<<

North American Philosophical Publications

Recent Work on Author(s): Guy Axtell Source: American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 34, No. 1 (Jan., 1997), pp. 1-26 Published by: University of Illinois Press on behalf of the North American Philosophical Publications Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20009883 Accessed: 03-11-2016 12:31 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms

North American Philosophical Publications, University of Illinois Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to American Philosophical Quarterly

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms American Philosophical Quarterly Volume 34, Number 1, January 1997

RECENT WORK ON

Guy Axtell

I. Introduction influential articles on different aspects of the epistemology/ethics analogy by William A he period of a dozen years since Gregory Alston (1978), Roderick Firth (1978, Pence's APQ review article on "Recent 1981), Jonathan Dancy (1982), Richard Work on " (1984) has witnessed Feldman (1988) and Matthias Steup continued interest in , its rela? (1988). Issues of the voluntariness of be? tionships with normative ethics and action lief and of the distinction between theory, and the opposition between aretaic, and acceptance are pertinent here, but it is consequentialist, and deontological ethics. a mistake to see any of these meta-episte It has also witnessed something Pence mological accounts as dependent upon could hardly have anticipated: the signifi? doxastic voluntarism.2 That this objection cant development of versions of aretaic or misses the point is made especially clear virtue epistemology. An intellectual vir? on the "pragmatic" accounts of intellectual tue is a cognitive disposition utilized or virtue such as those of Hookway (1994) exercised in the formation of beliefs. and Zagzebski (1996), where the focus is Giving intellectual virtues a central ex? on human inquiry, a kind of activity, and planatory role in epistemology is not of where the primary focus of evaluation is course entirely a novel idea, since recent shifted from the act or belief to the agents' work in virtue epistemology (hereafter VE) character traits. On such accounts the jus? has occurred in concert with renewed in? tifiability of beliefs is derivative, and the terest in the role of intellectual virtue in emphasis is on epistemic evaluations made 's epistemology. Reliabilist ver? in the context of inquiry.3 sions of VE are its best-known extant Dancy notes that, like the terms already versions, and reliabilist VE has also dove? mentioned, "internalism" and "externalism" tailed with renewed interest in Thomas entered epistemology through analogy with Reid's faculty-centered epistemology the long-standing use of those terms in eth? (Lehrer, 1989). ics.4 The method for this carry-over is today are often charac? analogical and not reductive. The concern terized by terms such as aretaic, deonto? that it not be reductive is evident in reti? logical, and consequentialist (specifically, cence over the use of the long-standing 'epistemic rule-utilitarian').1 This lan? term "," which for some guage has moved into epistemology rather brings to mind such connotations (dis? swiftly, given initial impetus by several cussed in Firth 1978; Code, 1987). Others

1

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 2 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

who do adopt the idea of an ethics of The most developed accounts of virtue belief in discussions of normative episte? epistemology are Ernest Sosa's virtue mology are at pains to show that their use perspectivism, developed in articles many is not reductionistic of epistemology of which are collected in his (Zagzebski 1996). The analogical method in Perspective (1991 ; hereafter KIP), and has been perceived as greatly expanding 's historical , the resources of epistemologists by open? the VE version of which is developed pri? ing up useful channels for comparison and marily in "Epistemic Folkways and contrast of epistemological theories. Still, Scientific Epistemology," contained in Li? its use exhibited initial drawbacks as well, aisons (1992; hereafter LI). There have due to overgeneralizations about the rela? also been other book-length treatments and tive "maturity" of the two fields, and about a growing number of articles and reviews. In order to cast attention on the division what "results" in ethics could be unprob lematically assumed (Dancy, 1992; 1993). between "reliabilist" and "responsibilist" versions of VE, I will discuss Lorraine Virtues and skills are subtly different traits, but to attribute either of them to a Code's Epistemic Responsibility (1987), James Montmarquet's subject requires dispositions that are not andDoxastic Responsibility (1993), and ar? fleeting and have a significant degree of ticles by John Greco, Christopher Hookway character-stability; action instancing or and Hilary Kornblith. Of special interest manifesting ethical virtue, and belief mani? here is 's Virtues of the festing intellectual virtue, are for this Mind (1996), the most extensive develop? reason explanatorily useful. The virtues are ment to date of a unified conception of ethical also closely related to normative or evalu? and intellectual virtue. ative questions. Virtues are dispositional Reliabilism and responsibilism were states of character or inner nature con? both, of course, options in epistemology ceptually bound up with the good, and before the appearance of their explicitly their attribution to agents as motivations virtue-centered versions. What I will call contributing to actions we perform, or con? virtue reliabilism emerged as a develop? tributing to the formation and acceptance ment within externalist approaches to of beliefs, may also reflect praise or blame knowledge, which themselves developed upon us. The virtues thus serve both de? mainly in response to the "Gettier-type scriptive/explanatory and normative/ problem" and the challenge it presented to evaluative tasks; and it is incumbent upon the model of knowledge as "true justified the naturalistic virtue theorist (as upon any belief." Responsibilism, as an account of form of 'normative naturalism') to both justified belief, has also been well-repre? keep these tasks logically separated and yet sented in the post-Gettier era. Following to give an account, through the concept of Sosa's initial sketch of a virtue-centered virtue, of their relationship. Making this epistemology in his influential 1980 article, demand is really to burden the virtue theo? "The Raft and the Pyramid," epistemic rist with the daunting task of an account 'virtue-talk' was next picked up in a of the place of normativity in a naturalis? responsibilist context by Heil (1983) and tic world view; but it is surely no more Kornblith (1983). Code's book, which I daunting than the burdens of explanation will describe as the first explicit version that fall on either "eliminative" naturalists of virtue responsibilism, draws, as she or on non-naturalists of different stripes. clearly acknowledges, both from previous

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RECENT WORK ON VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY / 3 responsibilist thought in ethics and episte? bringing in a specific focus on the explana? mology, and from Sosa's articles of the tory strategies employed in each kind. early and mid-1980's (1987, p. 50). Yet While there remains disagreement over already in her work, and even more so in whether goals or motivations have episte? responses to it, the tension between mic primacy, she emphasizes that "In virtue reliabilist and responsibilist conceptions of ethics, the concept of a virtue has almost intellectual virtue is readily apparent always combined internally accessible and (Haack, 1991; BonJour 1990). internally inaccessible criteria for its pos? Clearly, there is some close connection session" (p. 331). The epistemic correlates between responsibilism and internalism, of this conception, embodied in her "dual since one objection to externalism rests on component" account of intellectual virtue, the intuition that the main requirement of can be compared in section IV with virtue epistemic justification is that acceptance reliabilist strategies for avoiding the ex? of a belief is rational or responsible in re? tremes of epistemic externalism and lation to our cognitive goal or goals internalism. I begin by canvassing the ex? (BonJour 1992). We here take the pri? tant forms of VE through the recent work mary sense of the internalism/externalism by its leading proponents and the objec? contrast to be over the connection or "bas? tions of their critics. ing" relationship between a belief and its II. Virtue-Reliabilism adequate grounds; internalism asserts, while externalism denies, that this relation The association of 's should be available to the agent upon in? proper functionalism with VE is tenuous trospective reflection (Kim, 1993).5 As at best, and we begin with it here only in a matter of orientation toward one's own order to pass quickly on to those who ex? knowledge-seeking self, responsibility re? plicitly endorse VE. This association is due quires an introspective capacity (Code, both to the identification of VE with fac? 1987). But whether this makes our two ulty-based reliabilism, and to the place of extant forms of VE irreconcilable is some? ergon in Aristotle's account of the virtues. thing we will have to investigate in the In "Proper Functionalism and Virtue Epis? context of their specific construals of in? temology" (1993), in which Sosa outlines tellectual virtue and epistemic justification. his outstanding differences with Plantinga The contrast of virtue reliabilism and and with the Goldman of "Epistemic Folk? virtue responsibilism (the latter term is ways," he concludes that the disagreements suggested by Goldman) is not intended to between the three "seem relatively small, be exhaustive of possible forms of VE; yet when compared with the large areas of even though there have been few direct agreement, [and] it seems appropriate to exchanges between these groups, it recog? view the three approaches as varieties of a nizes one significant manner in which those single more fundamental option in episte? doing work within VE mark differences mology, one which puts the explicative among themselves. Zagzebski's distinc? emphasis on -conducive intellectual tion between two forms of pure virtue virtues or faculties, and is properly termed theory, the "good-based" and the "agent 'virtue epistemology'" (KIP p. 64). based," drawn in part from Michael Slote's I have already sounded a warning about work (1996), significantly overlaps with the narrowness of simply identifying VE my own distinction between virtue reliabil? with its reliabilist versions and will have ism and virtue perspectivism, while more to say about this later. The point here

