 1 The Pessimistic Induction The Pessimistic Induction (PI) relies on the history of science in an attempt to establish anti-realism in this way: PI-1 The historical record reveals that past theories which were successful typ- ically turned out to have been false. PI-2 So, our present scientific theories, although successful, will probably turn out to be false. PI-3 Therefore, we should not believe our best present theories. In the voluminous literature replying to the PI, realists have tried to block the argument in a number of ways. Several kinds of objection are worth distinguish- ing. First, even admitting that there is a pattern in the historical record, gener- alizing from the pattern might be fallacious. Various statistical considerations have been used to try and block the move from history to PI-1. Lewis [Lew01] has argued that it commits a base rate fallacy. Lange [Lan02] has argued that it commits what he calls the turnover fallacy. To be sure, generalizing from history is a tricky business. Second, realists try to block the inference from PI-1 to PI-2 by insisting that present theories are better in some respect than abandoned past theories. If this difference can be made explicit, so much the better | but even in the absence of an explicit description, a realist can still claim that there is some difference. Stanford acknowledges the possibility of this reply and accepts it arguendo [Sta06, p. 10{11], but he does not seem to give it much weight; after answering the third sort of reply (discussed below), he considers the PI estab- lished. Nevertheless, this realist reply need not be hopelessly ad hoc. One might consider this to be part of a realist package, in the sense of Boyd [Boy90]. The idea behind the package reply is this: The anti-realist may match the realist on each individual point, with each individual contention coming to a stalemate. Nevertheless, realism does better as an overall view | it provides a more coher- ent explanatory account of science. Part of the realist account is that present theories are better than past theories, and so we have some reason to believe that they are. 2 Third, realists say that the parts of the theories that got the world right were the same parts that were responsible for the theories' success. These parts have not been rejected, but instead continue as parts of present theories. Just as we still believe in the working parts of past theories, we should now believe in the working parts of our present theories. Arguments of this kind are given by Kitcher [Kit93] and Psillos [Psi99], among others. The approach admits that past theories were literally false, while insisting that they were nevertheless partly correct. Following Chang [Cha03], I'll call this approach preservative realism. Stanford calls this an appeal to \partial confirmation” and replies to it at length [Sta06, chs. 5{6]. We might be able to tell such a story retrospectively, he argues, but it should come as no surprise that the parts of the successful past theories that we now think were the core of them were the parts that we now think are true. What is judged to have been useful is what is judged to have been true, but the standards by which we judge what was efficacious are the same standards by which we judge what was true. Moreover, preservative realism only allows the realist to say after the fact which parts of a theory were doing the work. That is, the realist can only retrospectively identify which parts of a superseded theory were likely to be true and thus were worthy of belief. It is not enough for scientific realism as a general doctrine that we can, in some special instances, divide the confirmed from the unconfirmed parts of present theories. A general doctrine requires a general criterion. Stanford does not claim a priori that such a forward-looking criterion is impossible, but notes that we do not have such a criterion and do not have any prospects for finding one. If Stanford is right, then the realist cannot justify belief in our present theories | we will only be able to say at some point in the future what it is that we would now have been justified in believing today. Stanford calls this a \pyrrhic victory" for realism. They win the preservative battle at the cost of their realist souls. 2 Stanford's New Induction Stanford poses a problem which he means to be a hybrid of the PI and the problem of underdetermination. He dubs it the Problem of Unconceived Alter- natives, and he means to establish it by a New Induction (NI). In this section, I briefly summarize the NI. Scientists typically cannot address all the relevant theoretical alternatives. There are theories which never explicitly occur to them as live possibilities, but which later scientists take seriously. Yet scientists often rely on eliminative inference; that is, they rule out all but one of the possibilities and conclude that whatever remains must be right. (On the importance of eliminative inference to science, see inter alia Kitcher [Kit93, ch. 7] and Bird [Bir06].) Of course, eliminative induction is sometimes justified. It is an \old axiom," as Sherlock Holmes says, \that when all other contingencies fail, whatever re- mains, however improbable, must be the truth" [Doy05, p. 926]. To take a mystery-story example, suppose we know that one of five suspects in the se- 3 cluded manor must have committed the murder. If evidence exonerates four of them, then the fifth must be the killer. It is always logically possible to question the exhaustion premise in such a case, but there might not be any alternatives worth taking seriously in a mundane case like this. The requisite premise is contingent and known only fallibly, but we can know it in some cases. Stanford will admit as much, and he is not concerned to challenge every use of eliminative inference [Sta06, p. 29 ff.]. In scientific cases concerning distant regions or exotic features of the world, however, Stanford argues that we cannot be confident that we have considered all the possibilities.
