Peano and Russell

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Peano and Russell PEANO AND RUSSELL Introduction Gottlob Frege is customarily awarded the honorific title ‘the father of modern logic’. Jean van Heijenoort (1992: 242) tells us that ‘Modern logic began in 1879, the year in which Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) published his Begriffsschrift’, while Michael Dum- mett (1993: xiii) regards Frege as the ‘initiator of the modern period in the study of logic’. Yet, the praise so frequently accorded to the originality and quality of Frege’s logic and philosophy has obscured the significance and influence of his contem- porary, Guiseppe Peano. The contribution of the latter has been underestimated; indeed in terms of causal consequence, Peano’s work had a greater impact on the development of logic at a crucial period surrounding the turn of the nineteenth cen- tury. Peano’s influence was felt principally through his impact on Bertrand Russell (indeed, much the same can be said of Frege). In this essay we shall examine this line of influence, looking first at Peano’s logic and then at Russell’s. Guiseppe Peano Guiseppe Peano was born in Piedmont, in 1858, ten years after Frege and fourteen years before Russell. He was educated in the Piedmontese capital, Turin, where he became professor of mathematics, teaching and researching in analysis and logic. As with several other mathematicians, his interest in logic was in part motivated by the need to promote rigour in mathematics. The emphasis he places on rigour can be appreciated through a debate between Peano and his colleague Corrado Segre. Segre had made important contributions to algebraic geometry, and with Peano made Turin a notable centre for geometry. Nonetheless, they had quite different at- 1 titudes towards rigour, proof, and intuition. Segre felt that in order to make progress in a new area of mathematics, it would often be necessary to resort to less rigorous, incomplete procedures (Borga and Palladino 1992: 23). Peano (1891: 66) responded that, ‘a result cannot be considered as obtained if it is not rigourously proved, even if exceptions are not known.’ The difference between the intuitive approach and the rigorous approach is ap- parent in the mathematical understanding of continuity. The intuitive notion of a continuous curve is one that can be divided into parts each of which is contin- uously differentiable. Curves of the latter sort cannot fill a space—however small a space we choose, the curve cannot go through every point in the space. Intu- itively a one-dimensional thing, a continuous curve, cannot fill two-dimensional space. However, Peano shows that some continuous curves can go through every point in a finite space, indeed in infinite space. In a paper published in 1890, Peano gave a formal description of what became known as the ‘Peano curve’, a curve that passes through every point in the unit square. The paper gave no illustration of the curve, precisely because, Peano held, it is thinking in visual terms about geometry and analysis that leads to the use of intuition in mathematics and the breakdown of rigour. The other influence on the Peano curve was Cantor. Peano was intrigued by Can- tor’s proof that the set of points in the unit interval (the real numbers between 0 and 1) has the same cardinality as (i.e. can be put into 1–1 correlation with) the number of points in the unit square. Since the cardinality of the unit interval is equal to that of the whole real line, this raises the possibility that there is a curve that proves Can- tor’s conclusion by going though every point in the unit square. Peano’s curve does exactly that. Peano’s logical symbolism In the year following publication of his space-filling curve, Peano instituted his ‘For- mulario’ project, the aim of which was to articulate all the theorems of mathemat- ics using a new notation that Peano had devised. A little earlier Peano (1888) has 2 published a book on the geometrical calculus, following the approach of Hermann Grassmann’s Ausdehnungslehre. According to Grassmann, geometry does not have physical space as its subject matter. It is rather a purely abstract calculus that may have application to physical space. Conceiving it this way allows for a formal ap- proach to geometrical proof divorced from intuition and thereby allows for flaws in intuition-based reasoning (for example in Euclid) to be avoided. Moritz Pasch, in his Vorlesungen über neuere Geometrie (1882) takes certain terms as primitive and undefined (‘Kernbegriffe’ as Pasch later called them) while certain theorems (‘Kern- sätze’) are taken as unproved, i.e. are the axioms. Derived theorems are to be proved by