Minimalist Conception of Democracy: a Defense

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Minimalist Conception of Democracy: a Defense Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense Adam Przeworski nal deliberation, and to be represented as the Introduction view of the informed majority, the fact that rulers are elected is of no particular significance. I want to defend a ‘‘minimalist,’’ Schumpeterian, Voting is just a time-saving expedient (Buchanan conception of democracy, by minimalist, Pop- and Tullock 1962) and majority rule is just a perian, standards. In Schumpeter’s (1942) con- technically convenient way of identifying what ception, democracy is just a system in which everyone would or should have agreed to. Yet if rulers are selected by competitive elections. Pop- the point of departure is that in any society there per (1962: 124) defends it as the only system in are conflicts, of values and of interests, electing which citizens can get rid of governments with- rulers appears nothing short of miraculous. out bloodshed. Let us put the consensualist view of democ- Since neither the position I wish to defend nor racy where it belongs—in the Museum of the claim in its favor are new, what do I defend Eighteenth-century Thought—and observe that them from? Perusing innumerable definitions, all societies are ridden with economic, cultural, one discovers that democracy has become an al- or moral conflicts. True, as the modernization tar on which everyone hangs his or her favorite theory (notably Coser 1959) emphasized, these ex voto. Almost all normatively desirable aspects conflicts can be ‘‘cross-cutting’’: they need not of political, and sometimes even of social and pit class against class or religion against religion. economic, life are credited as intrinsic to de- They can be attenuated by an ‘‘overlapping con- mocracy: representation, accountability, equal- sensus’’: consensus about practicalities compati- ity, participation, justice, dignity, rationality, ble with di¤erences of values (Rawls 1993). They security, freedom, . , the list goes on. We are may be also moderated by public discussion of repeatedly told that ‘‘unless democracy is x or both normative and technical reasons, although, generates x, . .’’ The ellipsis is rarely spelled out, as I have argued above, deliberation is a two- but it insinuates either that a system in which edged sword, for it may lead just to solidifying governments are elected is not worthy of being conflicting views. Yet in the end, when all the called ‘‘democracy’’ unless x is fulfilled or that coalitions have been formed, the practical con- democracy in the minimal sense will not endure sensus has been elaborated, and all arguments unless x is satisfied.2 The first claim is normative, have been exhausted, conflicts remain. even if it often hides as a definition. The second My defense of the minimalist conception pro- is empirical. ceeds in two steps. I take it as obvious that Yet suppose this is all there is to democracy: that rulers are elected. Is it little? It depends on the point of departure.24 If one begins with a vi- 2. Widely cited statements in this vein are We¤ort sion of a basic harmony of interests, a common 1992 and Schmitter and Karl 1991, but the phrase is ubiquitous. Here is Shapiro (1996: 108): ‘‘If democracy good to be discovered and agreed to by a ratio- does not function to improve the circumstances of those who appeal to it, its legitimacy as a political sys- Excerpted from: Adam Przeworski, ‘‘Minimalist Con- tem will atrophy.’’ Even Kelsen (1988 [1929]: 38) poses ception of Democracy: A Defense.’’ In Democracy’s the threat that ‘‘Modern democracy will not live unless Value, edited by Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker- the Parliament will show itself an instrument appro- Cordo´n. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, priate for the solution of the social questions of the 1999. 6 Cambridge University Press, 1999. Reprinted hour.’’ with the permission of Cambridge University Press. 24. Shapiro (1996: 82) also takes this position. Defining Democracy 13 we want to avoid bloodshed, resolving conflicts Yet the very prospect that governments would through violence.25 Starting with this assump- alternate may induce the conflicting political tion, I first argue that the mere possibility of forces to comply with the rules rather than en- being able to change governments can avoid gage in violence, for the following reason. Al- violence. Secondly, I argue that being able to though the losers would be better o¤ in the short do it by voting has consequences of its own. run rebelling rather than accepting the outcome Popper’s defense of democracy is that it allows of the current round, if they have a su‰cient us to get rid of governments peacefully. But why chance