Laws I-II Trans & Comm

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Laws I-II Trans & Comm 1 Plato: Laws, Books I and II Translated with commentary © Susan Sauvé Meyer 2012 (penultimate draft) to be published by Oxford University Press Clarendon Plato Series corrections welcome! [email protected] 2 Preface/Foreward Why the present volume? Students of Plato’s Laws already have the benefit of a several excellent commentaries and translations produced in the last century. England’s magisterial commentary on the Greek text (1922) continues to be a valuable resource to readers in English, as is the more limited set of notes on the text in Saunders 1972. Neither, however, offers much guidance on points of philosophical, as opposed to philological, interpretation. On many fronts both have been superseded by the excellent commentary in German, with accompanying translation, recently completed by Schöpsdau (1994-2011). The latter contains considerably more historical material than England, and is an indispensable resource for any serious scholarship on the Laws. Readers of Spanish or French have the benefit of up-to-date scholarly translations with accompanying notes by Lisi 1999 and Brisson/Pradeua (2006), respectively. The closest that readers in English have to a philosophical commentary on the Laws are the notes and long interpretive essay that accompany the 1980 translation by Pangle, and the detailed analysis by Strauss 1975, but the aggressively “Straussian” orientation of these works makes them less helpful to readers of other philosophical persuasions. Of course, no philosophical commentary can plausibly claim to be without theoretical presuppositions, and the orientation of the present work reflects presuppositions characteristic of scholarship on Plato by so-called “analytic” philosophers in the English-speaking world over the last four or five decades. The translation aims to be more idiomatic than Pangle’s, and is heavily indebted to the very elegant and readable translation by Saunders 1972. The latter translation reflects a detailed and nuanced appreciation of Plato’s Greek text that it would be a formidable task to match, but it is often less precise in its rendering of that text, on points crucial to the interpretation of the philosophical issues and arguments in the work, than is optimal for the Greekless reader. It is to the needs of such a reader that the present translation is addressed. The main concern of the commentary is to understand how the work is structured as a complex piece of argumentation, and to appreciate the theories (legal, ethical, and psychological) expounded and criticized within it. For the most part, it pays attention to textual or philological issue only when these have implications for these philosophical issues. While preparing the translation and commentary I have benefitted from the generosity and advice of many colleagues, friends, and correspondents: Elizabeth Asmis, Chris Bobonich, Anna Cremaldi, Radcliffe Edmonds III, Margaret Graver, Brad Inwood, Charles Kahn, Grace Ledbetter, Ralph Rosen, Krisanna Scheiter, Peter Struck, Christian Wildberg, and Emily Wilson, as well as an anonymous referee for Oxford University Press. I learned much from the students in my graduate seminar on the Laws in 2008 and have profited greatly from the research assistance provided by Nora Donovan, Jesse Dubois, and Jan Maximillian Robitzsch. Grants from School of Arts and Science and from the University Research Foundation of the University of Pennsylvania supported the 3 preparation of the final version of the manuscript, and a sabbatical leave from that same university gave me the intellectual leisure in which to complete the project. Susan Sauvé Meyer Philadelphia, Pennsylvania September 2012 4 THE LAWS OF PLATO Persons in the Dialogue: An Athenian, Clinias of Crete, Megillus of Sparta BOOK I 624a ATH: Is it a god or a human being, Strangers, who gets the credit for establishing your laws? CL: A god, Stranger, most assuredly a god! Here, we say it is Zeus while among the Spartans, where this man comes from, I believe they say it is Apollo. Isn’t that so? MEG: Yes. ATH: Isn’t your story the one in Homer, that Minos b established the laws for your cities by making pilgrimage to his father every nine years and following the oracles he received from him? CL: That is exactly what we say here, and also that his brother Rhadamanthus—you’ve heard the name, I’m sure— 625a was a paragon of justice. We Cretans would say he deserves this accolade from the excellent way he meted out justice in legal disputes. ATH: A fine reputation indeed, most appropriate to a son of Zeus. Now since you and our friend here