Recommended publications
  • Polygamy As a Red Herring in the Same-Sex Marriage Debate
    012306 09_KHALSA.DOC 2/6/2006 10:22 AM Note POLYGAMY AS A RED HERRING IN THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE DEBATE RUTH K. KHALSA INTRODUCTION Critics of same -sex marriage have argued that if same-sex marriage is legalized, then eventually polygamy and other currently prohibited sexual relationships, such as bestiality and incest, will be legalized as well. The polygamy issue received increased attention during the 1996 congressional hearings1 on the Defense of Marriage Act.2 Representative Bob Inglis of South Carolina asked, “If a person had an ‘insatiable desire’ to marry more than one wife . what argument did gay activists have to deny him a legal, polygamous marriage?”3 That same year, the Supreme Court decided Romer v. Evans,4 holding unconstitutional a Colorado state amendment that would have repealed existing city ordinances prohibiting Copyright © 2005 by Ruth K. Khalsa. 1. Professor Hadley Arkes stated that: [I]f marriage . could mean just anything the positive law proclaimed it to mean, then the positive law could define just about anything as a marriage. [W]hy shouldn’t it be possible to permit a mature woman, past child bearing, to marry her grown son? In fact, why would it not be possible to permit a man, much taken with himself, to marry himself? . [Although] I am not predicting that, if gay marriage were allowed, we would be engulfed by incest and polygamy[,] . [w]hat is being posed here is a question of principle: [w]hat is the ground on which the law would turn back these challenges? Defense of Marriage Act: Hearings on H.R.
    [Show full text]
  • Griffis V. Luban: a Red Herring in the High Seas of Personal Jurisdiction Laura S
    William Mitchell Law Review Volume 29 | Issue 2 Article 15 2002 Griffis v. Luban: A Red Herring in the High Seas of Personal Jurisdiction Laura S. Ferster Follow this and additional works at: http://open.mitchellhamline.edu/wmlr Recommended Citation Ferster, Laura S. (2002) "Griffis v. Luban: A Red Herring in the High Seas of Personal Jurisdiction," William Mitchell Law Review: Vol. 29: Iss. 2, Article 15. Available at: http://open.mitchellhamline.edu/wmlr/vol29/iss2/15 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Reviews and Journals at Mitchell Hamline Open Access. It has been accepted for inclusion in William Mitchell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Mitchell Hamline Open Access. For more information, please contact [email protected]. © Mitchell Hamline School of Law Ferster: Griffis v. Luban: A Red Herring in the High Seas of Personal Juri FINAL FERSTER GRIFFIS.DOC 10/28/2002 10:47 PM GRIFFIS V. LUBAN: A RED HERRING IN THE HIGH SEAS OF PERSONAL JURISDICTION Laura S. Ferster† I. INTRODUCTION ...................................................................343 II. GRIFFIS:FACTS & PROCEDURAL HISTORY..............................345 A. Facts ............................................................................345 B. Griffis in the Minnesota Court of Appeals........................346 C. Griffis in the Minnesota Supreme Court ..........................347 III. ANALYSIS OF THE GRIFFIS HOLDING......................................348 A. “Sound Bites” of Fair Play and Substantial
    [Show full text]
  • Why Disparate Impact Liability Does Not Induce Hiring Quotas