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 4 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

is that while Goldman explicitly endorses "perspective" on the reliable source of his Sosa's term "virtue epistemology" (LI p. beliefs, and Goldman uses the lack of 157), Plantinga refuses the identification. match between the causal process and vir? Goldman adopts the term as an alternative tues on the typical epistemic evaluators description of the view that he develops in "list" of virtues. Plantinga argues against "Epistemic Folkways," which modifies his the satisfactoriness of these alternative ac? previous views, identified as "historical or counts and concludes that ". . . insofar as genetic reliabilism" (p. 117); his current an epistemic virtue is an epistemic faculty, version of VE adds what he thinks are Sosa's virtue epistemology is really a va? "some distinctive features that improve its riety of proper functionalism" (1993c, p. 81). [V?"s] prospects." Plantinga, however, re? There appear to be still unresolved prob? sponds to Sosa's "irenic conclusion" by lems here in how to separate virtue inverting the suggested relationship be? reliabilism from proper functionalism. tween proper functionalism and VE. But given this sharp rebuttal to Sosa on The point is not just that the emphasis Plantinga's part, together with the obvious on truth-conducive faculties is qualified in fact that Plantinga nowhere makes central different ways by the two, to make room use of descriptions of epistemic warrant or for the role of "design" in Plantinga's case epistemic agents in terms of intellectual and "epistemic perspective" in Sosa's. The virtues, I will not pursue his recent devel? notions of design plan and proper function opment of proper functionalism or his are "correlative" for Plantinga, and proper extensive work on warrant (1993a; 1993b). function can't be separated, as he finds Sosa's specific form of VE is called vir? Sosa trying to do, from "functioning in ac? tue perspectivism. According to Sosa, "the cordance with imposed design." Though view I defend involves two main elements: his definition of the virtues is functional the concept of an intellectual virtue, and teleological, Sosa rejects the need for a the concept of an epistemic perspective. theological or even evolutionary account Roughly, a cognitive faculty or intellectual of the notion of "design" is order to under? virtue is a competence to distinguish the stand a properly ordered faculty (compare true from the false in some field of propo? KIP p. 282). sitions F when in certain circumstances C" Plantinga uses a well-known example of (1994c). This truth-linked conception of a brain lesion victim whose lesion happens intellectual virtue, where virtues are in? to reliably produce true beliefs. Proper grained dispositions that lead to a pre? function tied to design plan gives an ex? ponderance of over falsehoods, is planation of why the lesion produces, strongly analogous to the conception of accidentally though reliably, true beliefs, moral virtues as dispositions that reliably and hence saves the intuition that the vic? promote the good. Placing beliefs in epi? tim is unjustified in his beliefs. Can these stemic perspective means taking note of the intuitions be saved on a "weaker" account sources of one's first-order beliefs and of that foregoes the notion of design plan? In? how reliable these sources are in different tellectual virtues will not provide a fully kinds of circumstances, say, of lighting and satisfactory account of the difference be? distance for beliefs based on the faculty of tween accidentality and non-accidentality visual . if they are simply defined through their Sosa characterizes virtue perspectivism truth-conduciveness. To supplement, as "a type of generic reliabilism," while Sosa uses the idea of the agent's lack of recognizing that reliabilism "comes in a

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RECENT WORK ON VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY / 5 great variety of types most of which are justified in his beliefs. Hence the upshot clearly unacceptable."6 The modifications is that the reliabilists' conditions are too virtue perspectivism makes to generic weak, that is, not sufficient for the justi? fication of belief. reliabilism are set in part by the problem of the "accidental reliability" of belief 3) the "Generality Problem" alleges a producing mechanisms or processes. Here, problem for reliabilists in the specifica? as a start, the virtue reliabilist tries to rule tion of reliable processes. If taken too out random and ad hoc processes by re? narrowly, the argument runs, such pro? quiring that justified beliefs be generated cesses show themselves not to be neces? by a genuine capacity or competence to sary for justification; and if taken too arrive at truth, identifying these with in? broadly, then they may be necessary but tellectual virtue. But this will hardly are also shown insufficient. This places suffice to mark differences with other a specific demand on virtue reliabilists forms of generic reliabilism, and so we to provide a specification of a faculty or must turn to the context of at least three virtue that is neither so specific that ev? additional problems that Sosa builds his ery true belief is credited to a reliable account around. These problems, usually faculty, nor so broad that a single fac? posed by internalists, should be understood ulty generates beliefs that seem to have as primarily directed against "the combi? different epistemic statuses (compare nation of reliabilism as a theory of Hookway, 1994). justification with a conception of knowl? We can use the context of these problems edge as justified true belief" (KIP, p. 244). as background for sketching some of the Very briefly, they are the following: distinctions that Sosa sees as giving virtue perspectivism substantial advantages over 1) the "New Evil Demon Problem" poses other forms of generic reliabilism (see also cases of systematic deception or whole? BonJour 1992): sale falsehood (including brain-in-vat Virtue perspectivism distinguishes between cases). Here it is claimed that the aptness and justification of belief, where a reliabilist's conditions on justification do belief is apt if it derives from a faculty or not fit our intuitions, which seem to side virtue, but is justified only if it fits coher? with the subject being justified in her be? liefs despite the unreliability (in the ently within the epistemic perspective of the demon world) of the process that pro? believer ?perhaps by being connected to duced them. The upshot of the argument adequate reasons in the mind of the believer is to show that reliabilist requirements in such a way that the believer follows ad? on epistemic justification are too strong, equate or even impeccable intellectual that is, not necessary for the justifica? procedure . . . tion of belief. Virtue perspectivism distinguishes between 2) the "Meta-Incoherence Problem" poses animal and reflective knowledge. For ani? cases such as that of a person with a mal knowledge one needs only belief that reliable belief-producing faculty of clair? is apt and derives from an intellectual vir? voyance, yet unaware of her own faculty. tue or faculty. By contrast, reflective The conditions generic reliabilism places knowledge always requires belief that not on justification would here seem to be only is apt but also has a kind of justifica? met; yet the reliabilist analysis again tion, since it must be belief that fits does not fit our intuitions, if we agree coherently within the epistemic perspective these tell us that the clairvoyant is not of the believer (KIP, p. 145).7

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 6 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

Animal knowledge may be treated in beliefs are justified (her beliefs may be as more strictly reliabilist fashion. Animal coherent as ours from her epistemic per? knowledge is exemplified in an agent's di? spective); yet it also shows why she lacks rect response to its environment, through knowledge ?her beliefs do not derive from perception or memory, for example, with faculties that are apt relative to her demon little or no benefit of reflection or under? world. Her epistemic perspective, though standing. But virtue perspectivism places coherent, "is pervaded by falsehood con? requirements of justification on reflective cerning the supposed virtues or faculties knowledge, and these requirements have a by appeal to which [she] explains [her] be? clear internalist character to them. "For liefs (and concerning much else besides)" reflective knowledge one not only must (KIP p. 281). believe out of virtue. One must also be The related distinction between animal aware of doing so. Of course one need not and reflective knowledge is used heavily know with precision and detail the relevant in connection with the latter two problems, C and F. Some grasp of them is required, though I reserve comment on the general? however, even if it remains sketchy and ity problem until the next section. Sosa's generic" (1994c). reply to the meta-incoherence problem can Sosa shows in these passages that he is save the intuition that the clairvoyant is not attempting to "solve" the above prob? unjustified. Despite the reliability of the lems in favor of a strictly reliabilist clairvoyant's special faculty, "he can be account of both knowledge and justifica? seen as subjectively unjustified through tion. Reliabilism well-begun leads to lack of an appropriate perspective on his , and perspectivism is pre? belief: either because he positively takes sented as Sosa's form of coherentism (KIP the belief to be ill-formed, or because he p. 97). "Pure" reliabilism is rejected in 'ought' to take it to be ill-formed given his favor of an account with mixed reliabilist total picture of things, and given the cog? and coherentist elements, for each con? nitive processes available to him" (p. 134). tain insights that need to be integrated in We have seen that Sosa's virtue per? an account of justification. Reliabilism is spectivism makes significant concessions centrally present in justification through its to coherentism and incorporates internalist focus on faculties or virtues; but internal elements in its account of justification. The justification is largely a matter of compre? "argumentative" or agent-reasons concep? hensive coherence. The basic distinction tion of justification is well-ensconced in underlying virtue perspectivism, then, is common language, and eliminating the ar? "my distinction between externalist, reli? gumentative account altogether, as in a ability-bound aptness and internalist, strictly reliabilist account of justification, rationality-bound justification" (1995). seems "drastic" to Sosa. To this extent his It will be impossible for us to do more epistemology is quite irenic. Yet it retains here than to indicate in the briefest fash? a strongly reliabilist orientation. Cases of ion how Sosa's virtue perspectivism animal and human children's knowledge, addresses the three problems in KIP and as externalists have emphasized, show a more recent articles (see also BonJour 1992 sense in which justification is not even and 1995). The aptness/justification dis? necessary for some kinds of knowledge. tinction is used in his treatment of the new Yielding justification and its cognate terms evil-demon problem. This distinction to the argumentative account "requires in helps save the intuition that the victim's turn that justification be demoted from its