have been raised under such distinguished laws, I expect you would not find it unpleasant if we spent our journey together in conversation about constitutions and laws. b In any case, the road from Knossos to the sacred cave of Zeus is fairly long, we are told, with shady places to rest along the way under tall trees. As the day is likely to be very hot, those at our stage of life would do well to take frequent breaks there and refresh ourselves with conversation. That way the distance will pass quite easily. CL: In fact, Stranger, there are cypress trees of wondrous 5 c height and beauty up ahead in the sacred groves, as well as meadows in which we might spend our time when resting along the way. ATH: A very good idea. CL: Indeed. When we see for ourselves, we shall think so all the more. So let us be off, and may good fortune go with us. ATH: Amen. Now tell me, on what principle has the law ordained your common meals, your regime of athletic training, and your style of arms? CL: I think our ways are pretty easy for anyone to understand, Stranger. The nature of the terrain all over Crete, you may observe, d is unlike the flat land of the Thessalians, which is why they train mainly on horseback and we on foot, our uneven terrain being well suited to foot racing. Our arms must accordingly be lightweight, so that we aren’t burdened down while we run. The lightness of bows and arrows, then, makes them the perfect weapons for us to use. All this equips us well for war, e and it is with the same end in view, I believe, that the lawgiver devised all our institutions—even our common meals. He organized these, I would venture, based on the observation that an army on the battlefield is compelled to eat together in order to maintain a proper guard. He had contempt for the folly of most people, who fail to grasp that everyone is engaged in a continuous life-long war against all other cities. If we must eat together in order to be on our guard during times of war, 626a with a roster of sentinels and their officers to keep watch, we should do likewise in peacetime—for what most people call peace is nothing but a name, while in fact every city is by nature always in an undeclared war against every other. If you look at it this way, you will discover, I submit, that it is with war in mind that the Cretan lawgiver established all the institutions that govern our public and private life. He b endowed us with laws to stand guard on the understanding that those who fail to prevail in war derive no benefit from anything else, whether possession or practice, since all the goods of the vanquished go to the victors. ATH: You evidently have a well trained understanding, Stranger, of Cretan institutions. But please clarify one point for me about the criterion you gave for a well governed city. c You are saying, I gather, that its affairs must be arranged to make it victorious in war over other cities. Isn’t that so? CL: Absolutely, and I think that our friend here agrees with me. MEG: How, sir, could a Spartan answer any differently? 6 ATH: Do you think that this is correct about the relations between cities, but that between villages it is different? CL: Not at all. ATH: So is it the same there? CL: Yes. ATH: What about relations between households within villages and between individual men? Is it still the same? CL: It is the same. d ATH: And a man in relation to himself— should we think of him as one enemy pitted against another? What is our position here? CL: Well done, Stranger from Athens—for I would not want to address you, as hailing from Attica, when are evidently more deserving of an appellation invoking the goddess! You invoke quite correctly the fundamental principle that clarifies the matter and will enable you to discover the truth of our present contention. Everyone is the enemy of everyone else in public life, and in private each person is pitted against himself. e ATH: My goodness! What do you mean? CL: In the latter contest, Stranger, victory over oneself is the highest and most excellent of all victories, whereas being “worsted by oneself” is the most shameful and wretched of defeats. These ways of speaking indicates that each of us is engaged in an internal war against himself. ATH: Well, let’s apply this thesis back to the previous cases. Since each of us as a single individual is either master of or worsted by himself, 627a should we say that the same thing happens in households, villages, and cities? Or should we deny it? CL: You are asking whether some of them are masters of themselves and others worsted by themselves? ATH: Yes. CL: Another good question. This sort of thing most emphatically does occur, especially within cities.