    The Q-Word as Red Herring: Why Disparate Impact Liability Does Not Induce Hiring Quotas Ian Ayres* and Peter Siegelman** I. Introduction The debates over the passage of Title VII of the 1964 Civil Rights Act' were marked by passionate disagreement: conservatives objected to the legislation as an unwarranted interference with employers' freedom of contract, while liberal supporters considered it a first step toward racial justice. While disagreement about what employment discrimination law should do has continued-in much the same form-to this day,3 there has been surprising consensus about the mechanism by which Title VII actually works:4 whether it is thought of as inadequate or excessive, Title VII is * William K. Townsend Professor of Law, Yale Law School. ** Research Fellow, American Bar Foundation and Olin Law and Economics Visiting Fellow, Yale Law School. Henry Hansmann made helpful comments, as did Keith Hylton on a much earlier version of some of the ideas. We also gratefully acknowledge many constructive discussions with members of the Symposium on The Changing Workplace. Dawn Jeglum-Bartusch, Franklin Parlamis, and Cathy Sharkey provided excellent research assistance. 1. 42 U.S.C. § 2000a (1994). 2. See ALFRED W. BLUMROSEN, MODERN LAW: THE LAW TRANSMISSION SYSrEM AND EQUAL EMPLOYMENT OPPORTUNITY 43 (1993) ("The common ground between [southern Democrats and conservative Republicans in the U.S. Senate] was the desire to minimize federal regulation. Conservative Republicans did not want business hobbled by extensive regulation, and the southern Democrats had the same conviction about the southern way of life [i.e., segregation]."); Michael E. Gold, Griggs' Folly: An Essay on the Theory, Problems, and Origin of the Adverse Impact Definition of Employment Discriminationand a Recommendation for Reform, 7 INDUS.
    [Show full text]
  • Corpus Study of Tense, Aspect, and Modality in Diglossic Speech in Cairene Arabic
    CORPUS STUDY OF TENSE, ASPECT, AND MODALITY IN DIGLOSSIC SPEECH IN CAIRENE ARABIC BY OLA AHMED MOSHREF DISSERTATION Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics in the Graduate College of the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, 2012 Urbana, Illinois Doctoral Committee: Professor Elabbas Benmamoun, Chair Professor Eyamba Bokamba Professor Rakesh M. Bhatt Assistant Professor Marina Terkourafi ABSTRACT Morpho-syntactic features of Modern Standard Arabic mix intricately with those of Egyptian Colloquial Arabic in ordinary speech. I study the lexical, phonological and syntactic features of verb phrase morphemes and constituents in different tenses, aspects, moods. A corpus of over 3000 phrases was collected from religious, political/economic and sports interviews on four Egyptian satellite TV channels. The computational analysis of the data shows that systematic and content morphemes from both varieties of Arabic combine in principled ways. Syntactic considerations play a critical role with regard to the frequency and direction of code-switching between the negative marker, subject, or complement on one hand and the verb on the other. Morph-syntactic constraints regulate different types of discourse but more formal topics may exhibit more mixing between Colloquial aspect or future markers and Standard verbs. ii To the One Arab Dream that will come true inshaa’ Allah! عربية أنا.. أميت دمها خري الدماء.. كما يقول أيب الشاعر العراقي: بدر شاكر السياب Arab I am.. My nation’s blood is the finest.. As my father says Iraqi Poet: Badr Shaker Elsayyab iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I’m sincerely thankful to my advisor Prof. Elabbas Benmamoun, who during the six years of my study at UIUC was always kind, caring and supportive on the personal and academic levels.