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RECENT WORK ON VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY / 7

position as principal concept of episte? "two-tiered" (Goldman) or "stratified" mology" (p. 255). The justification/aptness (Sosa) character.8 Among their many dif? distinction, or the "split" between two ferences, however, I will focus on three senses of justification (subjective and ob? areas that will remain important in rela? jective) as Sosa sometimes alternatively tion to our later discussion of objections puts it, makes questions of externalist, reli? to virtue reliabilism. ability-bound aptness epistemically primary. 1. The relativization of justification. Further clarification of virtue reliabilism Sosa treats justification and aptness as can be gained by comparing Sosa's virtue "indexical" terms and distinguishes same perspectivist account with Alvin Goldman's world and actual-world justification: "S is recent writings. Intellectual borrowing has 'same-world justified' in world W in be? gone both directions between these two, lieving P if S P in W in virtue of a but Goldman's "Epistemic Folkways" faculty that in W is truth conducive. S is notes a clear debt to Sosa's KIP for the 'actual-world justified' in world W in be? virtue-centered approach he now takes in lieving P if S believes P in W in virtue of a comparison to that of his Epistemology and faculty that in our actual world a is truth Cognition (1986). Goldman's approach conducive" (1995). Goldman rejects is unique in its focus on the "psychology Sosa's relativization of aptness and justi? of the epistemic evaluator" (the "folk" as fication to environment, because "there is evaluators) rather than on the epistemic no evidence that 'the folk' are inclined to agent. This also places emphasis on the relativize virtues and vices to this or that role of exemplars of virtue and vice as op? possible world" (1992, pp. 161). This dif? posed to mere definitions or abstract ference also affects the way that each goes characterizations, and on the mentally about handling counter-examples given in stored set or "list" of cognitive virtues and the "possible worlds" semantics of modal vices that reflective epistemic evaluators . Goldman developed what is known are assumed to hold. The tasks of episte? as "normal worlds reliabilism," but later mology include not just stating abstract abandoned it partly due to the reasoning conditions of justification but also show? above. He now tries to handle such cases ing what psychological processes are without relativizing, mostly by use of the conducive to justification. Goldman's at? "weak/strong justification" distinction dis? tention to a broad range of cognitive and cussed in (3) below. social scientific studies is exceptional, un? 2. Doxastic Ascent. Sosa traces his meta derlining the concern of virtue theory that belief requirements on justification to "the normative ethics and epistemology be challenge of doxastic ascent," the chal? based upon the best current theories of ac? lenge, incumbent on the reflective knower, tual human motivational capacities (1993a; to have a certain amount of self-knowledge 1993b). Epistemology for Goldman is di? about his faculties (though not about non vided between the descriptive and the introspectable mechanisms). Without this prescriptive, and also between individual self-knowledge, we could not discriminate epistemology, representing 's in favor of memory and against suddenly interaction with cognitive science, and endowed clairvoyance. We might come to , representing its rela? learn that we can rely on the latter faculty tionship with the social sciences. As with as we normally do on the former, but a kind Sosa, the reliabilist orientation of the ac? of doxastic ascent is just what consti? count of justification is shown by its tutes such learning (KIP, p. 95). Virtue

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 8 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY perspectivism acknowledges this challenge, (1992; 1993a; 1993b), which assaults a but many other forms of generic reliabilism thesis he identifies not only with virtue do not. Goldman challenges the idea that perspectivism, but indeed with a majority epistemic evaluators have or require meta of "iterative" epistemologies today, both beliefs about the sources of their own internalist and externalist. "There is no beliefs. This is also said to be based on role for a status of perspectival belief in description of "epistemic folkways." Just epistemology on his view, which holds as the folk are unlikely to relativize justi? perspectivism to present a confusion be? fication to environment, they are unlikely tween a belief's being justified and a to have (or to hold upon reflection) the kind believer being justified (1993, p. 27). Pro? of metabeliefs that Sosa makes requisite ponents of perspectivist epistemologies for justification in the case of beliefs that would disagree with Schmitt's claim that count as reflective knowledge. they fail to account for that distinction, and 3. The seat of justification. We have we have also seen Sosa reject a related seen that the features Goldman develops claim Schmitt makes, that pure reliabilism to improve the prospects of virtue relia? and pure coherentism are the only viable bilism include his psychological starting accounts of justification. We will later point with the epistemic evaluator, and his touch upon a further contrast of aretaic "list" proposal with its connection to an theory with Schmitt's deontological account.9 exemplar approach to concept representa? In a review of KIP, Schmitt also argues tion. For his part, Sosa distinguishes virtue that Sosa's virtue perspectivism is both too perspectivism from deontological episte? strong and too weak (compare Greco mology, as well as from "truth tracking" 1993a). It is seen as too weak to the ex? (Nozick), from "reliable process" tent that it lacks an account of the (Goldman), and from "reliable indicator" (Armstrong, Swain) versions of relia? appropriate causal connections between the bilism. None of these other approaches, perceptual faculty and the belief (relying he argues, satisfactorily allows the subject instead on the notion of "exercising" the her place as the seat of justification: virtue of faculty). It is seen as too strong to the extent that one might think of cases When we praise a performance as skillful or an action as right, or a judgment as wise where a belief-forming process is reliable or apt . . . we speak not only of the perfor? but does not constitute a. stable disposition mance or the action or the judgment, but in the agent (1993a). Schmitt has in mind also of the agent or the subject and of the here cases similar to what aptitude of character or intelligence that is (1993) calls the case of the "inconstant reflected in what they did or thought. . . . knower," one who is generally a sloppy That seems a rather distinctive type of view reasoner but on occasion atypically reasons that one can plausibly hold both in episte? impeccably well. Would virtue reliabilism mology and in ethics. . . . The virtue deny him knowledge on this occasion be? epistemology and the virtue ethics suggested here place the emphasis rather on the agent cause the disposition to reason in this way and cognizer (1994c). is not stable for him? (compare Sosa's KIP, Ch.16). III. Objections to Virtue Reliabilism In one recent exchange, Sosa responds to critiques made by Richard Fumerton The broadest contemporary critique of (1994) and by Richard Foley (1994). perspectivism is that of Frederick Schmitt Fumerton objects to Sosa's reliance on

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RECENT WORK ON VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY / 9

coherence in his account of epistemic have coherent "meta-beliefs" about the justification and to his conception of the mechanisms giving rise to our beliefs, and environment-relative reliability of faculties the fields and conditions under which or virtues. More specifically, he queries those mechanisms are reliable. Sosa's vir? Sosa over how he intends to formulate and tue perspectivism "require[s] that one have analyze the truth conditions of the sub? reason to think one's first order beliefs true, junctive conditionals that define the since it requires that first order beliefs be faculties on this account (see KIP, p. 284). placed in 'epistemic perspective,' where one takes note of the sources of one's be? Fumerton finds the additional problem that, if virtues are defined relative to environ? liefs (of the first order ones, at a minimum) ment, it becomes exceedingly difficult to and of how reliable these are" (1995). resist specifying the virtue in so narrow a Foley finds it dubious that many of us have way that we are impaled on the first horn the required degree of awareness of the of the generality problem, that is, "to in? bases of our own reliability. In this Foley sure trivially virtuous belief relative to the disagrees with Sosa over the degree of environment we pick." Sosa's response is awareness required, insisting that the logic of the accidental reliability problem must to be found in the condition that one pick drive Sosa to something more than the one's description of the environment (rela? "sketchy" awareness or inferential habit tive to which one judges the virtue of a that the latter finds sufficient for ordinary belief-forming process) in such a way that reflective knowledge.10 the resulting judgements are useful. "The Sosa's way of responding is to say that likely solution lies in allowing only Fs and we must not assign stronger perspectival Cs appropriately usable by us for reason? requirements than are likely to be met in able generalizations about our intellectual ordinary cases (1994c). His discussion of aptitudes" (KIP, p. 291). But Fumerton "inferential habits" as implicit beliefs is a argues we need something closer to a provocative one with Aristotelian connec? probabilistic connection between the con? tions, though we cannot pursue it here. ditions that produce a belief and the "Sketchy awareness" of the source of first resulting belief's being true (see also order beliefs (sight, hearing, smell, etc.) Fumerton 1995). The subjunctive condi? goes together with minimal requirements, tionals defining the truth-conducive where we have attained an awareness of faculties or virtues underlying the episte? our tendency to be right in a field under mic virtues "should be made true by certain conditions, and have reasoned that probabilistic laws." this tendency is not a mere accident. Re? Foley questions what he sees as essen? flective awareness comes in degrees, but tially pragmatic reasons ? why we care reasoning in such a way is essential to our about justification and reliability, or the ability to "bootstrap" ourselves to a higher 'usefulness' thesis mentioned above ? level of self-conscious awareness. We being taken as defining conditions of should avoid making the minimal condi? knowledge in virtue perspectivism (1994). tions for reflective knowledge too strict, These result in pragmatic and social con? on pain that little human knowledge will straints on knowledge to which he meet it; but normative epistemology retains objects. "Why we generally care about a legitimate interest in how greater self knowledge is one thing; its defining awareness contributes to the comprehen? characteristics are something quite dif? siveness and coherence of our total body ferent." He also questions whether we of beliefs.

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 10 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

There are of course also those who think that virtue perspectivism is caught in vicious any second-order or meta-belief require? circularity in its attempt to explicate ment for justification must be resisted on higher-order justification for metabeliefs in pain of launching an infinite regress. But terms of the notion of "broad coherence." KIP argues strenuously against that view. I will pursue this line of thought through I would suggest Sosa's requirement might the more recent exchange between Sosa be regarded as the epistemic correlate of and Laurence BonJour (1995). the first of Aristotle's three requirements Bonjour acknowledges certain advan? for actions from virtue (at NE 1105a29ff), tages in Sosa's treatment of the three the requirement of a "recognitional" capac? aforementioned problems for generic ity. This requirement, according to reliabilism but points to continuing diffi? Aristotle, is necessary for the reflective culties with his responses to them. A fourth agent's being "in the right state" ?prop? problem he develops is one that he erly attuned to his environment or properly acknowledge's Sosa has himself identified affected by it.n Audi ( 1995) and Sherman and tried to address: how is the reliabilist (1989) provide insightful analyses on to identify his reliable sources of belief and Aristotle's conditions on action from virtue. justify the claim that they are reliable, with? Alston is among those who argue that out relying on those very sources in a there is a problem of epistemic circularity viciously circular way? Here he develops that is fatal to reliabilism, virtue reliabilism a dilemma for Sosa: included ( 1991 ). Our j udgment of the re? Either the appeal to internal coherence can liability of the faculties cannot itself be somehow, perhaps when coupled with fur? justified non-circularly. To claim that if a. ther internal elements of some sort, provide faculty is reliable, it can be shown so em? a genuinely cogent reason for thinking that pirically, by a track record argument for one's perspectival beliefs ... are likely to be true, or it cannot. On the former alter? instance, requires the acceptance of pre? native, as Sosa himself seems to suggest, mises which beg the question against the the appeal to external reliability is, as it skeptic.12 But if one abandons justifica? were, absorbed by the appeal to perspectival tion on empirical grounds in favor of 'the coherence and seems to have no indepen? coherence of reliability,' a similar circu? dent justificatory function. But on the latter larity problem emerges. As Paul Moser alternative, which I believe to be the one puts this objection, coherence of mere be? that Sosa actually holds, the internal epi? liefs appears incapable of providing non stemic perspective turns out to be itself question-begging support for the alleged unjustified, and hence the reason for thinking reliability of the faculties. Vicious episte? that virtue perspectivism is an improvement mic circularity rears its head: "the circle over crude reliabilism is apparently lost seems swift and unbreakable" (Moser (1995, p. 220). 1991; Sosa 1994a). According to BonJour, none of the alter? Moser's objection seems to strike espe? natives open to the virtue perspectivist cially at Sosa's perspectivist form of virtue yields a clear account of how the perspec? reliabilism. Assuming that I do at least tival beliefs can be epistemically justified have meta-beliefs about the sources of my without at the same time threatening to beliefs, what can effectively justify these undercut the basic externalist thrust of metabeliefs? Questions such as this have virtue perspectivism. His own "qualified been the basis for the single most perva? coherentist" position is considerably closer sive objection leveled at Sosa, the objection to the first alternative offered, but he is