Recommended publications
  • Plato Journal
    DEZ 2013 ISSN 2079-7567 I3 eISSN 2183-4105 Established 1989 http://platosociety.org/ Papers William H.F. Altman “The Missing Speech of the Absent Fourth: Reader Response and Plato’s Timaeus-Critias” David Levy, “Socrates vs. Callicles: Examination and Ridicule in Plato’s Gorgias.” Nathalie Nercam, “En tout et pour tout (Théétète 204a-210b)” Matthew Robinson, “Competition, Imagery, and Pleasure in Plato’s Republic, 1-91” Scott J. Senn, “Ignorance or Irony in Plato’s Socrates?: A Look Beyond Avowals and Disavowals of Knowledge” INTERNATIONAL PLATO SOCIETY PLATO INTERNATIONAL PL ATO Société Platonicienne JOURNALInternationale Associazione Internazionale dei Platonisti Sociedad Internacional de Platonistas Internationale Platon-Gesellschaft Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra Coimbra Universiy Press 2 | Enicaper ficaed susta nondin is es nonim et dolore CREDITS EditOriAL BOARD INterNAtiONAL PLATO Francisco Gonzalez SOcietY EXecutiVE University of Ottawa COmmittee (2013-16) Irmgard Männlein-Robert President: Francisco Bravo Universität Tübingen Universidad Central de Venezuela Angela Ulacco President: Gabriele Cornelli Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg Universidade de Brasília Vice President: Tom Robinson ScieNtific BOArd University of Toronto Luc Brisson Ex-President: Mauro Tulli CNRS – UPR76 Centre Jean-Pépin, Paris Università degli Studi di Pisa Tomás Calvo Next President: Luc Brisson Universidad Complutense, Madrid CNRS – UPR76 Centre Jean-Pépin, Paris John Dillon Next President: Olivier Renaut Trinity College, Dublin Université Paris
    [Show full text]
  • Chaotic Descriptor Table
    Castle Oldskull Supplement CDT1: Chaotic Descriptor Table These ideas would require a few hours’ the players back to the temple of the more development to become truly useful, serpent people, I decide that she has some but I like the direction that things are going backstory. She’s an old jester-bard so I’d probably run with it. Maybe I’d even treasure hunter who got to the island by redesign dungeon level 4 to feature some magical means. This is simply because old gnome vaults and some deep gnome she’s so far from land and trade routes that lore too. I might even tie the whole it’s hard to justify any other reason for her situation to the gnome caves of C. S. Lewis, to be marooned here. She was captured by or the Nome King from L. Frank Baum’s the serpent people, who treated her as Ozma of Oz. Who knows? chattel, but she barely escaped. She’s delirious, trying to keep herself fed while she struggles to remember the command Example #13: word for her magical carpet. Malamhin of the Smooth Brow has some NPC in the Wilderness magical treasures, including a carpet of flying, a sword, some protection from serpents thingies (scrolls, amulets?) and a The PCs land on a deadly magical island of few other cool things. Talking to the PCs the serpent people, which they were meant and seeing their map will slowly bring her to explore years ago and the GM promptly back to her senses … and she wants forgot about it.
    [Show full text]
  • Law and the Metaethics of Discord
    Katja Maria Vogt, katjavogt.com, Columbia University 1 Law and the Metaethics of Discord, NYU Colloquium in Legal, Political, and Social Philosophy, Draft 08-2020 For: Special issue on the Normativity of Law, Ancient Philosophy Today: Dialogoi Law and the Metaethics of Discord Plato’s Euthyphro, I argue, lays out a metaethics that responds to persistent and unresolved value disagreement, and that is a genuine contender for us today. With this proposal, I reject centuries of scholarship, not to speak of countless anthologies and syllabi in ethics and the philosophy of law.1 The Euthyphro begins with three cases of unresolved value disagreement. These cases are to be adjudicated by the law, which turns out to be difficult. Today if an author starts with three examples, we expect that the subsequent text is going to address them. This, I submit, is the structure of the Euthyphro. Against my reading, discussions of the Euthyphro tend to focus almost exclusively on a brief section in which Plato discusses what is now known as the Euthyphro Problem. Socrates asks whether the gods love the pious because it is pious, or whether the pious is pious because it is loved by the gods. In the idiom of contemporary metaethics, the puzzle may seem to be this: is value attitude-independent or is value conferred by attitudes?2 Alternatively, in the idiom of traditional Divine Command Theory, do the gods —or, does God, since Divine Command Theory tends to be monotheistic—recognize value, or is value conferred by divine approval?3 1 Much of the literature on the Euthyphro focuses on two out of fifteen pages of the dialogue, where the so- called Euthyphro Problem is discussed.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Forms 1 Theory of Forms
    Theory of Forms 1 Theory of Forms Plato's theory of Forms or theory of Ideas[1] [2] [3] asserts that non-material abstract (but substantial) forms (or ideas), and not the material world of change known to us through sensation, possess the highest and most fundamental kind of reality.[4] When used in this sense, the word form is often capitalized.[5] Plato speaks of these entities only through the characters (primarily Socrates) of his dialogues who sometimes suggest that these Forms are the only true objects of study that can provide us with genuine knowledge; thus even apart from the very controversial status of the theory, Plato's own views are much in doubt.[6] Plato spoke of Forms in formulating a possible solution to the problem of universals. Forms Terminology: the Forms and the forms The English word "form" may be used to translate two distinct concepts that concerned Plato—the outward "form" or appearance of something, and "Form" in a new, technical nature, that never ...assumes a form like that of any of the things which enter into her; ... But the forms which enter into and go out of her are the likenesses of real existences modelled after their patterns in a wonderful and inexplicable manner.... The objects that are seen, according to Plato, are not real, but literally mimic the real Forms. In the allegory of the cave expressed in Republic, the things that are ordinarily perceived in the world are characterized as shadows of the real things, which are not perceived directly. That which the observer understands when he views the world mimics the archetypes of the many types and properties (that is, of universals) of things observed.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Symposium
    PLATO’S SYMPOSIUM Continuum Reader’s Guides Continuum’s Reader’s Guides are clear, concise and accessible introduc- tions to classic works of philosophy. Each book explores the major themes, historical and philosophical context and key passages of a major philosophical text, guiding the reader towards a thorough under- standing of often demanding material. Ideal for undergraduate students, the guides provide an essential resource for anyone who needs to get to grips with a philosophical text. Reader’s Guides available from Continuum Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics – Christopher Warne Aristotle’s Politics – Judith A. Swanson and C. David Corbin Berkeley’s Principles of Human Knowledge – Alasdair Richmond Berkeley’s Three Dialogues – Aaron Garrett Deleuze and Guattari’s Capitalism and Schizophrenia – Ian Buchanan Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition – Joe Hughes Derrida’s Writing and Difference – Sarah Wood Descartes’ Meditations – Richard Francks Hegel’s Philosophy of Right – David Rose Heidegger’s Being and Time – William Blattner Heidegger’s Later Writings – Lee Braver Hobbes’s Leviathan – Laurie M. Johnson Bagby Hume’s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion – Andrew Pyle Hume’s Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding – Alan Bailey and Dan O’Brien Kant’s Critique of Aesthetic Judgement – Fiona Hughes Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason – James Luchte Kant’s Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals – Paul Guyer Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions – John Preston Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding – William Uzgalis Locke’s Second Treatise of Government – Paul Kelly Mill’s On Liberty – Geoffrey Scarre Mill’s Utilitarianism – Henry West Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morals – Daniel Conway Plato’s Republic – Luke Purshouse Rousseau’s The Social Contract – Christopher Wraight Sartre’s Being and Nothingness – Sebastian Gardner Spinoza’s Ethics – Thomas J.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Does Plato's Laws Exist?
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 2017 Why Does Plato's Laws Exist? Harold Parker University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Parker, Harold, "Why Does Plato's Laws Exist?" (2017). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 2515. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/2515 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/2515 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Why Does Plato's Laws Exist? Abstract If the ideal city described at length in Plato’s Republic is a perfect and philosophically attractive encapsulation of Plato’s political philosophy, why does Plato go on to write the Laws – which also describes an ideal city, albeit one very different from the Republic? The fundamental challenge of scholarship concerning the Laws is to supply a comprehensive account of the dialogue that explains all aspects of it while also distinguishing the Laws from the Republic in a way that does not devalue the Laws as a mere afterthought to the Republic. Past attempts at meeting this challenge, I argue, can be classified under the headings of the democratic, legal, and demiurgic approaches. Although each is prima facie plausible, each also faces its own set of problems. Furthermore, none are truly capable of explaining the Laws in its full specificity; the intricate array of customs, regulations, and practices making up the life of the city described form a complex totality not reducible to the concept of democracy, the rule of law, or demiurgy.
    [Show full text]
  • Notations on the Song Commentary by Gregory of Nyssa 1.Pdf
    Notations on the Commentary on the Song of Songs by Gregory of Nyssa (one of two) Introduction This document is the second of a three part series which consists in examining the three commentaries on the Song of Songs by Origen, Gregory of Nyssa and Bernard of Clairvaux. The first is completed and posted on the Lectio Divina Homepage under the title Notations on the Commentary on the Song of Songs by Origen. A third document will follow the current one and will be entitled Notations on the Commentary on the Song of Songs by Bernard of Clairvaux. Gregory’s Commentary on the Song of Songs consists of a Prologue and fifteen homilies, the same format used in these notations. Except for the Prologue, the notations are preceded by verses from the Song of Songs, the subject matter on which Gregory of Nyssa comments. These verses are included in order to put the notations in better context. As for the key sentences lifted from the Commentary itself, they are listed in accord with the critical edition of the Greek text (Gregorii Nysseni in Canticum Canticorum edited by Hermann Langerbeck, Leiden, 1960). The first numeral represents the page and the second numeral represents the line within that page. This enables the reader to access quickly a given word either by a forward or backward search. Obviously the references become increasingly common as the document progresses; towards the beginning it is employed seldom because the words are new. After the posting of excerpts from Gregory of Nyssa’s Commentary and before the paragraph consisting of notations there is inserted a string of the transliterated Greek words (all in italics) from the excerpt just cited including any preposition that has been noted.
    [Show full text]
  • Textos Herméticos
    TEXTOS HERMÉTICOS INTRODUCCIÓN, TRADUCCIÓN Y NOTAS DE XAVIER RENAU NEBOT f e EDITORIAL GREDOS BIBLIOTECA CLÁSICA GREDOS, 268 A se se n |ΐιι i a la sección griega: C arlos G arcía G u m .. Ντμ.ιιιι Ius normas ile la IV C. G., la traducción de este volumen ha sido u-visiiilii j»>i Ml ui i i>i s I,όι·ι:/. Sai.va. <n i;i)H()i<iAi.(iRi:iK)S, s. a . Sánchez 1’acheco, 85, Madrid, 1999. Depósito Legal: M. 40654-1999. ISBN 84-249-2246-8. Impreso en España. Printed in Spain. Gráficas Cóndor, S. A. Esteban Terradas, 12. Polígono Industrial. Leganés (Madrid), 1999. INTRODUCCIÓN 1. HERMES, EL DIOS TRES VECES MUY GRANDE Hermes Trimegisto es la denominación griega del dios egipcio Tot1. La identificación es temprana: ya Heródoto (II, 138), dice ‘Templo de Hermes’ para referirse a un tem­ plo de Tot. Hacia finales del s. m a.C. ya es un hecho co­ mún; en el decreto de la piedra de Rosetta2 Tot es el ‘Her­ mes grande grande’ que ayuda a Horus a reconquistar el delta. Cicerón, en fin, a mediados del s. i a. C., designa co­ mo quinto Hermes a «aquél que es adorado en Feneo (Arca­ dia), del que se dice que mató a Argos y por ello huyó a Egipto, donde enseñó a los egipcios las leyes y la escritura: los egipcios lo denominan Theúth y llaman de la misma manera al primer mes del año3». 1 Cf. W. K.ROI.L, «Hermes Trismegistos», en A.
    [Show full text]
  • UNIVERSITY of CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO Democratic Education in The
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO Democratic Education in the Works of Plato A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Political Science by Richard A. Barrett Committee in charge: Professor Tracy B. Strong, Chair Professor Page duBois Professor Fonna Forman Professor Marcel Hénaff Professor Gerry Mackie 2014 Copyright Richard A. Barrett, 2014 All rights reserved. The Dissertation of Richard A. Barrett is approved, and it is acceptable in quality and form for publication on microfilm and electronically: ______________________________________________ ______________________________________________ ______________________________________________ Chair UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO 2014 iii DEDICATION To those who have shared conversations about our world with me. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS Signature Page……………………………………………………………………...…iii Dedication……………………………………………………………………………..iv Table of Contents……………………………………………………………………....v Vita…………………………………………………………………………………....vii Abstract of the Dissertation.………………………………………………………....viii Introduction: Plato and the Problem of Democratic Education ..................................... 1 Chapter 1 Reading Plato: Plato and Xenophon as Teachers and Poets ............. 7 1.1 Introduction ...................................................................................................... 7 1.2 Comparison of Apologies ................................................................................ 8 1.3 Plato on the Relationship of Philosophy,
    [Show full text]
  • PROCEEDINGS Table of Contents Basanizein
    PROCEEDINGS Table of Contents Basanizein. Practical Experience as the Touchstone of Platonic Education ................................................. 1 Francisco Benoni (University of Verona) Concealment, Compulsion, and the Educated Citizen of the Protagoras .................................................... 8 Ryan Drake (Fairfield University) Imag(in)ing Nature and Art in Plato’s Phaedrus......................................................................................... 20 Marina McCoy (Boston University) Aristotle, Philosophêmata, and Aristotle’s Disciplinary History of Philosophy .......................................... 25 Chris Moore (Pennsylvania State University) Aristotle on Pleonexia, Proper Self-Love and the Unity of Justice.............................................................. 32 Marta Jimenez (Emory university) Philodemus and the Peripatetics on the Role of Anger in the Virtuous Life .............................................. 42 David Kaufmann (Transylvania University) Among the Boys and Young Men: Philosophy and Masculinity in Plato’s Lysis ......................................... 50 Yancy Dominick (Seattle University) The Dis-Community of Lovers: Kinship in the Lysis ..................................................................................... 58 Benjamin Frazer-Simser (DePaul University) How to Speak Kata Phusin: Magico-religious Speech in Heraclitus ............................................................ 71 Jessica Elbert Decker (California State University) Heraclitus and the Riddle
    [Show full text]
  • George Spencer-Brown's Laws of Form Fifty Years On
    MATHEMATICS TEACHING RESEARCH JOURNAL 161 Special Issue on Philosophy of Mathematics Education Summer 2020 Vol 12 no 2 George Spencer-Brown’s laws of form fifty years on: why we should be giving it more attention in mathematics education Steven Watson University of Cambridge Abstract: George Spencer-Brown’s Laws of Forms was first published in 1969. In the fifty years since its publication, it has influenced mathematicians, scientists, philosophers, and sociologists. Its influence on mathematics education has been negligible. In this paper, I present a brief introduction to the theory and its philosophical underpinnings. And I set out an argument why Laws of Form should be given more attention in mathematics education. Introduction Last year (2019) marked the 50th anniversary of the publication of Laws of Form (LoF), written by George Spencer-Brown (1969). Bertrand Russell described Laws of Form as, “a calculus of great power and simplicity. Not since Euclid’s Elements have we seen anything like it” (Homes, 2016). Heinz von Foerster, pioneer of second order cybernetics, offered no reserve in his praise for Spencer-Brown’s Laws of Form. The laws of form have finally been written! With a "Spencer-Brown" transistorized power razor (a Twentieth Century model of Occam's razor) G. Spencer-Brown cuts smoothly through two millennia of growth of the most prolific and persistent of semantic weeds, presenting us with his superbly written Laws of Form. This Herculean task which now, in retrospect, is of profound simplicity rests on his discovery of the form of laws. Laws are not descriptions, they are commands, injunctions: "Do!" Thus the first constructive proposition in this book (page 3) is the injunction: "Draw a distinction!" an exhortation to perform the primordial creative act (von Foerster, 1971, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Alexander Pruss Aristotelian Forms and Laws of Nature
    Alexander Pruss Aristotelian Forms and Laws of Nature Analiza i Egzystencja 24, 115-132 2013 „Analiza i Egzystencja” 24 (2013) ISSN 1734-9923 ALEXANDER PRUSS* ARISTOTELIAN FORMS AND LAWS OF NATURE Abstract Aristotelian Forms are mysterious entities. I offer an account of them as entities that make the laws of nature be laws. The Aristotelian ontology is fundamentally an anti-Humean ontology: Not only are laws a reality over and beyond regularities, but that in virtue of which they are laws is in fact that which is most truly called substance. If we further take it, say, on ethical grounds, that there are individual forms, then we get a multiplicity of substances in the universe, including multiple substances of the same sort, and the laws of nature end up being grounded in their powers. But we have global regularities, then, only because there is coordination between the lawmakers, or forms, of the solo doings of individual entities, a coordination that entails global patterns. Keywords: Aristotle, forms, laws of nature, metaphysics, ontology, matter * Alexander Pruss—Professor of Philosophy at Baylor University, Director of Graduate Studies of Philosophy. His publications include the books One Body: An Essay in Christian Sexual Ethics and The Principle of Sufficient Reason: A Reassessment, as well as articles in metaphysics, ethics, philosophy of religion, formal epistemology and pure mathematics. Blog: http://alexanderpruss.blogspot.com; web page: http://alexanderpruss. com. E-mail: [email protected]. 116 Alexander Pruss I. Introduction We may have a bit of a handle on roughly what kinds of entities the Platonic Forms are.
    [Show full text]