    [Show full text]
  • 35. Logic: Common Fallacies Steve Miller Kennesaw State University, [email protected]
    Kennesaw State University DigitalCommons@Kennesaw State University Sexy Technical Communications Open Educational Resources 3-1-2016 35. Logic: Common Fallacies Steve Miller Kennesaw State University, [email protected] Cherie Miller Kennesaw State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.kennesaw.edu/oertechcomm Part of the Technical and Professional Writing Commons Recommended Citation Miller, Steve and Miller, Cherie, "35. Logic: Common Fallacies" (2016). Sexy Technical Communications. 35. http://digitalcommons.kennesaw.edu/oertechcomm/35 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Open Educational Resources at DigitalCommons@Kennesaw State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Sexy Technical Communications by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Kennesaw State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Logic: Common Fallacies Steve and Cherie Miller Sexy Technical Communication Home Logic and Logical Fallacies Taken with kind permission from the book Why Brilliant People Believe Nonsense by J. Steve Miller and Cherie K. Miller Brilliant People Believe Nonsense [because]... They Fall for Common Fallacies The dull mind, once arriving at an inference that flatters the desire, is rarely able to retain the impression that the notion from which the inference started was purely problematic. ― George Eliot, in Silas Marner In the last chapter we discussed passages where bright individuals with PhDs violated common fallacies. Even the brightest among us fall for them. As a result, we should be ever vigilant to keep our critical guard up, looking for fallacious reasoning in lectures, reading, viewing, and especially in our own writing. None of us are immune to falling for fallacies.
    [Show full text]
  • From Homo Sovieticus to Homo Zapiens: Viktor Pelevin's Consumer
    From Homo Sovieticus to Homo Zapiens: Viktor Pelevin’s Consumer Dystopia SOFYA KHAGI Boasting a rich tradition of utopian/dystopian fiction, Russian literature has seen the most recent burgeoning of the genre in the late twentieth and early twenty-first centuries. With the advancement of Gorbachev’s reforms in the mid-1980s, Russian writers engaged in an increasingly open attack on the mythology of Socialist utopia. It was during those years that the negative subgenre of dystopia once again came to the forefront of literature. As the collapse of the Soviet empire seemed more and more imminent, a number of parodic treatments of the Socialist experiment appeared, as well as more somber works concerned with the menaces attending the looming breakdown of the Soviet state.1 Whether writing in the primarily satiric vein used by Voinovich, Veller, and Aksenov, or in the more wistful spirit exemplified by the Strugatsky brothers in their later oeuvre, the writers of Gorbachev’s epoch sought to reinterpret the past and to discern possible venues for the country’s future. These attempts continued after the fall of the Soviet Union. This article examines Viktor Pelevin’s Generation “П”, one of the most conspicuous turn-of-the-century Russian novels. It can be productively analyzed as a fin-de-siècle expression of dystopian imagination.2 I view Pelevin’s work as marking a crucial watershed in the development of the genre in Russia. While dystopias written during perestroika, including Pelevin’s Omon Ra and some of his early short stories from the collection Blue Lantern, were mainly preoccupied with the deconstruction of Soviet utopia, and with prognostications of the possible consequences of the country’s breakdown, Generation “П” is the first major post-Soviet work to come to grips with the introduction of consumer capitalism and global pop culture.
    [Show full text]
  • Delhi's Plan for Air Filters at Intersections Is a Red Herring
    Delhi's Plan for Air Filters at Intersections is a Red Herring http://thewire.in/77114/air-filters-delhi-pollution/ ENVIRONMENT BY SARATH GUTTIKUNDA ON 01/11/2016 • LEAVE A COMMENT 1 of 9 04-11-2016 22:39 Delhi's Plan for Air Filters at Intersections is a Red Herring http://thewire.in/77114/air-filters-delhi-pollution/ The setting sun over Connaught Place, New Delhi. Credit: wili/Flickr, CC BY 2.0 New Delhi: The first sentence we hear in an introduction to air pollution is that it knows no boundaries – unless you build a wall around it. Then again, even the great wall of China is incapable of holding back the interaction of pollutants between China and Mongolia – both of which, along with India, have the most polluted cities in the world according to the WHO (http://www.who.int /phe/health_topics/outdoorair/en/). The situation in Delhi, where the conversation on air pollution has been peaking because of Diwali celebrations, additional factors like agricultural clearing (http://www.indiaairquality.info/emissions-forest-and-agri-burning/) by fire in the Indo-Gangetic plain, slowing wind speeds, curling north- westerly winds (http://www.indiaairquality.info/iaqi-meteo/), dropping temperatures (necessitating the need to burn some more wood and coal to keep warm) have exacerbated the problem. At this juncture, the Delhi Government has just announced (https://www.theguardian.com/world/2016/oct/29/choking-delhi-to-install- air-purifiers-at-intersections-for-diwali) that it will install air filters and mist fountains at traffic intersections to make the air cleaner.