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RECENT WORK ON VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY / 11 correct that Sosa rejects the idea that the work on it has centered around his concept internal justification of perspectival beliefs of "broad coherence" and its foundationa is entirely a matter of their internal coher? list, coherentist, and reliabilist aspects. ence. Is he also right that no 'mixed' view The actual aptness of our beliefs lies be? can possibly provide reasons for the agent yond us. Ultimately, it is the reliability of to think that his perspectival beliefs are true? coherence and not the coherence of reli? We cannot get waylaid long by questions ability that must be taken as fundamental of skepticism or we will not get all of the in what is itself the more fundamental ques? day's chores completed. But since I have tion, that of actual aptness or successful not pursued in any depth Sosa's responses fit between our faculties and the world. It to the objections raised earlier, I will offer is a confusion to insist that we "go norma? a thin sketch of his strategy concerning this tive" to find a higher criterion justifying skeptical challenge (which is how BonJour our initial trust; that demand is surely con? himself addresses it). This strategy is akin fused and can result only in our then to that of , whose approach demanding in turn logical or factual sup? also combined elements of naturalism, port for that criterion, and a vicious circle , and coherentism. The re? is assured. We cannot "justify" such reli? sponse to the skeptic is based on a ability a priori, but only look from an a fundamental meta-principle of the trust? posteriori and inductive position for how worthiness of the innate human faculties. well or poorly our beliefs and their prag? Trust in these faculties is theoretically a matic success support our initial trust in principle of reasonableness or intelligibil? the reliability of our cognitive faculties. ity and pragmatically a prerequisite for Other connections to Sosa's approach avoiding skepticism. Sosa has never re? could be brought to bear. Schmitt rightly ally denied the presence of epistemic points out that the kind of skepticism in circularity, only its viciousness. The de? question is Humean antecedent skepticism, fense of the reliability of any one faculty which "rests on the assumption, not only will depend upon assumption of the reli? that justified belief requires exercising a ability of others, and this alone is enough reliable process, but that it requires & guar? to establish that there is no non-circular antee of the reliability of the process" guarantee of reliability. But does rational? (1992, p. 6). But ironically, where Schmitt ity require such a guarantee? sees antecedent skepticism deriving from Certainly not all internalists agree with an unholy combination of reliabilism and this, since some agree with reliabilists in access internalism, John Greco's articles seeing this demand as a confusion of the on VE indicate that this same "mixed" ap? state and the activity of justification. But proach provides just the right grounds for Sosa says that BonJour, and in a some? a non-question-begging reply to the what different context Alston and Moser skeptic (1992; 1993a;1993b;1994). as well, labor under assumptions about Greco's "relevant possibilities" approach justification of perspectival beliefs that to antecedent skepticism argues that "a no epistemology could satisfy. This possibility is relevant if it is true in some assumption amounts basically to a demand close possible world, irrelevant if it is "for a fully general, legitimating" philo? not. This proposal explains many of our sophical account of human knowledge, pre-theoretical intuitions about which something that Sosa wants to reject as a possibilities need to be ruled out, and misplaced and unfulfillable ideal. His own which do not, in order to know, and it

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 12 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY explains why the skeptical possibilities do Cognition remains "structural" through its not need to be ruled out" (1994, p. 63). emphasis on the arrangement of human The skeptic uses evil-demon cases as pos? knowledge, and not genuinely genetic. sibilities inconsistent with my knowing, The use of virtue-talk in the service of a and so implicitly insists that they be ruled Cartesian epistemological project is seen out in order for my claims to knowledge as self-undermining. It would be interest? to be justified. This is essentially the same ing to see Kvanvig's arguments for this "guarantee demand" in other language, and directed specifically to Sosa. For Sosa Greco's approach, while it depends on dif? does describe virtue perspectivism as ficult distinctions like that between close "structurally Cartesian"; virtue perspectiv? and non-close worlds, provides a well-di? ism depicts epistemic agents as in much rected approach to undermining it. the same position as Descartes in respect Moreover, on Greco's account the "rel? to our need to use broad coherence to se? cure our trust in the senses and to defend evant possibility approach to skepticism and virtue epistemology are mutually-supportive": against skeptical doubts (1995). There re? mains potential for a central role of the If knowledge essentially involves cognitive virtues in epistemology, but it is in the abilities and if abilities are dispositions to achieve results across close possible worlds, alternative epistemological project then this explains why possibilities are rel? Kvanvig characterizes as socially and ge? evant only when they are true in some close netically oriented, in contrast to the individualistic and structural orientation possible world. Specifically, only such pos? sibilities as these can undermine one's of Cartesian epistemology. Kvanvig's cognitive abilities. In an environment where robust "social perspective" illustrates deception by demons is actual or probable, something of the potential of intellec? I lack the ability to reliably form true be? tual virtue-centered epistemologies to be liefs and avoid false beliefs. But if no such developed in diverse ways. demons exist in this world or similar ones, It is worth noting that most proponents they do not affect my cognitive abilities of VE hold a substantial place for social (1994, p. 64). epistemology and a naturalistic commit? Jonathan Kvanvig's The Intellectual Virtues ment to the continuity of epistemology and and the Life of the Mind (1992) criticizes the special sciences. Yet Goldman has what he takes as the attempt to make the sometimes come under fire by social epis virtues serve a "Cartesian" epistemologi temologists (Fuller 1992 and 1996) and cal project, one based on methodological pyschologists of science (Heyes 1898) for individualism and a "time-slice" orienta? a rigid division of labor sometimes seen as inconsistent with the theme of Liai? tion for analyzing beliefs. This project attempts to explain the importance of the sons that epistemology should fear no intellectual borders. virtues solely in terms of the roles they are perceived to play in justification and IV. Virtue Responsibilism knowledge. Goldman's development of historical reliabilism was meant to contrast For both reliabilist and responsibilist VE, "current-time-slice" theories, but he is still the exercising of intellectual virtues is a prime target for Kvanvig, who holds that central to epistemic justification. These two "patching up" a Cartesian perspective in central branches of VE, however, display Goldman's way doesn't improve things. divergent interests in the normative and Goldman's account in Epistemology and causal-explanatory use of the intellectual

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RECENT WORK ON VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY / 13

virtues in epistemology. Reliabilists insist primary individual epistemics" (LI, p. 197). justification qua epistemic responsibility For Greco, intellectual virtues are "ground? is not sufficient for knowledge, while ed in conscientious belief formation and responsibilists insist it is at least necessary. maintenance, rather than in an unchanging The virtue reliabilist says we need an epis? nature" (1993a, p. 428). "We should . . . temology that does justice to the great amend the basic idea of VE, so that the diversity of genetic human capacities, as cognitive virtues which are relevant for brought out, for instance, by the unique? knowledge have their bases in the episte? ness of savants; the virtue responsibilist, mic responsibility of the knower" (1993a, meanwhile, says that we need an episte? p. 432). And Montmarquet wants to re? mology that does justice to the great strict the virtues to qualities of character, diversity of personal effort to secure truth for whose exercise or nonexercise we can (including levels of acquired skills of criti? plausibly be held responsible (praisewor? cal reasoning). While reliabilists worry thy or culpable). "I want to treat the about evil demons and ignorant clairvoy? epistemic virtues as, more narrowly, the ants, responsibilists worry that if we cannot counterparts of the moral virtues?and not assign epistemic culpability to a Hitler or just the counterparts of any personal a Mussolini for holding certain beliefs, we characteristic (e.g. intelligence) that may are on weak theoretic ground for judging be thought conducive to morally desir? him morally culpable for the acts premised able ends" (1993, p. x; compare 1987a on those beliefs. and 1987b). These and other related interests in the The motivations for these expressions of explanatory value of the virtues become virtue responsibilism are similar to those immediately evident in the divergent ways behind Code's Epistemic Responsibility, that reliabilists and responsibilists define where she argues that "epistemic respon? them.13 To the extent that VE is often sim? sibility is a central virtue from which other ply identified by the broader philosophical virtues radiate" (p. 44). While this book community with its faculty-centered, expresses no special affinities with femi? reliabilist form, the important issues raised nism, some of her more recent work, with by this division escape our critical eye. its continued emphasis on the virtues, When Sosa speaks of a "virtue or faculty," underlines the point that feminist episte? the phrase is essentially redundant, since mology often attempts to understand the the list he uses is a list divided between cognitive agent in ways informed by the generation faculties (perception, intuition, best attempts to understand moral agency introspection) and transmission faculties (Braaten, 1990; Dancy 1992). Her biggest (deduction, memory). When he speaks of departure from Sosa's views is in thinking the subject's stable "inner nature," it is con? of virtues as "accruing to their possessor strued in terms of these genetically-granted rather than to the faculties themselves, par? faculties, though many specific "habits" ticularly for the purpose of deriving that play a part in our cognitive processes attributions of epistemic responsibility are of course learned. from an individual's general, cognitive The virtue responsibilists reject an conduct. Such attributions are more ap? identification of virtue with either Sosa's propriately assigned to persons than to broad range of truth-conducive faculties, faculties" (1987, p. 57). or with the "natural or native processes" Peter Simpson (1992) argues that while that comprise for Goldman "the domain for contemporary virtue ethics benefits from