pure logic alone, independently of any intuition. Pasch’s approach influenced Peano’s I principii di geometria logicamente esposti (1889). For this programme to be realised fully, Peano held, the geometrical calculus needed the framework of a logical calculus. In 1889 Peano also published his Arithmetices principia, nova methodo exposita. This work (in Latin) contained his famous five postulates for arithmetic—the ‘arith- metices principia’. The phrase ‘nova methodo exposita’ refers to the new symbolism that Peano introduced for logical relations: the now familiar ‘²’ for set/class mem- bership and ‘ ’C for implication (a rotated ‘C’ for ‘consequentia’—in the second vol- ume of the Formulaire Peano replaced ‘ ’C by the now-familiar horseshoe‘ ’). Peano ⊃ has already used several other new symbols that were to become central to the sym- bolism of logic and set-theory, such as the symbols for union and intersection, ‘ ’ [ and ‘ ’, and existential quantification, ‘ ’, and the tilde ‘ ’ for negation (Cajori 1929: \ 9 » 298–302). Peano signified universal generalisation using subscripts with his ‘ ’.C The familiarity of these symbols tends to mask the importance of their introduction. But the idea is familiar that having the appropriate terminology is crucial not just to ex- pressing thoughts clearly but often also to having the relevant thoughts at all. The development of a symbolism for logic was not just a lubricant to the accelerating ve- hicle that was mathematical logic, but was an essential part of its motor, as Bertrand Russell was soon to acknowledge. 3 From Peano to Russell In the last summer of the nineteenth century, the first International Congress of Phi- losophy took place in Paris (it was to be followed immediately by the second Interna- tional Congress of Mathematics). Peano was on the committee for the Congress and one of its leading lights. Also attending was twenty-eight year old Bertrand Russell. Born into the aristocracy, the grandson of a Prime Minister, Russell came from quite a different background from Peano. Nonetheless, their interests converged on the intersection of mathematics, logic, and philosophy. Russell went up to Cambridge in 1890, where he completed both the Mathematical and Moral Sciences (Philoso- phy) Triposes. Like Peano, Russell was much taken by the work of Georg Cantor. He had begin to study Cantor’s work in 1896 (Grattan–Guinness 1978: 129), and had been thinking a great deal when he met Peano in August 1900. In his autobiography, Russell (1967: 144) records the significance of his meeting thus: The Congress was the turning point of my intellectual life, because there I met Peano. I already knew him by name and had seen some of his work, but had not taken the trouble to master his notation. In discus- sions at the Congress I observed that he was always more precise than anyone else, and that he invariably got the better of any argument on which he embarked. As the days went by, I decided that this must be ow- ing to his mathematical logic . It became clear to me that his notation afforded an instrument of logical analysis such as I had been seeking for years . and thus (Russell 1959: 65): I went to [Peano] and said, ‘I wish to read all your works. Have you got copies with you?’ He had, and I immediately read them all. It was they that gave the impetus to my own views on the principles of mathemat- ics. 4 Burali-Forti’s paradox and Cantor’s theorem Russell, who had been intending to stay for both congresses, left Paris in order to return home to study Peano’s work in greater detail. He was, however, already aware of Burali-Forti’s paradox and of Cantor’s paradox. Cesare Burali-Forti was Peano’s assistant and lectured on Peano’s mathematical logic and used Peano’s symbolism in his own work. In 1897 Burali-Forti had published his famous paradox concerning ordinals. In a simple terms the class of all ordinals, ­, is an ordinal or corresponds to an ordinal. But then we can construct a greater ordinal, which is both a member of ­, (because it is an ordinal) and not a member of ­, (because it is greater than ­). Georg Cantor had earlier (1891) published his diagonal proof that the power set of a set is always larger than the set itself (as follows). Let us assume that there is a 1-1 correspondence between S and its power set, P (S). This 1-1 correspondence, f : S P (S) is a bijection; for every member of x ! of S, f (x) P (S), and for every member y of P (S), there is a unique x S such that 2 2 f (x) y (Table 1). Æ S P (S) x f (x) Table 1: f is a 1-1 correlation between S and P (S) The various f (x) are subsets of S. And so some members of S may be correlated by f with sets of which they are themselves members, i.e.