    [Show full text]
  • Race As a Red Herring - the Logical Irrelevance of the Race Vs
    Denver Law Review Volume 88 Issue 4 Special Issue - Class and American Article 10 Legal Education December 2020 Race as a Red Herring - The Logical Irrelevance of the Race vs. Class Debate Arin N. Reeves Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.du.edu/dlr Recommended Citation Arin N. Reeves, Race as a Red Herring - The Logical Irrelevance of the Race vs. Class Debate, 88 Denv. U. L. Rev. 835 (2011). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ DU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Denver Law Review by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ DU. For more information, please contact [email protected],[email protected]. RACE AS A RED HERRING? THE LOGICAL IRRELEVANCE OF THE RACE VS. CLASS DEBATE ARIN N. REEVESt A theory has only the alternative of being right or wrong. A model has a thirdpossibility: it may be right, but irrelevant. - Manfred Eigent INTRODUCTION A theory is a hypothesis of what will happen when a particular set of circumstances are in play. The theory can be right in predicting out- comes or it can be wrong. When a theory is well-tested and highly reli- able, it can hope to become a scientific principle or even a scientific law. A model, on the other hand, is a structure or a narrative through which one strives to illustrate the theory being pursued. As Manfred Eigen elucidates in the quote above, a theory can be proven right or wrong with data and/or by experimentation; however, the model or narrative created to explain that theory does not necessarily have to be wrong to be wholly irrelevant.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ledger and Times, September 13, 1948
    Murray State's Digital Commons The Ledger & Times Newspapers 9-13-1948 The Ledger and Times, September 13, 1948 The Ledger and Times Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.murraystate.edu/tlt Recommended Citation The Ledger and Times, "The Ledger and Times, September 13, 1948" (1948). The Ledger & Times. 6988. https://digitalcommons.murraystate.edu/tlt/6988 This Newspaper is brought to you for free and open access by the Newspapers at Murray State's Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Ledger & Times by an authorized administrator of Murray State's Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. sk. 'r ,.,r-1-7-i- Itite,*7.f4:- • Selected As Best All-Round Kentucky Community Newspaper For 1941 "777 3 • s•-• MU Milli i4114" I I WEATHER FORECAST KENTUCKY—Fair and quite rain of warm today, some cloudiness kful. timight and Tuesday, not Si, Mr. and at warm Tuesday. Mr. and laughter fnn Orr ni and callers YOUR PROGRESSIVE H 0 M F NEWS- • — Vol. XX; No. 75 as Van- United Press PAPER FOR OVER HALF A CRNTURY Murray, Kentucky, Monday Afternoon, Sept. I 3, 1948 MURRAY POPULATION 8,000 ene and CeY. Mr. daugh- rs. EXPECTED Geo- Last Week TRUMAN Local F.F.A. Members Mr. and TO VISIT KENTUCKY laturday In Kentucky irned to ON CAMPAIGN TOUR Kentucky politicians moved fast my after during the past week as the fall LOUISVILLE, Ky.. Sept. 13. For th To rela- Exhibit First shape up. • campaign began to rUP)---Kentucky Democrats today Russell I.