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 14 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

study of Aristotle, it is essentially novel in Some interesting objections to virtue a way that may even make even the de? reliabilism come to light through the vir? scription "neo-Aristotelian" problematic. tue responsibilist's criticism of the Some may say that this is all the more true "teleological" or "consequential" concep? of contemporary VE. All of our authors tion of intellectual virtue. On the one look to Aristotle for insight, but whether it hand, Montmarquet argues, the intellectual is co-opting Aristotle to use him as either virtues are important to goals not limited the virtue reliabilists or the virtue responsi? to the purely epistemic goal of truth. Con? bilists do is another question in itself, too forming to a virtue is not a quality broad to engage in here. What we can say derivative only from its quality of being is that each takes leave from Aristotle's truth conducive. On the other hand, iden? account of intellectual virtue, but in dif? tifying the unit of analysis with faculties ferent ways. The reliabilists broaden the given a genetic or biological gloss may be notion of virtue beyond dispositions logically arbitrary (1987b; 1993). This associatable with character, and if Dancy's latter objection can be related to one also made by Alston in relation to Sosa's ter? criticism is on target (1995), they also make minology, where "virtue" is used inter? truth a more simple or "unified" aim for the intellect than Aristotle himself in? changeably with "faculty," "power," and "ability." The three latter terms, Alston tended. The responsibilists, on the other points out, go together in that they may be hand, sometimes argue for far more sym? possessed by a subject even if infrequently metry between the true and the good than Aristotle's own account can bear. exercised; whereas a virtue is traditionally understood as "of the nature of habit." "It What supplies the degree of unity to the is a matter of what one would do under intellectual virtues needed to assure that certain conditions rather than of what one the use of the term does not pick out a mot? is able to do" (1993, pp. 202).15 ley crew? Is truth a unified end, by which Montmarquet asks, "Why introduce the the claims of various states of inner nature entire notion of an 'epistemic virtue' if this to be virtues are determinable? Virtue is not to place something like a special reliabilists answer the latter question af? normative role in one's epistemology?" firmatively; Sosa identifies this as "a (1993, p. x). The teleological account has teleological approach" to intellectual vir? difficulty doing justice to our intuition that tue, and finds support for this approach in a Newton and an Einstein may be roughly Aristotle's directly truth-linked account. equal in virtue, while far apart in terms of Truth-linkage is then also his answer to the truth. There is a distinction between the first question. Montmarquet, on the other progress of knowledge and the improve? hand, who rejects this teleological ap? ment of epistemic character, a distinction proach, attempts to provide an alternative which seems lost on the teleological ac? and more robust kind of unity for intellec? count. This sounds vaguely Kuhnian, and tual virtues through an epistemic analogue responsibilists may tend to see their of Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean.14 The problematic as that set by Kuhn: their "regulative function" of the intellect characterizations of intellectual virtues "represents a mean between two broadly make them akin to "cognitive values." The complementary types of epistemic virtues, importance of cognitive values seems lost those of impartiality and those of intellec? if we treat them as largely undifferentiated tual courage" (1993). "ampliative aspects" of coherence-seeking

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RECENT WORK ON VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY / 15 reason; they hold place in questions of surrounds this failure or that success: there choice present in the everyday course of will be a holistic aspect to our moral and our individual and communal lives. to our epistemic assessment" (1995, p. 203). Zagzebski acknowledges the teleological Through his characterization of the vir? or "good-based" account as one of two tue reliabilist account as an unhappy forms of "pure virtue theory," the other be? amalgam of aretaic and consequential rea? ing the "agent-based" account she herself soning, Dancy leads into a provocative favors. But "reliabilism is structurally par? discussion of underlying differences be? allel to consequentialism, not virtue tween contemporary meta-epistemological theory" (1996, p. 10). Even the explicitly approaches. This includes reasons for their virtue-based reliabilist epistemologies have mutual dissatisfaction with a Sosa-like this fault, because, she says, they have not "irenic solution." It is theoretically un? carefully enough considered the ethical stable, Dancy maintains, for a virtue theories from which they borrow. The result theorist to adopt a consequentialist picture is too weak a conception of responsibility, in a limited area. There can be no suit? because responsibility is viewed as deriva? able basis in this for a genuine aretaic tive from overt acts rather than motivations. of the relationship between

When epistemologists borrow moral concepts, beliefs from virtue and the virtues they ex? they implicitly borrow the types of ethical hibit. Any theorist, whether in ethics or in theories in which these concepts are embed? epistemology, must provide a comfortable ded. . . . Since contemporary epistemology home, if we may call it that, for rules, con? is belief-based, it is no surprise that the type sequences, and virtues. But that does not of moral theory from which these theories mean, to use our prime example, that the borrow is almost always an act-based theory, virtue theorist must accept a deontological either deontological or consequentialist. . . . understanding of rules, or a consequential? Almost all contemporary epistemic theories ist understanding of consequences. The take an act-based moral theory as their requirement is for comfortably accommo? model, even most of those that use the con? dating rules and consequences, not deonto cept of virtue (pp. 2, 7). logists and consequentialists! Dancy (1995) and Foley (1994) also both One cannot have all of these theories to? argue that the truth-conducive definition of gether, Dancy insists: "they just do not fit the intellectual virtues introduces a together," and compromise solutions are "consequentialist" element quite at odds really philosophically unstable. Each ethi? with what a genuine aretaic epistemology cal or epistemological theory is committed requires. The point seems underlined by to the primacy of its description, be it of Goldman's and Sosa's favorable reaction rule, consequence, or character. Views to understanding reliabilism as "epistemic such as Dancy's about the relationship be? rule-utilitarianism." Dancy has long seen tween virtue theory and its others are this type of question as an example of a sometimes considered "radical" (Baier, conflict between a "monism" and a "plu? 1988). But these views (or perhaps "atti? ralism" of aims; a genuinely aretaic tudes" would be a better term) are quite epistemology for today requires a plural? prominent in meta-ethics today, and we istic and holistic conception of the goals now see clearly one form that their meta of our intellectual life. "Praise and blame, epistemic counterpart takes. for a true virtue theorist, will be mediated As another example, take an epistemic by consideration of the sort of life that deontologist like Schmitt (1992), who argues

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 16 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

that the deontological conception "excludes whether this particular war is inevitable. any account appropriate to an aretaic con? In the space that remains I want to further ception of justified belief." Recognition develop virtue responsibilism and then con? of the primacy of rules may render refer? struct a hypothetical exchange between ences to virtue "otiose," in which case the these two camps. I do so in order to sug? aretaic account is likely to "revert to an gest that Dancy misses some irenic account of justified belief that conforms possibilities, ones that seem closed to to the deontic conception" (1992, p. 97). externalists and internalists of the usual This account appears still more radical in stripes, but open to those working within the sense that there is to be no quarter given the framework of shared assumptions to explanations under virtue-based descrip? provided by VE. The central virtue respon? tions, not even for their heuristic value, but sibilist argument we will examine is that only a thin promise of their ultimate re the responsibilist, but not the reliabilist, ducibility to rule-based explanations. If succeeds at what Sosa sees as one of the the notion of responsibility is relevant at goals of VE: making the person and his all to justification, it is a deontic notion intellectual character the seat of justification. rather than an aretaic one. Working from the distinction between The very uniqueness of aretaic explana? subjective and objective justification in tions is part of what is at issue in Schmitt's ethics, what Montmarquet finds important claim, and so it is little wonder if it seems in the distinction is the difference between that only aretaic theorists find aretaic justification as reflecting a person's opti? theory a unique philosophical option. In mal use of his own resources, versus both ethics and epistemology we are con? justification as objectively defined rela? fronted with explanations under alternative tions holding among belief contents and descriptions (Audi 1993; 1995), and a reso? features of the agent's circumstances. lution to the question of epistemic primacy According to Montmarquet, ethical and appears very distant. But it is clear from epistemic justification are essentially in? the foregoing that the oppositions between terconnected. Our notion of subjective aretaic theorists and their others must be epistemic justification should be guided by, thought through on both sides of the ethics/ or at least conform with, the consideration epistemology divide. that a justified belief is one that a person Dancy's argument places a damper on the would be morally justified in acting upon kind of synthetic or "irenic" approach Sosa (1993 p. 108). He examines the internalist/ has favored in the debate between episte? externalist debates and the place of sub? mic externalism and internalism, and this jective justification in both ethics and reflects rather directly on the opposition epistemology. The epistemic analogue of between virtue reliabilism and virtue subjective justification in ethics (construed responsibilism. Dancy says in no uncertain in terms of conscientiousness) is epistemic terms that "to be externalist in its relation responsibility. Subjective justification is to the notion of aptness, where a mere ten? thus a matter of the quality of one's under? dency to promote the truth is sufficient, and lying doxastic efforts. at the same time to be internalist in its talk The construal of internalism as a matter of blamelessness and character" is to have of the subject's "having reasons" (by his "feet in two warring camps" (1995). own lights) for his belief is inconsistent The virtue reliabilists' feet may here be with this focus on conscientious effort in in warring camps, but the question is really ethics. Kornblith and Montmarquet view