Recommended publications
  • Mathematical Induction - a Miscellany of Theory, History and Technique
    Mathematical Induction - a miscellany of theory, history and technique Theory and applications for advanced secondary students Part 4 Peter Haggstrom This work is subject to Copyright. It is a chapter in a larger work. You can however copy this chapter for educational purposes under the Statutory License of the Copyright Act 1968 - Part VB For more information [email protected] Copyright 2009 [email protected] The building blocks of Gödelʼs Theorem The foundations of Gödel’s Theorem (ie his undecidability theorem) are to be found in about 50 papers contained in a book by Jean van Heijenoort:, “From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879 - 1931”. Every serious logic student has read this book. Van Heijenoort is worth mentioning even if only for his colourful past which is described by Benjamin H Yandell in his book “The Honors Class: Hilbert’s Problems and Their Solvers”, A K Peters, 2002, page 66. I quote in full: “ I assumed van Heijenoort was merely a logician as I gratefully pored over his book and was astounded when I learned that as a young man, in the 1930s, he had followed Leon Trotsky from Turkey to France to Norway to Mexico, as his body guard and secretary. Anita Feferman’s ”From Trotsky to Gödel”: The Life of Jean van Heijenoort” tells van Heijenoort’s remarkable story. Trotsky and his camp were pursued by Stalinist agents; van Heijenoort always packed a gun. Van Heijenoort had an affair with an artist Frida Kahlo. He epitomized cool and was attractive to women, and this continued even after he became a logician, He had grown tired of the rigors of life with Trotsky and traveled to New York in 1939 on a somewhat vague mission.
    [Show full text]
  • From Von Mises' Impossibility of a Gambling System to Probabilistic
    From von Mises' Impossibility of a Gambling System to Probabilistic Martingales MSc Thesis (Afstudeerscriptie) written by Francesca Zaffora Blando (born January 27th, 1988 in Chivasso, Italy) under the supervision of Prof. Dr. Paul Vit´anyi and Prof. Dr. Michiel van Lambalgen, and submitted to the Board of Examiners in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MSc in Logic at the Universiteit van Amsterdam. Date of the public defense: Members of the Thesis Committee: September 16th, 2015 Prof. Dr. Johan van Benthem Prof. Dr. Michiel van Lambalgen (supervisor) Dr. Piet Rodenburg Dr. Leen Torenvliet Prof. Dr. Paul Vit´anyi (supervisor) Prof. Dr. Ronald de Wolf (chair) Per Si´sPi`uOtto! Abstract Algorithmic randomness draws on computability theory to offer rigorous formulations of the notion of randomness for mathematical objects. In addition to having evolved into a highly technical branch of mathematical logic, algorithmic randomness prompts numerous methodological questions. This thesis aims at addressing some of these questions, together with some of the technical challenges that they spawn. In the first part, we discuss the work on randomness and the foundations of probability of the Austrian mathematician Richard von Mises [1919], whose theory of collectives constitutes the first attempt at providing a formal definition of randomness. Our main objective there is to ascertain the reasons that led to the demise of von Mises' approach in favour of algorithmic randomness. Then, we turn to the myriad definitions of randomness that have been proposed within the algorithmic paradigm, and we focus on the issue of whether any of these definitions can be said to be more legitimate than the others.
    [Show full text]
  • How Peircean Was the “'Fregean' Revolution” in Logic?
    HOW PEIRCEAN WAS THE “‘FREGEAN’ REVOLUTION” IN LOGIC? Irving H. Anellis Peirce Edition, Institute for American Thought Indiana University – Purdue University at Indianapolis Indianapolis, IN, USA [email protected] Abstract. The historiography of logic conceives of a Fregean revolution in which modern mathematical logic (also called symbolic logic) has replaced Aristotelian logic. The preeminent expositors of this conception are Jean van Heijenoort (1912–1986) and Don- ald Angus Gillies. The innovations and characteristics that comprise mathematical logic and distinguish it from Aristotelian logic, according to this conception, created ex nihlo by Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) in his Begriffsschrift of 1879, and with Bertrand Rus- sell (1872–1970) as its chief This position likewise understands the algebraic logic of Augustus De Morgan (1806–1871), George Boole (1815–1864), Charles Sanders Peirce (1838–1914), and Ernst Schröder (1841–1902) as belonging to the Aristotelian tradi- tion. The “Booleans” are understood, from this vantage point, to merely have rewritten Aristotelian syllogistic in algebraic guise. The most detailed listing and elaboration of Frege’s innovations, and the characteristics that distinguish mathematical logic from Aristotelian logic, were set forth by van Heijenoort. I consider each of the elements of van Heijenoort’s list and note the extent to which Peirce had also developed each of these aspects of logic. I also consider the extent to which Peirce and Frege were aware of, and may have influenced, one another’s logical writings. AMS (MOS) 2010 subject classifications: Primary: 03-03, 03A05, 03C05, 03C10, 03G27, 01A55; secondary: 03B05, 03B10, 03E30, 08A20; Key words and phrases: Peirce, abstract algebraic logic; propositional logic; first-order logic; quantifier elimina- tion, equational classes, relational systems §0.
    [Show full text]
  • Georg Kreisel Correspondence with Jean Van Heijenoort
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/c84q7wxh No online items Guide to the Georg Kreisel Correspondence with Jean van Heijenoort Daniel Hartwig Stanford University. Libraries.Department of Special Collections and University Archives Stanford, California October 2010 Copyright © 2015 The Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University. All rights reserved. Note This encoded finding aid is compliant with Stanford EAD Best Practice Guidelines, Version 1.0. Guide to the Georg Kreisel SC0233 1 Correspondence with Jean van Heijenoort Overview Call Number: SC0233 Creator: Kreisel, Georg, 1923- Title: Georg Kreisel correspondence with Jean van Heijenoort Dates: 1949-1981 Physical Description: 6 Linear feet Summary: Correspondence, notes, memoranda, articles and other materials by Professor Georg Kreisel, sent to his colleague, Professor J. van Heijenoort of Harvard University. Includes some correspondence with other colleagues. Language(s): The materials are in English. Repository: Department of Special Collections and University Archives Green Library 557 Escondido Mall Stanford, CA 94305-6064 Email: [email protected] Phone: (650) 725-1022 URL: http://library.stanford.edu/spc Gift of J. van Heijenoort, 1981. Information about Access This collection is open for research. Ownership & Copyright All requests to reproduce, publish, quote from, or otherwise use collection materials must be submitted in writing to the Head of Special Collections and University Archives, Stanford University Libraries, Stanford, California 94304-6064. Consent is given on behalf of Special Collections as the owner of the physical items and is not intended to include or imply permission from the copyright owner. Such permission must be obtained from the copyright owner, heir(s) or assigns.
    [Show full text]
  • Bio-Bibliographical Sketch of Jean Van Heijenoort
    Lubitz’ TrotskyanaNet Jean Van Heijenoort Bio-Bibliographical Sketch Contents: Basic biographical data Biographical sketch Selective bibliography Sidelines, notes on archives Basic biographical data Name: Jean Van Heijenoort Other names (by-names, pseud. etc.): Alex Barbon ; Jacques Carton ; García Cestero ; Jarvis Gerland ; J.v.H. ; Vladimir Ivlev ; John ; Marcel Letourneur ; Daniel Logan ; Marc Loris ; K.M. ; M. Marcel ; Karl Mayer ; Karl Meyer ; Jean Rebel ; V. ; Van ; Jean Louis Maxime Van Heijenoort ; John Van Heijenoort ; Jean Vannier ; Ann Vincent ; J. Walter Wind ; Windy Date and place of birth: July 23, 1912, Creil (France) Date and place of death: March 29, 1986, México, D.F. (México) Nationality: French ; USA Occupations, careers: Professor of philosophy, mathematician, logician, archivist, writer, editor, translator, secretary, political activist Time of activity in Trotskyist movement: 1931 - 1948 Biographical sketch Jean Van Heijenoort was undoubtedly one of the most distinguished and devoted persons who shared the Trotskyist movement: first a secretary and bodyguard to Trotsky, then a secretary of the Fourth International and eventually one of the most eminent scholars in the field of modern mathematics and history of logic. His remark- able and quite extraordinary itinerary has been described and appraised by various renowned historians and scholars such as Pierre Broué or Irving H. Anellis, and a rich book-length biography about him from Anita B. Feferman's pen has been available since 19931. Jean (Louis Maxime) Van Heijenoort was born in Creil (Département Oise, France) on July 23, 1912 as son of a working-class family: his father was Jean Théodore Didier van Heijenoort (b. 1885), a Dutchman who had immigrated to France, and his mother was Charlotte Hélène Balagny (b.
    [Show full text]
  • On Diagonal Argument. Russell Absurdities and an Uncountable Notion of Lingua Characterica
    ON DIAGONAL ARGUMENT. RUSSELL ABSURDITIES AND AN UNCOUNTABLE NOTION OF LINGUA CHARACTERICA JAMES DOUGLASS KING Bachelor of Arts, University of Lethbridge, 1996 A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies of the University of Lethbridge in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree MASTER OF ARTS Department of Philosophy University of Lethbridge LETHBRIDGE, ALBERTA, CANADA © James Douglass King, 2004 ABSTRACT There is an interesting connection between cardinality of language and the distinction of lingua characterica from calculus rationator. Calculus-type languages have only a countable number of sentences, and only a single semantic valuation per sentence. By contrast, some of the sentences of a lingua have available an uncountable number of semantic valuations. Thus, the lingua-type of language appears to have a greater degree of semantic universality than that of a calculus. It is suggested that the present notion of lingua provides a platform for a theory of ambiguity, whereby single sentences may have multiply - indeed, uncountably - many semantic valuations. It is further suggested that this might lead to a pacification of paradox. This thesis involves Peter Aczel's notion of a universal syntax, Russell's question, Keith Simmons* theory of diagonal argument, Curry's paradox, and a 'Leibnizian' notion of language. iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The following people are due great thanks and gratitude for their constant support and understanding over the considerable time that it took to develop this thesis. They are each sine qua non of my success. Bryson Brown has supported my efforts from beginning to end, since my undergraduate studies when I first found my love of logic and philosophy; he also brought me to understand much that I have otherwise found obscure and/or irrelevant, and he provided important moral support.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapters Are Organised Thema� Cally to Cover: Wri� Ng and Solving Equa� Ons, Geometric Construc� On, Coordinates and Complex Numbers, A� Tudes to the Use
    E Making up Numbers A History of Invention in Mathematics KKEHARD EKKEHARD KOPP Making up Numbers: A History of Inventi on in Mathemati cs off ers a detailed but K Making up Numbers accessible account of a wide range of mathema� cal ideas. Star� ng with elementary OPP concepts, it leads the reader towards aspects of current mathema� cal research. A History of Invention in Mathematics Ekkehard Kopp adopts a chronological framework to demonstrate that changes in our understanding of numbers have o� en relied on the breaking of long-held conven� ons, making way for new inven� ons that provide greater clarity and widen mathema� cal horizons. Viewed from this historical perspec� ve, mathema� cal abstrac� on emerges as neither mysterious nor immutable, but as a con� ngent, developing human ac� vity. Chapters are organised thema� cally to cover: wri� ng and solving equa� ons, geometric construc� on, coordinates and complex numbers, a� tudes to the use of ‘infi nity’ in mathema� cs, number systems, and evolving views of the role of M axioms. The narra� ve moves from Pythagorean insistence on posi� ve mul� ples to gradual acceptance of nega� ve, irra� onal and complex numbers as essen� al tools in quan� ta� ve analysis. AKING Making up Numbers will be of great interest to undergraduate and A-level students of mathema� cs, as well as secondary school teachers of the subject. By virtue of UP its detailed treatment of mathema� cal ideas, it will be of value to anyone seeking N to learn more about the development of the subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematics Self Proves Its Own Consistency and Other Matters
    Inconsistency Robustness in Foundations: Mathematics self proves its own Consistency and Other Matters Carl Hewitt This article is dedicated to Alonzo Church, Stanisław Jaśkowski, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Ernst Zermelo. Abstract Inconsistency Robustness is performance of information systems with pervasively inconsistent information. Inconsistency Robustness of the community of professional mathematicians is their performance repeatedly repairing contradictions over the centuries. In the Inconsistency Robustness paradigm, deriving contradictions have been a progressive development and not “game stoppers.” Contradictions can be helpful instead of being something to be “swept under the rug” by denying their existence, which has been repeatedly attempted by Establishment Philosophers (beginning with some Pythagoreans). Such denial has delayed mathematical development. This article reports how considerations of Inconsistency Robustness have recently influenced the foundations of mathematics for Computer Science continuing a tradition developing the sociological basis for foundations.1 Classical Direct Logic is a foundation of mathematics for Computer Science, which has a foundational theory (for convenience called “Mathematics”) that can be used in any other theory. A bare turnstile is used for Mathematics so that ├Ψ means that Ψ is a mathematical proposition that is a theorem of Mathematics and Φ├Ψ means that Ψ can be inferred from Φ in Mathematics. The current common understanding is that Gödel proved “Mathematics cannot prove its own consistency, if it is consistent.” However, the consistency of mathematics can be proved by a simple argument using standard rules of Mathematics including the following: rule of Proof by Contradiction, i.e., (Φ⇒(ΘΘ))├ Φ and the rule of Soundness, i.e., (├ Φ)⇒Φ Formal Proof.
    [Show full text]
  • On Godel's Way In: the Influence of Rudolf Carnap
    On Godel's Way In: The Influence of Rudolf Carnap The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Goldfarb, Warren. 2005. On Godel's way in: The influence of Rudolf Carnap. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11, no. 2: 185-193. Published Version http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/bsl/1120231629 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:3153305 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA On Godel's Way in: The Influence of Rudolf Carnap Author(s): Warren Goldfarb Source: The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, Vol. 11, No. 2 (Jun., 2005), pp. 185-193 Published by: Association for Symbolic Logic Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1556748 Accessed: 24/06/2009 18:20 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=asl.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Views of Russell and Russell's Logic by His
    SOME VIEWS OF RUSSELL AND RUSSELL’S LOGIC BY HIS CONTEMPORARIES, WITH PARTICULAR REFERENCE TO PEIRCE IRVING H. ANELLIS In the years prior to World War I, it was not yet definitively certain that the new logistic developed and espoused by Frege and Russell was the “wave of the future” of mathematical logic. Ernst Schröder’s Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik (1895– 1905) was still new and viewed as the cutting edge of (algebraic—as opposed to Aristote- lian) logic; Giuseppe Peano still proclaimed, in his earliest work on logic, his indebted- ness to George Boole, Charles Peirce, and Ernst Schröder, in the first footnote of his Arithmetices principia nova methodo exposita (1898), while, in a letter to Russell of 19 March 1901,1 Peano told Russell that his paper “Sur la logique des relations avec des ap- plications à la théorie des séries” on the logic of relations (1901) just “fills a gap between the work of Peirce and Schröder on the one hand and” his own “Formulaire on the other;” Alfred North Whitehead’s Treatise on Universal Algebra (1898) also still new, brought together the algebraic logic of Boole with the linear and multilinear algebras of Arthur Cayley, James Joseph Sylvester, William Rowan Hamilton, and Charles Peirce’s father Benjamin Peirce, and the calculus of extension of Hermann Grassmann. In his Treatise, Whitehead (p. x) not only named Hamilton and De Morgan as “the first to ex- press quite clearly the general possibilities of algebraic symbolism,” but continually ex- pressed his indebtedness to Boole, Grassmann, De Morgan, Schröder, and John Venn; and he described his Treatise (p.
    [Show full text]
  • | Book Re Vie W S from Trotsky to Gödel, the Life of Jean Van
    60 NAW 5/7 nr. 1 maart 2006 Boekbesprekingen A. Burdman Feferman From Trotsky to Gödel, The Life of Jean van Heijenoort A.K. Peters, 2001 Book Reviews 432 p., prijs $ 25,– | ISBN 1-56881-148-9 As one commentator said, this book is ‘stranger than fiction’. This well-written biography about the cultured logician van Heij- enoort was first published under a different title: ‘Politics, Logic and Love’, with the same subtitle and content. Indeed, Jean van Heijenoort (1912–1986) was active in these three fields in mem- orable ways. He was for seven years secretary and bodyguard of Trotsky; he was a logician having a wide-angle view, result- ing among other things in his publication From Frege to Gödel, a source book of the fundamental papers of modern mathematical logic with a fine choice of topics; and finally he was enchanted by women in such a way that it finally became fatal. When Jean van Heijenoort was two years old his father died, because of the lack of medical care during World War I. This re- sulted in the separation from his mother, who had to provide for a living, and he was raised by his (very catholic) aunt and two older (female) cousins. Later his mother remarried a man whom he did not like. This situation has given him an unhappy youth. After World War I young Jean was very painfully struck by the endless fields of crosses at a war cemetery. He ‘rejected —totally rejected— the system that caused the war. “I wanted something else.” During his school years van Heijenoort was impressed by the autobiography of Trotsky, both for its contents and style and he became a left-winged idealist.
    [Show full text]
  • Cut As Consequence
    Cut as Consequence Curtis Franks Department of Philosophy, University of Notre Dame, Indiana, USA The papers where Gerhard Gentzen introduced natural deduction and sequent calculi suggest that his conception of logic differs substantially from now dominant views introduced by Hilbert, G¨odel, Tarski, and others. Specifically, (1) the definitive features of natural deduction calculi allowed Gentzen to assert that his classical system nk is complete based purely on the sort of evidence that Hilbert called ‘experimental’, and (2) the structure of the sequent calculi li and lk allowed Gentzen to conceptualize completeness as a question about the relationships among a system’s individual rules (as opposed to the relationship between a system as a whole and its ‘semantics’). Gentzen’s conception of logic is compelling in its own right. It is also of historical interest because it allows for a better understanding of the invention of natural deduction and sequent calculi. 1. Introduction In the opening remarks of 1930, Kurt G¨odeldescribed the construction and use of formal axiomatic systems as found in the work of Whitehead and Russell—the procedure of ‘initially taking certain evident propositions as axioms and deriving the theorems of logic and mathematics from these by means of some precisely formulated principles of inference in a purely formal way’—and remarked that when such a procedure is followed, the question at once arises whether the ini- tially postulated system of axioms and principles of inference is complete, that is, whether it actually suffices for the derivation of every logico-mathematical proposition, or whether, perhaps, it is conceivable that there are true [wahre1] propositions .
    [Show full text]