    [Show full text]
  • Kirkus Reviews on Our BOARD & NOVELTY BOOKS
    Featuring 340 Industry-First Reviews of Fiction, Nonfiction, Children'sand YA books KIRKUSVOL. LXXXIX, NO. 8 | 15 APRIL 2021 REVIEWS SPECIAL Indie ISSUE Plus interviews with: Celebrating the spark & spirit of Kaitlyn Greenidge, Justine Bateman, independently published books Laekan Zea Kemp, and Jay Hosler With a sampler of great Indie writing and conversations with the authors FROM THE EDITOR’S DESK | Karen Schechner Chairman Direct Access Reading HERBERT SIMON President & Publisher MARC WINKELMAN # When writing about independent publishing, I usually trot out the Chief Executive Officer stats. The point being: Read more Indie! Millions of people already do. MEG LABORDE KUEHN For this year’s Indie Issue, instead of another rundown of Bowker’s lat- [email protected] Editor-in-Chief est figures, we wanted to offer direct access to Indieland’s finest. Look TOM BEER for excerpts in various genres, like a scene from Margaret F. Chen’s eerie [email protected] Vice President of Marketing short story collection, Suburban Gothic, and in-depth conversations with SARAH KALINA several authors, including Esther Amini, who talks about Concealed, her [email protected] memoir of growing up as a Jewish Iranian immigrant. And, since it’s been Managing/Nonfiction Editor ERIC LIEBETRAU one of our worst, most isolating, stressful years, we checked in with Indie [email protected] authors; here’s how they coped with 2020-2021. Fiction Editor LAURIE MUCHNICK During the lockdown, author and beekeeper J.H. Ramsay joined an [email protected] online network of writers and artists, and he completed his SF debut, Young Readers’ Editor VICKY SMITH Predator Moons.
    [Show full text]
  • Performing Murder and Metaphor Language, Literature, And
    Language, Literature, and Interdisciplinary Studies (LLIDS) ISSN: 2457-0044 Performing Murder and Metaphor Red Herrings and the Knowledge of the World in The Hound of Baskerville and The Murder of Roger Ackroyd Ritwick Bhattacharjee And then, in correcting the proofs, we notice some misconstructions, some oddities... We send for Marana, we ask him some questions, he becomes confused, contradicts himself.... We press him, we open the original text in front of him and request him to translate a bit orally.... He confesses he doesn't know a single word of Cimbrian! -Italo Calvino The Webster dictionary defines a red herring as “something unimportant that is used to stop people from noticing or thinking about something important”. This definition of a red herring as a mere distraction, however, fails at delineating the philosophy of red herrings, especially in its form of and as a literary device. Considering red herrings as sign systems then, the current paper seeks to outline a paradigm to understand not only the world of and around red herrings in a novel but also the subjectivities that both control and are controlled because of red herrings. Since red herrings are primarily deployed in detective fiction, the paper uses Sir Arthur Conan Doyle’s The Hound of Baskervilles and Agatha Christie’s The Murder of Roger Ackroyd to both create the aforementioned theoretical paradigm and chart out a tradition of red herrings as it has been passed from Doyle to Christie. Before a consideration of detective fictions, it seems fitting to discuss in brief Italo Calvino’s If On a Winter’s Night a Traveler because it exemplifies the philosophical complexities of red herrings in its entirety.
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Fallacies: Don’T Do Them Sure, Looking at What to Do Is Helpful, but Sometimes Looking at What Not to Do Can Be of Even Greater Help
    Logical Fallacies: Don’t Do Them Sure, looking at what to do is helpful, but sometimes looking at what not to do can be of even greater help. So, what shouldn’t you do while debating or making an argument? In general, while debating or making an argument, don’t commit the following logical ​ fallacies: ​ ● Ad hominem: a latin term meaning “against the man.” It’s when you attack the person ​ behind the argument rather than the argument itself. ● Straw man: when you argue against a point that the opponent doesn’t actually hold. ● Slippery slope: an argument where you suppose, since A is allowed, eventually Z will happen. ○ Example: Certain people who align with alt-right American politics argue that because American liberals have pushed for laws defending homosexual marriage, eventually they will push for laws that defend pedophilia. ● Appeal to authority: The idea that something must be true because an authority said it. ● Texas sharpshooter: when you twist the data or numbers to argue something they don’t by ignoring the differences while stressing the similarities. ● Appeal to novelty: because an argument is newer, it’s better. ● Hasty generalization: making assumptions or stereotyping a group based on inconclusive or unreliable evidence. ● Red herring: a distraction from the central focus of the debate or argument. ○ Example: In a paper you argue the following: “The Society of Jesus’s doctrine of Finding God in All Things, and the Kuyperian doctrine of Sphere Sovereignty share multiple theological principles… (and you would put the principles here).” In this paper, you would want to stick to the theological principles that the two Christian traditions share, it would be inappropriate to write an entire page on St.
    [Show full text]