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RECENT WORK ON VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY / 17

virtue responsibilism as consistent only So responsibility-related traits of char? with specially qualified forms of internal? acter appear to drop out of the reliabilist ism, ones which put emphasis on the account whenever the latter says that jus? responsible cognitive agent and his regu? tification amounts "to a sort of inner lating motivation or desire for truth.16 coherence" (Sosa) or to an agent's own Montmarquet's arguments are developed standards or beliefs "about reliable belief around two kinds of possible cases where forming processes" (Goldman of 1986). To the standard internalist accounts of justi? characterize our two authors by these lines, fied belief are found not to provide an however, would be to greatly oversimplify intuitive basis for an account of morally their accounts, and the responsibilist would justified action. The first is the possibility need to confront their conceptions of sub? of a belief justified on internalist views jective justification directly. But the worry about connection or basing, but unvir is that the notions of reasons accessible on tuously held. The second is the possibility one's perspective reflect the radically sub? of a virtuously held belief that fails to pass jective or "inner lights" internalism which the internalist's standard of justification. overlooks questions of quality of agent The upshot of this argument is that it is efforts, and is inconsistent with the moti? subjective justification in the respon vational elements recognized in a require? sibilist's sense, rather than in the more ment of doxastic responsibility. common internalist sense of inner coher? Goldman's development of the distinction ence, that provides the right kind of between "weak and strong justification" in connection between epistemology and ethi? a 1988 article is directly tied to Kornblith's cal theory (p. 106). objections to his earlier justification Hilary Kornblith has also argued that externalist stance. On Goldman's distinct? justification as inner coherence is unsatis? ion, weak justification relates directly to factory. If we take coherence to be responsibility: a belief is weakly justified determined by the subject's own lights, it "as long as it is blameless or nonculpable" is too subjective; here we focus on the (LI, p. 169).17 Sosa also gives examples agent's evidence as fixed, and ask only if of epistemically irresponsible agents and he has reasons, disregarding how well or says that "the contrast between the aptness poorly he gathers evidence. This is sup? and the justification of a belief does not ported by Feldman's doubt that any real remove the need for two varieties of justi? sense can even be made of "radical sub? fication, the subjective and the objective" jective justification," the supremely (KIP, p. 11). Both writers today addition? iterative thesis that "5 is subjectively epi ally add lots of wrinkles to avoid a simple stemically justified in believing P if S "own lights" coherentism, like Goldman's believes that S has good reasons to believe that "S neither possesses, nor has available P" (1988, p. 411). On the other hand, to him/her, a reliable way of telling that Kornblith continues, coherence as an ob? [his/her own] process is unreliable" jective relation between beliefs "is too (1986, p. 59). external a relation to provide an account So there is an acknowledgment of the of the agent's internal perspective" (1986, responsibilists' sense of subjective justifi? p. 122). Factors of coherence so con? cation, but perhaps still a problem of little ceived, Kornblith argues, can no more systematic place for it in the virtue replace the role of epistemic responsibil? reliabilist account. Sosa has been critical ity in justification than can reliability itself. of Goldman's weak/strong distinction, and

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 18 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY perspectivism is meant to strengthen it, but reliabilist criterion" (LI, p. 169). As long whether it does, or whether the responsi? as Goldman is consistently able to ac? bilist will object that virtue perspectivism knowledge this and does not suppose that is too weak, depends in part on whether weak justification or blamelessness is im? the responsibilist conception of weak jus? plied by a truth-linked account of strong tification is retained or lost in Sosa's justification, then Kornblith's complaint perspectivism. For otherwise there are that reliably formed belief "is an ideal to cases where S's believing that p meets be sought, but cannot be a requirement for Sosa's conditions for justification, but justified belief (1983, p. 45) need not af? where S is nevertheless epistemically irre? fect him. The reliabilist is no longer sponsible in believing that p. replacing the responsibilist's requirements The responsibilist's list of virtues should on justification, but building upon them. not drop out of the picture if what is going Kornblith's reasoning in the last quota? on is really merely a "broadening" of the tion seems not based on the previous case, concept of virtue. The responsibilist sense but on the case of reliably produced be? of justification does not appear to have a liefs due to irresponsible action. Kornblith place in Sosa's delineation of the virtue raises this case, but Greco argues that in defining parameters of "field," "condition," normal human cognitive processes, reli? "environment," nor even of "inner nature" ability results from responsibility (Greco, as we have seen that understood. If it has 1993a). Greco thus sees that the virtue responsibilist must be careful not to dropped out, then Sosa seems to be infer? problematize the connection between sub? ring that his sufficient conditions for jective and objective justification, or to reflective knowledge ?roughly, truth plus slide back into forms of internalism he virtuous generation plus valid epistemic explicitly rejects. Let me pose a related perspective ? imply agent nonculpability question to the responsibilists here: How (blamelessness). This would basically be is the virtue responsibilist to distinguish a variation of the justification-reliabilist himself from the kind of internalist who view that a belief is rational or responsible would assume or insist that we need two only if it has an appropriate causal history. lists of virtues, one conducive to knowl? But that inference doesn't appear available, edge, and one conducive to justification? at least on the conception of epistemic per? Limiting the virtues to traits of character spective as a kind of inner coherence. So seems, from the reliabilist standpoint, to one question for Sosa is, What insures that drive justified belief and epistemically vir? the irresponsible agent lacks Sosa's episte? tuous belief apart. The claim that deontic mic perspective? and aretaic conceptions of justification Kornblith raises two related kinds of don't hook up with truth in the right way counter-example cases. One is meant to has, after all, often been grounds for re? show that responsibly-produced belief need jecting reliabilism (Steup 1988 on Alston). not be reliable (1983). And Goldman con? It has likewise been grounds for the idea curs, writing in "Epistemic Folkways" that of contrasting "veretic" (internalist) and "a belief is [weakly] justified as long as its "evidential" (externalist) conceptions of acquisition is blameless or nonculpable. epistemic luck (Hall 1994). In severing the Given limited resources and limited in? truth connection, the subject is made the formation, a belief might be acquired seat of justification, but has no kingdom nonculpably even though its generating to rule, having no view to issues of broader processes are not virtuous according to the epistemological concern.

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RECENT WORK ON VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY / 19

The responsibilist must hold that doxastic parts, which separate out questions about responsibility is a necessary condition for the processes by which beliefs are acquired, justified belief, and hence for genuine re? from questions about the voluntary acts by flective knowledge. But Steup seems which these processes are influenced. One wrong to insist that he must also hold it question then is whether the belief was ar? sufficient for justified belief, on pain of rived at by way of a subjectively correct having an inadequate account (1988); an process, and another is whether the actions account can be incomplete without neces? which were performed were subjectively sarily being inadequate. Kornblith and correct in the sense of regulation by the Montmarquet concede that virtues of char? desire for truth. We then have a three-tier acter are a subset of the truth-conducive (a basis for a theory of justification that ac? separate issue from the question of what the compatibility of, respect? unity the "teleological" construal of intel? ively, a reliability constraint, an internal lectual virtue provides). Both seem to coherence constraint, and a responsibility agree that doxastic responsibility is constraint. It would be in the spirit of my grounded in the interests that the individual proposal if virtue epistemologists were to and society take in having a basic stock of concern themselves with a comprehensive true or well-justified beliefs, and that true conception of inferential "habits" connect? beliefs are indispensable for success in ing the three tiers. For this emphasis on whatever other goals one has. These tenets, habit formation would soften the contrast together with Montmarquet's understand? of the innate and the acquired, with its at? ing of responsibilism as a "first-person" tenuating separation of the reliabilists' and account of justification in need of a responsibilists' lists of virtues. complementing, externally-oriented "third VE offers unique advantages because the person" account, are a clear indication of concept of virtue usefully explains both conciliatory possibilities. what it means to be "in a position to know" But we are still working with too (a strong emphasis in Sosa's work) and simple a dichotomy between subjective/ what it means for an agent to be praise? first-person and objective/third-person worthy or blameworthy. Still, this is of accounts of justified belief. According to course far too simplistic a rendition of Kornblith's account in "Ever Since Kornblith's intended synthesis, and would Descartes" (1985), where he comes to ac? be qualified or contested by other virtue knowledge reliability constraints, it is responsibilists. Montmarquet approves of imperative to avoid conflating three sepa? Kornblith's general framework but argues rate questions corresponding to three strenuously against the idea that doxastic independent kinds of evaluation. I want responsibility is always to be understood to end this discussion by proposing that in terms of actions.1* Greco (1990; 1993a) something like the threefold approach he offers an interesting alternative synthesis laid out there provides a basis for bringing of reliabilist and responsibilist approaches, the virtue epistemologists closer together but one which leans on a notion of the over the issue of justification. "countenancing" of norms in need of fur? Very roughly, an account of objective jus? ther development. tification answers to the question whether The best developed account is Zagzebski's the belief arrived at and the actions per? agent-based account. There are two com? formed were objectively correct. An ponents to intellectual virtue on her view, account of subjective justification has two that of intellectual motivation and that of