to win and a su‰ciently large payo¤ in should we care about changing governments?26 the future rounds, they are better o¤ continuing My answer is that the very prospect that gov- to comply with the verdict of the coin toss rather ernments may change can result in a peaceful than fighting for power. Similarly, while the regulation of conflicts. To see this argument in winners would be better o¤ in the short run not its starkest form, assume that governments are tossing the coin again, they may be better o¤ in selected by a toss of a, not necessarily fair, coin: the long run peacefully leaving o‰ce rather than ‘‘heads’’ mean that the incumbents should provoking violent resistance to their usurpation remain in o‰ce, ‘‘tails’’ that they should leave. of power. Regulating conflicts by a coin toss Thus, a reading of the toss designates ‘‘winners’’ is then a self-enforcing equilibrium (Przeworski and ‘‘losers.’’ This designation is an instruction 1991: chap. 1). Bloodshed is avoided by the mere what the winners and the losers should and fact that, a` la Aristotle, the political forces expect should not do: the winners should move into a to take turns. White or Pink House or perhaps even a palacio; Suppose first that the winners of the coin while there they can take everything up to the toss get some predetermined part of the pie, constitutional constraint for themselves and their 1=2 < x < 1, while losers get the rest.27 Winners supporters, and they should toss the same coin decide at each time whether to hold elections at again when their term is up. The losers should the next time and losers whether to accept defeat not move into the House and should accept get- or to rebel. If democracy is repeated indefinitely ting not more than whatever is left. from t ¼ 0 on, the winner at t ¼ 0 expects to get Note that when the authorization to rule is DW ¼ x þ VW(e; x) and the loser at t ¼ 0 expects determined by a lottery, citizens have no elec- to get DL ¼ (1 À x) þ VL(1 À e; x), where V toral sanction, prospective or retrospective, and stands for the present value of continuing under the incumbents have no electoral incentives to democracy beyond the current round, e is the behave well while in o‰ce. Since electing gov- probability the current incumbent will win the ernments by a lottery makes their chances of next toss. Let ‘‘democratic equilibrium’’ stand survival independent of their conduct, there are for a pair of strategies in which the current win- no reasons to expect that governments act in a ners always hold tosses if they expect losers to representative fashion because they want to earn comply and the current losers always comply re-election: any link between elections and rep- if they expect the winners to hold tosses. Then resentation is severed. such an equilibrium exists if everyone is better o¤ under democracy than under rebellion: if 25. I am not arguing against Locke that violence is DW > RW and DL > RL, where R stands for the never justified, just that a system that systematically expected values of violent conflict for each of the avoids it is preferable to one that does not. two parties. 26. I want to thank Ignacio Sanchez-Cuenca for pos- ing this question. 27. This analysis is based on joint work with James Fearon, still in progress. Chapter 1 14 Moreover, the prospect of alternation may mine the strength of the adversaries in an open induce moderation while in o‰ce. Suppose that conflict. Hence, to avoid violence, the conflicting the current incumbent can either manipulate the political forces adopt the following device: agree probability, e, of being re-elected or can decide over those issues that can be specified and allow what share of the pie, x A [0; 1], to take, or both. the residual control to alternate according to There are some initial values {e(0); x(0)}; at t ¼ 1 specified probabilities. In this sense, the consti- the coin is tossed and it designates winners tution specifies x, the limits on incumbents, and losers. Whoever is the winner now chooses and e, their chances in electoral competition, but {e(1); x(1)}: the rules for this round, etc. Hence, a random device decides who holds residual rules are not given ex ante: the incumbent control. manipulates them at will. Yet there are con- Yet we do not use random devices; we vote. ditions under which a democratic equilibrium What di¤erence does that make? exists in which the incumbents do not grab Voting is an imposition of a will over a will. everything. If the cost of rebellion is su‰ciently When a decision is reached by voting, some high for both, each incumbent will prefer to people must submit to an opinion di¤erent from moderate its behavior while in o‰ce under de- theirs or to a decision contrary to their inter- mocracy rather than provoke a rebellion by the est.28 Voting authorizes compulsion.
Recommended publications
  • Democracy's Value
    Democracy's Value Edited by Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-CordoÂn published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge, CB2 2RU, UK http://www.cup.cam.ac.uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011±4211, USA http://www.cup.org 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia # Cambridge University Press 1999 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 1999 Printed in the United Kingdom at the University Press, Cambridge Typeset in 10/12pt Plantin [ce] A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 0 521 64357 0 hardback ISBN 0 521 64388 0 paperback Contents List of contributors page xi Preface xiii 1. Promises and disappointments: reconsidering democracy's value 1 ian shapiro and casiano hacker-cordOÂ n Part I: Minimal democracy 21 2. Minimalist conception of democracy: a defense 23 adam przeworski 3. Does democracy engender justice? 56 john e. roemer 4. Democracy and other goods 69 partha dasgupta and eric maskin Part II: Beyond minimalism 91 5. Democracy and development: a complex relationship 93 pranab bardhan 6. Death and taxes: extractive equality and the development of democratic institutions 112 margaret levi 7. Democracy and development? 132 john dunn 8. State, civil society, and social justice 141 iris marion young 9. Republican freedom and contestatory democratization 163 philip pettit ix x Contents 10.
    [Show full text]
  • Capitalism and Social Democracy, by Adam Przeworski (Cambridge University Press, 1986)
    The African e-Journals Project has digitized full text of articles of eleven social science and humanities journals. This item is from the digital archive maintained by Michigan State University Library. Find more at: http://digital.lib.msu.edu/projects/africanjournals/ Available through a partnership with Scroll down to read the article. DEKADT REVIEW ARTICLE Review of: Capitalism and Social Democracy, by Adam Przeworski (Cambridge University Press, 1986). Raphael de Kadt This brilliant study by Adam Przeworski must surely become mandatory reading not only for anyone who takes his or her socialist commitments seriously but also for anyone who wishes adequately to understand the relationship between class and electoral politics in the countries of advanced capitalism. The principal burden of Przeworski's intricate and multifaceted analysis of the dilemmas facing social democratic parties in the twentieth century is to show that the decision to participate in electoral politics necessarily constrains the capacity of such parties to effect, through command of the parliamentary system, a transition to socialism. This incapacity turns on the pivotal fact that nowhere (with the possible brief exception of Belgium in 1912) has the industrial working class constituted a majority of the population. In the countries of Western Europe, for example, 'from 1890 to 1980 the proletariat continued to be a minority of the population' (p23). The implications of this fact for parliamentary socialism have been profound, for the essence of the parliamentary system is that, in order to govern, parties must be able to claim representation of an effective majority of the population. Given the minority status of the industrial working class, those parties claiming to represent it have been forced into securing alliances with other classes - and white collar workers, petite bourgeois, students and retirees have all been targeted as potential allies in the socialist cause.
    [Show full text]
  • Adam Przeworski: Capitalism, Democracy and Science
    ADAM PRZEWORSKI: CAPITALISM, DEMOCRACY AND SCIENCE Interview with Adam Przeworski conducted and edited by Gerardo L. Munck February 24, 2003, New York, New York Prepared for inclusion in Gerardo L. Munck and Richard Snyder, Passion, Craft, and Method in Comparative Politics. Training and Intellectual Formation: From Poland to the United States Q: How did you first get interested in studying politics? What impact did growing up in Poland have on your view of politics? A: Given that I was born in May of 1940, nine months after the Germans had invaded and occupied Poland, any political event, even a minor one, was immediately interpreted in terms of its consequences for one’s private life. All the news was about the war. I remember my family listening to clandestine radio broadcasts from the BBC when I was three or four years old. After the war, there was a period of uncertainty, and then the Soviet Union basically took over. Again, any rumbling in the Soviet Union, any conflict between the Soviet Union and the United States, was immediately seen in terms of its consequences for our life. It was like this for me until I first left for the US in 1961, right after the Berlin Wall went up. One’s everyday life was permeated with international, macro-political events. Everything was political. But I never thought of studying politics. For one thing, in Europe at that time there really was no political science. What we had was a German and Central European tradition that was called, translating from German, “theory of the state and law.” This included Carl Schmitt and Hans Kelsen, the kind of stuff that was taught normally at law schools.
    [Show full text]
  • What's Left of the Left: Democrats and Social Democrats in Challenging
    What’s Left of the Left What’s Left of the Left Democrats and Social Democrats in Challenging Times Edited by James Cronin, George Ross, and James Shoch Duke University Press Durham and London 2011 © 2011 Duke University Press All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America on acid- free paper ♾ Typeset in Charis by Tseng Information Systems, Inc. Library of Congress Cataloging- in- Publication Data appear on the last printed page of this book. Contents Acknowledgments vii Introduction: The New World of the Center-Left 1 James Cronin, George Ross, and James Shoch Part I: Ideas, Projects, and Electoral Realities Social Democracy’s Past and Potential Future 29 Sheri Berman Historical Decline or Change of Scale? 50 The Electoral Dynamics of European Social Democratic Parties, 1950–2009 Gerassimos Moschonas Part II: Varieties of Social Democracy and Liberalism Once Again a Model: 89 Nordic Social Democracy in a Globalized World Jonas Pontusson Embracing Markets, Bonding with America, Trying to Do Good: 116 The Ironies of New Labour James Cronin Reluctantly Center- Left? 141 The French Case Arthur Goldhammer and George Ross The Evolving Democratic Coalition: 162 Prospects and Problems Ruy Teixeira Party Politics and the American Welfare State 188 Christopher Howard Grappling with Globalization: 210 The Democratic Party’s Struggles over International Market Integration James Shoch Part III: New Risks, New Challenges, New Possibilities European Center- Left Parties and New Social Risks: 241 Facing Up to New Policy Challenges Jane Jenson Immigration and the European Left 265 Sofía A. Pérez The Central and Eastern European Left: 290 A Political Family under Construction Jean- Michel De Waele and Sorina Soare European Center- Lefts and the Mazes of European Integration 319 George Ross Conclusion: Progressive Politics in Tough Times 343 James Cronin, George Ross, and James Shoch Bibliography 363 About the Contributors 395 Index 399 Acknowledgments The editors of this book have a long and interconnected history, and the book itself has been long in the making.
    [Show full text]
  • SS475: Comparative Political Institutions
    SS475: Comparative Political Institutions DEPARTMENT OF SOCIAL SCIENCES UNITED STATES MILITARY ACADEMY Course Overview “Institutions are the rules of the game in a society or, more formally, are the humanly devised constraints that shape human interaction. In consequence they structure incentives in human exchange, whether political, social, or economic. Institutional change shapes the way societies evolve through time 1 and hence is the key to understanding historical change.” The study of political institutions – “the rules of the game” that structure political competition within all states – sits at the center of comparative politics as a discipline and is the subject of SS475. In particular, we will focus on explaining the institutions that relate broadly to a country’s “regime type.” Though regime type is often boiled down to a distinction between democracy vs. dictatorship, political regimes are better understood as collections of institutions that regulate political power within a polity: how is power gained and lost? How is political power transferred? How is power divided, dispersed, or consolidated? By whom is political power granted and by whom is it taken away? Who has the right to exercise political power, and who does not? When viewed in comparative perspective, democracies, dictatorships, and “hybrid” regimes alike can all be analyzed along these dimensions and debates. Such a comparative analysis is the overarching objective of SS475. Part I of the course (“Foundations of Political Regimes”) begins with a critical assessment of the concept of democracy, exploring key debates in political science over how democracy should be defined and measured. From there we shift our attention to a rich literature that seeks to understand which – if any – economic and cultural factors influence whether countries become democracies or dictatorship.
    [Show full text]
  • 7976-1 Comparative Political Economy (Kim)
    © Wonik Kim POLI 7976 Comparative Political Economy THE POLITICS OF GROWTH AND INEQUALITY IN THE CAPITAL-NATION-STATE Monday 12:00 – 2:50 pm, fall 2015, 0001 Hatcher Hall Wonik Kim, [email protected], 225-578-5354 OH: 12:20 – 1:20 pm on Tuesday and Thursday, or by appointment Stubbs 229, Department of Political Science The leitmotif of this seminar is the politics of growth and inequality in the capitalist system. Traditional political economy studied this topic, by assuming that environments and political institutions are given and neutral with regard to the market allocations; they are there but they do not act. New political economy differs from the traditional approach in its treatment of politics. It accepts that political institutions and their relations to the economy and society are populated by actors who have interests/ideologies/faiths and pursue them. Hence, this course is based on the belief that socioeconomic development is fundamentally a political phenomenon. Another firm belief is that the politics of growth and inequality should be understood in terms of capitalism historically embedded in particular conditions. A warning: political scientists cannot study political economy without knowing some sort of economics, as we cannot study political history without dealing with history. So, we will study economic theories and formulations as well. The first part of the course examines the fundamentals of the capitalist system – the system of “the trinity of the capital-nation-state” (Karatani 2014), by reading Polanyi, Schumpeter, Gramsci, and Marx (mostly as a political observer, not as an economist). The second part provides a critical evaluation (with some methodological comment) of the main theories and empirics of the politics of inequality under the so-called “advanced” capitalist democracies.
    [Show full text]
  • MARGARET LEVI Sara Miller Mccune Director
    MARGARET LEVI Sara Miller McCune Director, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences at Stanford Professor of Political Science, Stanford University Senior Fellow, Stanford Woods Institute for the Environment Jere L. Bacharach Professor Emerita of International Studies, University of Washington CASBS @ Stanford University 75 Alta Road Stanford, CA 94305 [email protected] Education Ph.D. Harvard University 1974 (Government) A.B. Bryn Mawr College 1968 (Political Science, cum laude) Work History Director, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences @ Stanford University, 2014- Professor of Political Science, Stanford University, 2014- Senior Fellow, Stanford Woods Institute of the Environment, 2016- Professor of Political Science, University of Washington, 1987-2014 (went half time in 2009) Senior Fellow, Watson Institute of International Studies, Brown University, 2013-14 Chair in U.S. Politics, United States Studies Centre at the University of Sydney, 2009-13 Director, CHAOS (Comparative and Historical Analysis of Organizations and States) Center, UW, 2002 Harry Bridges Chair and Director, University of Washington Harry Bridges Center for Labor Studies, 1996-2000 Associate Professor of Political Science, University of Washington, 1981-87 Assistant Professor of Political Science and Public Affairs, University of Washington, 1974-81 Research Associate, Organizational Development, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 1973-74 Honors and Awards Johan Skytte Prize, 2019 Honorary Doctorate (Honoris Causa), Universidad Carlos
    [Show full text]
  • Analytical Marxism’ Marxism?
    Chapter Four Is ‘Analytical Marxism’ Marxism? Introduction G.A. Cohen, Jon Elster, John Roemer – without question, these are prolifi c writers with an impressive series of articles and books, who have become a signifi cant presence in commentaries and discussions of Marxism in recent years. My fi rst inkling, though, that more had emerged on the scene came from a 1983 article by John Gray (passed on by a sceptical friend); for the 1983 article hailed the emergence of ‘a powerful new school of Analytical Marxism, led by such outstanding fi gures as G.A. Cohen, Jon Elster and John Roemer, with whose works the future of Marxism, if it has any, must henceforth be associated’.1 Is there indeed such a school? The evidence on the existence of somesuch self-defi ned group is overwhelming. In his Making Sense of Marx, Elster notes that Cohen’s Karl Marx’s Theory of History came as a ‘revelation’: ‘Overnight it changed the standards of rigour and clarity that were required to write on Marx and Marxism.’ Accordingly, he notes, a small group of like-minded colleagues formed and began a series of annual meetings in 1979. Their discussions were decisive for the shaping of Elster’s book – and, 1 Gray 1983, p. 1461. 40 • Chapter Four in particular, the contributions of Roemer (subsequently stated in his ‘path- breaking’ A General Theory of Exploitation and Class) were ‘crucial’.2 In turn, Roemer begins the latter book by noting his particular indebtedness to Cohen and Elster, indicating among those who were helpful several others who also appear on Elster’s
    [Show full text]
  • The Recasting of Chinese Socialism: the Chinese New Left Since 2000 China Information 2018, Vol
    CIN0010.1177/0920203X18760416China InformationShi et al. 760416research-article2018 Research dialogue chiINFORMATION na The recasting of Chinese socialism: The Chinese New Left since 2000 China Information 2018, Vol. 32(1) 139 –159 © The Author(s) 2018 Reprints and permissions: sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav Shi Anshu https://doi.org/10.1177/0920203X18760416DOI: 10.1177/0920203X18760416 Tsinghua University, China journals.sagepub.com/home/cin François Lachapelle University of British Columbia, Canada Matthew Galway University of British Columbia, Canada Abstract In post-Mao China, a group of Chinese intellectuals who formed what became the New Left (新左派) sought to renew socialism in China in a context of globalization and the rise of social inequalities they associated with neo-liberalism. As they saw it, China’s market reform and opening to the world had not brought greater equality and prosperity for all Chinese citizens. As part of China Information’s research dialogue on the intellectual public sphere in China, this article provides a historical survey of the development of the contemporary Chinese New Left, exploring the range of ideas that characterized this intellectual movement. It takes as its focus four of the most prominent New Left figures and their positions in the ongoing debate about China’s future: Wang Shaoguang, Cui Zhiyuan, Wang Hui, and Gan Yang. Keywords contemporary China, market reform, end of history, New Left, Chinese socialism, Maoism, democracy, statism Corresponding author: Shi Anshu, School of Humanities, Tsinghua University, Haidian District, Beijing, 100084, China. Email: [email protected] 140 China Information 32(1) By the Cold War’s end, people suddenly discovered ‘the end of history’, and there appeared to be no alternative to the liberal economic order of or as envisaged by Francis Fukuyama.
    [Show full text]
  • Consider a Definition Meant to Pick out the Main Characteristics of a Modern Political Regime of a Distinctive Sort
    ©Casiano Hacker-Cordón (1999-2001) 1 Electoral Legitimation, Polyarchy, and Democratic Legitimacy1 As a concept, democracy is notoriously prone to a multiplicity of interpretations. The definition of democracy is contested, perhaps not “essentially” so in any technical sense, but hotly contested nonetheless. (Gallie 1957; Connolly 1974; Hurley 1989: 46- 50). Take, for instance, the disputation over the meaning and practical implications of the concept during the recent historical era of global Cold War. The anticommunist intelligentsia concocted a dichotomy between ‘liberal democracy’ and ‘totalitarianism’ to distinguish the good regimes of the ‘Free World’ from the evil, freedom-infringing regimes of one-party socialist states. (e.g., Brzezinski & Friedrich 1965). The antiauthoritarian intelligentsia critical of both illiberal one-party rule and capitalist modes of domination, for its part, distinguished ‘bourgeois’ or ‘capitalist’ democracy from the ‘real’ or ‘socialist’ democracy that elections under universal adult suffrage makes possible. (e.g., MacPherson 1972, Cohen & Rogers 1983). Writing in the wake of the end of the Cold War, Honderich (1994) still distinguished between the ‘hierarchic’ democracy of the more economically developed capitalist national states and the ‘egalitarian’ democracy that constitutionally privileges socioeconomic sufficiency and equality. I share the view that what passes for ‘democracy’ in the contemporary world is far from delivering on the promise of egalitarian social relations which people throughout the world rightly associate with the idea. It would be both historically ironic and politically sad if the fall of the Soviet Union should result in the rhetorical disarmament of the antiauthoritarian intelligentsia vis-à-vis the defenders of a pluriversal world order of capitalist national states.
    [Show full text]
  • Juan Linz, Presidentialism, and Democracy: a Critical Appraisal Author(S): Scott Mainwaring and Matthew S
    Juan Linz, Presidentialism, and Democracy: A Critical Appraisal Author(s): Scott Mainwaring and Matthew S. Shugart Reviewed work(s): Source: Comparative Politics, Vol. 29, No. 4 (Jul., 1997), pp. 449-471 Published by: Ph.D. Program in Political Science of the City University of New York Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/422014 . Accessed: 16/07/2012 17:13 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Ph.D. Program in Political Science of the City University of New York is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Comparative Politics. http://www.jstor.org Juan Linz, Presidentialism, and Democracy A CriticalAppraisal Scott Mainwaringand MatthewS. Shugart Since the 1960s Juan J. Linz has been one of the world's foremost contributorsto our understandingof democracy, authoritarianism,and totalitarianism.Although many of his contributionshave had a significant impact, few have been as far- reaching as his essay "Presidentialor ParliamentaryDemocracy: Does It Make a Difference?," originally written in 1985. The essay argued that presidentialismis less likely than parliamentarismto sustain stable democraticregimes. It became a classic even in unpublished form. Among both policymakers and scholars it spawned a broaddebate about the merits and especially the liabilities of presidential government.Now that the definitive version of the essay has appeared,we believe that a critical appraisalis timely.
    [Show full text]
  • Property Rights and Environmental Resources
    |-e;'s-IJI;1|-L -~ - -; - I- ^ ~~~~~14 13 1 Public Disclosure Authorized PROPERTYRIGHTS ANDTHE ENVIRONMENT Public Disclosure Authorized SOCIALAND ECOLOGICAL ISSUES Public Disclosure Authorized Editedby SusanHanna and MohanMunasinghe Public Disclosure Authorized The BeijerInternational Institute of EcologicalEconomics v and The World Bank r< r:-Y- Property Rights and the Environment Social and Ecological Issues Edited by Susan Hanna and Mohan Munasinghe Beijer International Institute of Ecological Economics and The World Bank Copyright © 1995 The International Bank for Reconstruction and Development/The World Bank 1818 H Street, N.W. Washington, D.C. 20433U.S.A. This publication may be reproduced in whole or in part and in any form for educational or nonprofit uses, without special permission from the copyright holder, provided acknowledgment of the source is made. Copies may be sent to the Environment Department, The World Bank, 1818H Street N.W., Washington, D.C. 20433,U.S.A. and to the Beijer International Institute of EcologicalEconomics, the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences, P. 0. Box 50005,S-10405, Stockholm, Sweden. No use of this publication may be made for resale or other commercial purpose without the prior written permission of the copyright holders. The designations of geographical entities in this book, and the presentation of materials, do not imply the expression of any opinion whatsoever on the part of the World Bank or the Beijer Institute concerning the legal status of any country, territory, or area, or of its authorities, or concerning the delimitation of its frontiers or boundaries. The interpretations and conclusions in this report are those of the authors and do not necessarily represent the views of the World Bank or the Beijer Institute.
    [Show full text]