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 20 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

success or reliability in reaching the ends insofar as the motive to know is a good thing of the motivational component, which she and persons with such a motive use pro? takes to be knowledge. Each is able to an cesses known to them to be reliable. So the extent to avoid the extremes of internalism motive to know operates in the background of those reliable procedures over which we and externalism, and she sees virtue theory have some degree of voluntary control, and as a key to leading epistemologists beyond this "stalemate" debate. Two main forms the value of the epistemic state to which this motive leads is enhanced by the value of of "pure virtue theory" are conceivable, the motive itself. So I have claimed that each springing from one of these two com? the internalist feature of motive is both the ponents. The issue between them ? usual accompaniment of reliable belief perhaps a new focus for debate ? is the forming processes and one whose value is question of which comes first, end or mo? important for the value we attach to the re? tive. Each of these forms of virtue theory sulting state" (p. 312). has distinct advantages and disadvantages. This approach is not traditional and has the The first account "explain[s] the good of a burden of making a plausible case for each virtue teleologically. Virtue is good be? of the virtues being good in a fundamen? cause of its connection to the thing that is tal, non-derivative way, which seems to more fundamentally good [i.e. the general rebel against the importance of the episte? aim]." This approach has the advantage mic community. While reliabilists may not of tradition, being a most natural interpre? be tempted to take this route, we may agree tation of Aristotle view of virtues as with Zagzebski that both forms of virtue constituents of or means to the good life; theory are worth exploring further for it also potentially unifies the virtues in the their advantages.19 deepest way and promises to supply nor? mative criteria in a straightforward manner V. Conclusion (Simpson 1992). But the difficulties of de? scribing the goal, the life of flourishing, Even a "methodological" use of analogies are also well known. Some regard appeals between ethical and epistemic justification to any notion of flourishing (ethical or ep? raises deeper issues of a "meta-philosophi istemic) as suspect starting-points cal" nature. And for some this is what is because they appear arbitrary choices, most challenging and interesting in virtue like decisions about "ways of life" ac? theory today. The availability of useful cording to and existentialism. analogies between ethics and epistemology Considerations like these, Zagzebski has never, at least for them, been sharply thinks, make a non-teleological theory divided from a substantial thesis of the preferable. On the "motivational" version structural parity or symmetry between of an agent-based account, the goodness these two fields as the primary normative of virtues is based on the goodness of the subdisciplines of philosophy (compare H. agent's motives, and this form of goodness and R. Putnam 1987; 1993). In this sense, is conceived as intrinsic, not derived. recent interest in a unified virtue-theoretic account of justification, ethical and episte? "I have argued that in the form of virtue theory I call motivation-based, the value of mic, marks a significant rapprochement reliability rests on the value of the motive between ethicists and epistemologists. for knowledge. There is no special value in Dancy sees VE as laudably raising the fact that a particular true belief arises "analogies with the supposed advantages from a reliable belief-forming process except of virtue ethics, and even the prospect of a

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RECENT WORK ON VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY / 21

unification of epistemology and ethics, asserting a sharp contrast in the respective built round the common notion of a vir? rationality of scientific and ethical judg? tue" (1994). On Montmarquet's view, ment, and b) in terms of the fortunes of contemporary VE has an explicit meta the concepts of "value" and "valuation" in philosophical goal: to reveal similarities the twentieth century ? or more specifi? between ethics and epistemology out of cally, the against-the-stream effort of a which we can understand their respective number of Continental and American phi? differences as emerging. The broader losophers, including R. B. Perry and John ideal standing behind this goal is what Dewey, to develop and win support for a Montmarquet calls "a unified conception "general theory of value" (Axtell 1996). of ethical and epistemic virtue." Zagzebski, But I view general theory of value, or who holds that the only really relevant dif? axiology as it is sometimes labeled, as a ference between ethical and intellectual better term for the analysis of values, and virtues is in terms of the general aim prefer the common language of ethics as a (eudaimonia/knowltdge) of the two type of value. So I resist Zagzebski's classes, points out that "it greatly distorts strong claim that "epistemic evaluation just the nature of both to attempt to analyze is a form of moral evaluation," even if she them in separate branches of philosophy," insists that this claim be understood as "ex? where epistemology is usually categorized pansionist" rather than "reductionist." I with metaphysics, and ethics with politi? suspect that these differences are more than cal philosophy and aesthetics. "I see no semantical, and that Zagzebski here re? way to explain the value of the state that is peats the error she so well pointed out the primary concern of epistemology ? among reliabilists, of smuggling in poten? knowledge ? without linking it with the tially unattractive substantive con? general study of value, and that means eth? ceptions of ethics.20 ics" (p. 336) In a companion article to this I hope that the debates and range of top? one, I further explore the meta-philosophi ics we have canvassed have provided the cal shift that a unitary, virtue-theoretical reader with insight into the wider concerns account of ethical and epistemic normativ of contemporary virtue epistemology, and ity would demand. The appeal of such a have served to caution against the still com? shift, I argue, can in turn be understood mon propensity to identify it with only one historically, both a) as a response to the specific position on already familiar inadequacy of influential scientistic views philosophical terrain.

University of Nevada, Reno Received September 4, 1996

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Alston, William (1978), "Meta-Ethics and Meta-Epistemology," in A. I. Goldman & J. Kim (eds.) Values and Morals. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Pub. Co., pp. 275-297. _(1993) Review of Knowledge in Perspective by Ernest Sosa. Mind vol. 102, no. 405, pp. 199-204. _(1991) Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Aristotle (1941) Nicomachean Ethics, Trans. W. D. Ross, trans., in Richard McKeon, ed., The Basic Works of Aristotle. New York: Random House.

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 22 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

Audi, Robert (1993) "Ethical Naturalism and the Explanatory Power of Moral Concepts," in Steven J. Wagner and Richard Warner (eds.) Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 95-116. _(1995) "Acting From Virtue," Mind, vol. 104, pp. 449-471. Axtell, Guy (1996) "Epistemic Virtue-Talk: The Reemergence of American Axiology?," in Journal of Speculative Philosphy, Vol. X, No. 3, pp. 172-198. Baier, Kurt (1988) "Radical Virtue Ethics," in Ethical Theory: Character and Virtue. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 13. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. BonJour, Laurence (1990) "Review of Epistemic Responsibility, by Lorraine Code," The Philosophical Review, vol. 99, No. 1, pp. 123-127. _(1992) "Externalism and Internalism," in J. Dancy and E. Sosa (eds.) A Companion to Epistemology. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 132-136. _(1995) "Sosa on Knowledge, Justification, and 'Aptness'," in Philosophical Studies, forthcoming, vol. 78, pp.207-220. Braaten, Jane (1990) "Towards a Feminist Reassessment of Intenllectual Virtue," in Hypatia, vol. 5 No. 3, pp. 1-5. Code, Lorraine (1987) Epistemic Responsibility. Hanover, NH: University Press of New England. Cooper, Neil (1994) "The Intellectual Virtues," Philosophy vol 69 no. 270, pp. 443-458. Cullity, Garrett (1995) "Moral Character and the Iteration Problem," Utilitas vol 7, pp 280-289. Dancy, Jonathan (1982) "Intuitionism in Meta-Epistemology" Philosophical Studies 42 pp. 395-408. _(1992) "Ethics and Epistemology," in Companion to Epistemology, Dancy and Sosa (eds.). Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell. _(1993) Moral Reasons. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. _(1995) " Supervenience, Virtues and Consequences," in Philosophical Studies, vol. 78, pp. 221-35. Feldman, Richard (1988) "Subjective and Objective Justification in Ethics and in Epistemology." Monist, vol 71, 1pp. 405-19. Firth, Roderick (1978) "Are Epistemic Concepts Reducible to Ethical Concepts?," in A. I. Goldman & J. Kim (eds.) Values and Morals. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, pp. 275-297. _(1981) "Epistemic Merit, Intrinsic and Instrumental," Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association Vol 55, No. 1, 5-23. Foley, Richard (1994) "Sosa's Epistemology," in Philosophical Issues, Vol. 5: Truth and Ratio? nality, Enrique Villanueva (ed.). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Pub. Co. Fuller, Stephen (1992) "Liaisons: Philosophy Meets the Cognitive and Social Sciences," Choice vol. 29, No. 11-12, pp.1693. _(1996) "Recent Work in Social Epistemology," American Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 33, No. 2, pp. 149-166. Fumerton, Richard (1994) "Sosa's Epistemology," in Philosophical Issues, Vol. 5: Truth and Rationality, Enrique Villanueva (ed.). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Pub. Co. _(1995) and Scepticism. London: Rowman and Littlefield. Goldman, Alvin (1986) Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. _(1992) Liaisons: Philosophy Meets the Cognitive and Social Sciences. Cambridge: MIT Press. _(1993a) Philosophical Applications of Cognitive Science. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. _(ed.) (1993b) Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books. Gouinlock, James (1993) Rediscovering the Moral Life. Buffalo: Prometheus Books. Greco, John (1990) "Internalism and Epistemically Responsible Belief," Synthese 85, p. 245-77.

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RECENT WORK ON VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY / 23

_(1992) "Virtue Epistemology," an entry contribution to A Companion to Epistemology, J. Dancy and E. Sosa (eds.). Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell, pp. 520-22. _(1993a) "Virtues and Vices of Virtue Epistemology," Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Volume 23, No. 3, p. 413-432. _(1993b) "How to Beat a Sceptic Without Begging the Question," Ratio vol. VI, no. 1. _(1994) "Virtue Epistemology and the Relevant Sense of 'Relevant Possibility'," The Southern Journal of Philosophy, Vol. XXXII, p. 61-77. Gouinlock, James (1993) Rediscovering the Moral Life. Buffalo: Prometheus Books. Haack, Susan (1991) Review of Epistemic Responsibility, by Lorraine Code. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, vol. 20, pp. 91-108. Hall, Barbara (1994) "On Epistemic Luck," Southern Journal of Philosophy vol. 32, pp.79-84. Heil, John (1983) "Believing What One Ought," The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 80, pp. 752-65. _(1984) "Doxastic Incontinence," Mind, 93 pp. 56-70. Heyes, Cecilia (1989) "Uneasy Chapters in the Relationship Between Psychology and Episte? mology," in Psychology of Science, Barry Gholson et. Al. (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 115-137. Hookway, Christopher (1994) "Cognitive Virtues and Epistemic Evaluations," International Journal of Philosophical Studies, vol. 2, no. 2, pp. 211-227. Kim, Kihyeon (1993) "Internalism and Externalism in Epistemology," American Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 30, no. 4, pp. 303-316. Kornblith, Hilary (1983) "Justified Belief and Epistemically Responsible Action," The Philosophical Review, 92, no. 1, p. 33-48. _(1985) "Ever Since Descartes," Monist, vol. 68, pp. 264-76. _(1986) "Naturalizing Rationality," in Naturalism and Rationality, N. Garver and P. Hare (eds.). La Salle, IL: Open Court, pp. 115-33. _(1993) "Epistemic Normativity," Synthese vol. 94, pp. 357-76. Kvanvig, Jonathan L. (1992) The Intellectual Virtues and the Life of the Mind: On the Place of the Virtues in Epistemology. Savage, MA: Rowman and Littlefield. Lehrer, Keith (1989) Thomas Reid. London: Routledge. Lemos, John (1994) "The Unity of the Virtues and its Defenses," Southern Journal of Philosophy vol. 32, pp. 85-106. Montmarquet, J. E. (1987a) "Justification: Ethical and Epistemic," Metaphilosophy, vol 18, no. 3 &4, pp. 187-199. _(1987b) "Epistemic Virtue," Mind, 96, 482-97. _(1993) Epistemic Virtue and Doxastic Responsibility. Boston: Rowman and Littlefield. Moser, Paul (1991) Review of Knowledge in Perspective, by E. Sosa. Canadian Philosophical Reviews, vol. 11, pp. 425-27. Pence, Greg (1984) "Recent Work on Virtues," American Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 21, no. 4, pp. 281-297. Plantinga, Alvin (1993a) Warrant and Proper Function. Oxford: Oxford University Press. _(1993b) Warrant: The Current Debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press. _(1993c) "Why We Need Proper Function," Nous, vol. 27, no. 1, pp.66-82. Putnam, Hilary (1993) " and the Science-Ethics Distinction," in M. Nussbaum and A. Sen (eds.) The Quality of Life. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 143-157. Putnam, Ruth Anna (1987) "Weaving Seamless Webs," Philosophy, Vol. 62, pp.207-220. Schmitt, Frederick (1992) Knowledge and Belief. New York: Routledge. _(1993a) Review of Knowledge in Perspective, by Ernest Sosa, The Philosophical Review, vol. 102, no. 3, pp. 421-425. _(1993b) "Epistemic Perspectivism," in John Heil (ed.) Rationality, Morality, and Self interest. Lanham, ML: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 3-28.

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 24 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

Sherman, Nancy (1989) The Fabric of Character: Aristotle's Theory of Virtue. New York: Oxford University Press. Simpson, Peter (1992) "Contemporary Virtue Ethics and Aristotle," Review of Metaphysics, vol. 45, pp. 503-524. Slote, Michael (1996 forthcoming) "Agent-Based Virtue Ethics," in Moral Concepts. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 20. Sosa, Ernest (1991) Knowledge in Perspective: Selected Essays in Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (Chs. 4 & 5 on intellectual virtues) _(1993) "Proper Functionalism and Virtue Epistemology," Nous 27:1 pp. 51-65. _(1994a) " and Externalist Epistemology," in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume. _(1994b) "Moral Relativism, Cognitivism, and Defeasible Rules," Social Philosophy and Policy, vol. 11, no. 1, pp. 116-38. _(1994c) "Response to Foley and Fumerton," in Philosophical Issues, vol. 5: Truth and Rationality, Enrique Villanueva (ed.). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Pub. Co. _(1995) "Perspectives in Virtue Epistemology: A Response to Dancy and Bonjour," in Philosophical Studies, forthcoming. Steup, Matthias (1988) "The Deontic Conception of Epistemic Justification," Philosophical Studies vol. 53, pp. 65-84. Wisdo, David (1993) The Life of Irony and the Ethics of Belief. Albany: SUNY Press. Zagzebski, Linda (1993) "Intellectual Virtue in Religious Epistemology," in Faith in Theory and Practice: Essays on Justifying Religious Belief, E. Radcliffe and C. White. La Salle, IL: Open Court. _(1996) Virtues of the Mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

NOTES

1. Deontologists include the internalist Chisholm and the externalist Schmitt; "epistemic rule utilitarianism" is a description due to Firth, 1981; as a description of reliabilism it is perceived favorably in Heil, 1984, Sosa, 1991 and Goldman, 1992. 2. On the assumption that "ought implies can" and the issue of doxastic voluntarism, see Steup 1988, Heil 1983, 1984 and Montmarquet 1993. Zagzebski discusses a range or scale of voluntariness of human character traits, both intellectual and moral (1996, pp. 61). 3. "Focusing on the context of inquiry, a kind of activity, encourages the expectation that there might be structural parallels between problems of practical reason and problems of theo? retical reason_Justified beliefs are those that issue from the responsible inquiries of virtuous inquirers. It is a mistake to put it the other way round: epistemic virtues are those habits and dispositions which lead us to have justified beliefs. The primary focus is on how we order activities directed at answering questions and assessing methods of answering questions; it is not upon the epistemic status of beliefs" (Hookway, p. & 211 & 225). 4. The analogy between internalism and externalism in ethics and epistemology, however, is not straightforward. In epistemology the dispute focuses on epistemic access; in ethics, it focuses on the relationship between moral justification and moral motivation. See Dancy (1992) and Zagzebski (1996), pp. 331. 5. See Kim (1993) for a useful classification of internalist or externalist theories on a distinction of 1) ground, 2) adequacy, and 3) basing connection issues.

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms RECENT WORK ON VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY / 25

6. Sosa 1993, p. 65 Fn 25. "Generic" is an umbrella term covering reliable process, mechanism, and indicator accounts. See Sosa 1991, pp. 131. 7. "A belief that p constitutes reflective knowledge that p only if one has a perspective on the source of that belief in a [reliable] faculty or intellectual virtue of one's own. Otherwise it is unreflective" (KIP, pp. 290).

8. On the "tiered" or "stratified" conception of justification, compare L/pp. 163 and KIP pp. 189. 9. On the iteration problem, compare Cullity (1995). 10. Compare Zagzebski (1996), for whom the ability to give place to meta-beliefs as an aspect of cognitive integration, is an advantage of a theory, but not a strong requirement of ordinary justified belief. Virtues of integration, , and understanding differ, and it is an advantage of a theory to be able to connect discussions of knowledge and justification to these deeper intellectual virtues.

11. On Aristotle and "being properly affected," compare Kornblith 1985, pp. 274 and 276 n. 22. Neil Cooper (1994) has relatedly argued that there is an 'unofficial superintendent intel? lectual virtue" in Aristotle's thought, paideia, which is "the capacity to discern what intellectual virtues are appropriate in a given subject-matter" (pp. 460). 12. Alston, 1991, p. 148; discussed in Sosa 1994a. 13. Zagzebski makes a useful distinction between "strong" virtue theory, which is definist in that it defines a virtue in terms of a right act or a right act in terms of a virtue, and "weak" or criterialist virtue theory, which says only that what a virtuous person would do is the best criterion of what is right. It is unclear why she seems to hold that any "pure virtue theory" must be strong or definist, since the criterialist view still treats evaluation as derivative from the character of an agent. See 1996, p. 16. 14. Hookway (1994) sympathetically develops Montmarquet's conception of an epistemic mean, while Dancy's position is incompatible with it (1995). See Lemos (1994) for background on defenses of the unity of the ethical virtues. 15. "It is quite obvious that sight, hearing, and memory are faculties, and ... the Greeks identified virtues, not with faculties themselves, but with the excellences of faculties" (Zagzebski, 1996, pp. 10). 16. Desire for truth contrasts with externally-glossed truth-relatedness. For a contrast of grounding epistemic normativity in desire, see Kornblith 1993, where he criticizes Goldman's alternative analytic or semantic account. 17. Goldman 1986, pp. 59; see also Fumerton 1995 for criticism. 18. Montmarquet qualifies Kornblith's account in this respect. See especially his 1993, pp. 21-22 and 134.

19. The complementarity of the two components of intellectual virtue from which they spring is further evidenced by the observation, commonplace in the sciences, that an item's contribut? ing to a desirable result does not fully explain its presence. A functional-teleological analysis cannot explain a feature's presence without a complementary aetiological account, which in our present case must be one in terms of the motivations of the epistemic agent. Zagzebski begins with the latter account rather than the former, but of course motives and reasons are not far separated, and reasons reenter in the normative constraints the motivation-based theory places upon on our epistemic motivations as necessary requirement for knowledge. 20. Zagzebski sees normative epistemology as a branch of ethics. She says that her account "subsumes the intellectual virtues under the general category of the moral virtues, or aretai

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 26 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY ethikai, roughly as Aristotle understands the latter" (p. 255). "I think of this move as expan? sionist rather than reductionist since it would be more accurately described as expanding the range of ordinary moral evaluation to include epistemic evaluation, rather than reducing the latter to the former" (p. 255). "Epistemic evaluation just is a form of moral evaluation" (p. 256). See also Zagzebski 1993.

This content downloaded from 129.215.108.87 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:31:31 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms