The Early Frankfurt School and Religion Also by Margarete Kohlenbach

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Early Frankfurt School and Religion Also by Margarete Kohlenbach The Early Frankfurt School and Religion Also by Margarete Kohlenbach DAS ENDE DER VOLLKOMMENHEIT: Zum Verständnis von Thomas Bernhards Korrektur WALTER BENJAMIN: Self-Reference and Religiosity Also by Raymond Geuss THE IDEA OF A CRITICAL THEORY HISTORY AND ILLUSION IN POLITICS MORALITY, CULTURE, AND HISTORY PUBLIC GOODS, PRIVATE GOODS POLITIK UND GLÜCK OUTSIDE ETHICS The Early Frankfurt School and Religion Edited by Margarete Kohlenbach and Raymond Geuss Editorial matter, selection, introduction © Margarete Kohlenbach and Raymond Geuss 2005 Chapter 2 © Raymond Geuss 2005 Chapter 4 © Margarete Kohlenbach 2005 Remaining chapters © Palgrave Macmillan Ltd 2005 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 2005 978-1-4039-3557-1 All rights reserved. No reproduction, copy or transmission of this publication may be made without written permission. No paragraph of this publication may be reproduced, copied or transmitted save with written permission or in accordance with the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, or under the terms of any licence permitting limited copying issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency, 90 Tottenham Court Road, London W1T 4LP. Any person who does any unauthorised act in relation to this publication may be liable to criminal prosecution and civil claims for damages. The authors have asserted their rights to be identified as the authors of this work in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. First published 2005 by PALGRAVE MACMILLAN Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 6XS and 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, N.Y. 10010 Companies and representatives throughout the world. PALGRAVE MACMILLAN is the global academic imprint of the Palgrave Macmillan division of St. Martin’s Press, LLC and of Palgrave Macmillan Ltd. Macmillan® is a registered trademark in the United States, United Kingdom and other countries. Palgrave is a registered trademark in the European Union and other countries. ISBN 978-1-349-51798-5 ISBN 978-0-230-52359-3 (eBook) DOI 10.1057/9780230523593 This book is printed on paper suitable for recycling and made from fully managed and sustained forest sources. A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data The early Frankfurt School and religion/edited by Margarete Kohlenbach and Raymond Geuss. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index. 1. Religion – Philosophy – History – 20th century. 2. Sociology – Philosophy – History – 20th century. 3. Critical theory. 4. Frankfurt school of sociology. 5. Institut fèr Sozialforschung (Frankfurt am Main, Germany) I. Kohlenbach, Margarete. II. Geuss, Raymond. BL51.E27 2004 200’.7’043––dc22 2004048940 10987654321 14 13 12 11 10 09 08 07 06 05 Contents Acknowledgements vii Abbreviations and Translations viii Notes on the Contributors ix Introduction: The Frankfurt School and the Problem of Religion 1 Margarete Kohlenbach and Raymond Geuss Part I Students, Theologians, Critical Theorists 1 Max Horkheimer’s Supposed ‘Religious Conversion’: A Semantic Analysis 15 Pascal Eitler 2 On the Usefulness and Uselessness of Religious Illusions 29 Raymond Geuss Part II Constructions of Religious Experience 3 Emerging ‘Orders’: The Contemporary Relevance of Religion and Teaching in Walter Benjamin’s Early Thought 45 Pierfrancesco Fiorato 4 Religion, Experience, Politics: On Erich Unger and Walter Benjamin 64 Margarete Kohlenbach 5 Allegory, Metonymy and Creatureliness: Walter Benjamin and the Religious Roots of Modern Art 85 Barnaba Maj Part III Legal Philosophy and Jewish Tradition 6 Law and Religion in Early Critical Theory 103 Chris Thornhill v vi Contents 7 Jewish Law and Tradition in the Early Work of Erich Fromm 128 David Groiser 8 Critical Theory and the New Thinking: A Preliminary Approach 145 Howard Caygill Part IV Dialectic of Enlightenment Reconsidered 9 Does Dialectic of Enlightenment Rest on Religious Foundations? 157 Rüdiger Bittner 10 Secularisation, Myth, Anti-Semitism: Adorno and Horkheimer’s Dialectic of Enlightenment and Cassirer’s Philosophy of Symbolic Forms 171 Gérard Raulet Notes 190 Bibliography 218 Index 234 Acknowledgements This book is the result of a working conference held at the Centre for Interdisciplinary Research (ZiF) at the University of Bielefeld in September 2003. The editors thank the Centre for its generous financial support, and for the professional and friendly assistance they received both before and during the conference. Thanks are also due to the Deutsches Literaturarchiv (Marbach) and the Max Horkheimer Archiv (Frankfurt/M.) for opening their collections to several contributors to this volume, and to Esther J. Ehrman ( Jerusalem) for granting us permission to quote from unpublished sources in Erich Unger’s estate. The University of Sussex and the University of Sassari supported the completion of this book by shouldering most of the translation costs. We are particularly grateful to Ladislaus Löb (Brighton) for the great skill and care with which he undertook the translation into English of three of the ten chapters, and for his general advice and bibliographical support. Our discussions at Bielefeld benefited a great deal from contributions by participants other than the authors assembled here. We thank espe- cially Martin Bauer of the Hamburg Institute of Social Research and Michael Gormann-Thelen (Hanover) of the Eugen Rosenstock-Huessy Society. We are also grateful to Wolfgang Braungart, Jürgen Frese and Michael Wolff of Bielefeld University, and to Martin Bonacker (Ham- burg), Martina Herrmann (Dortmund), Joachim Koch (Bad Oeynhau- sen), Christoph Lienkamp (Bremen), Timo Ogrzal (Hamburg), Johannes Sabel (Wipperfurth), Ingo Stucke (Bielefeld) and Andreas Seiverth (Frankfurt/M.). vii Abbreviations and Translations Primary and secondary sources are first cited by their complete title, then frequently with a characteristic abbreviation. Except for transla- tions acknowledged in the bibliography or the notes, all quotations from non-English sources were translated either by the authors or, in the case of Chapters 1, 3 and 10, by the translator Ladislaus Löb. The following abbreviations are used throughout the volume: AB Theodor W. Adorno, Walter Benjamin, Briefwechsel 1928–1940, ed. Henri Lonitz, Frankfurt/M. 1994. Cor Walter Benjamin, The Correspondence of Walter Benjamin 1910–1940, eds Gershom Scholem, Theodor W. Adorno, trans. Manfred R. Jacobson, Evelyn M. Jacobson, Chicago 1994. DA Max Horkheimer, Theodor W. Adorno, Dialektik der Aufklärung: Philosophische Fragmente, Frankfurt/M. 1977. DE Max Horkheimer, Theodor W. Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments, ed. Gunzelin Schmid Noerr, trans. Edmund Jephcott, Stanford 2002. GB Walter Benjamin, Gesammelte Briefe, eds Christoph Gödde, Henri Lonitz, 6 vols, Frankfurt/M. 1995–2000. MHGS Max Horkheimer, Gesammelte Schriften, eds Alfred Schmidt, Gunzelin Schmid Noerr, 19 vols, Frankfurt/M. 1985–96. SW Walter Benjamin, Selected Writings, eds Michael W. Jennings et al., 4 vols, Cambridge (Mass.) 1996–2003. TWAGS Adorno, Theodor W., Gesammelte Schriften, eds Rolf Tiedemann et al., 20 vols, Frankfurt/M. 1970–86. WBGS Walter Benjamin, Gesammelte Schriften, eds Rolf Tiedemann et al., 7 vols, Frankfurt/M. 1974–89. viii Notes on the Contributors Rüdiger Bittner is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Bielefeld. He is the author of What Reason Demands (1989), Doing Things for Reasons (2001), and the editor of Nietzsche’s Writings from the Late Notebooks (2003). Howard Caygill is Professor of Cultural History at Goldsmiths College, University of London. He is the author of Art of Judgement (1989), A Kant Dictionary (1996), Walter Benjamin: The Colour of Experience (1998), and Levinas and the Political (2002). Pascal Eitler works as a historian at the Research Centre ‘The Political as a Space of Communication’ at the University of Bielefeld. He is completing a doctoral thesis on the relationship between politics and religion in West German society during the 1960s and 1970s. Pierfrancesco Fiorato is Professor of Moral Philosophy at the University of Sassari. He is the author of Geschichtliche Ewigkeit: Ursprung und Zeitlichkeit in der Philosophie Hermann Cohens (1993) and has widely published on neo-Kantianism and German-Jewish thought in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. He is also the Italian editor and translator of several of Hermann Cohen’s works. Raymond Geuss is Reader in Philosophy at the University of Cambridge. His main publications comprise The Idea of a Critical Theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt School (1981), Morality, Culture, and History (1999), History and Illusion in Politics (2001), and Public Goods, Private Goods (2001). In 2005 his Politik und Glück will be published, and a collection of his essays entitled Outside Ethics is soon to appear. David Groiser is Lecturer in German at the University of Oxford and Fellow of Brasenose College. He works on nineteenth- and twentieth- century German intellectual history and literature, with a particular focus on the German-Jewish tradition. His Tradition and Revelation in the Works of Franz Rosenzweig will soon be published. He is also the editor of the forthcoming volume II of the Martin Buber Werkausgabe, Mythos und Mystik: Frühe Schriften 1900–1928. Margarete Kohlenbach is Reader in German at the University of Sussex. She is the author of Das Ende der Vollkommenheit: Zum Verständnis von ix x Notes on the Contributors Thomas Bernhards ‘Korrektur’ (1986) and Walter Benjamin:
Recommended publications
  • Geuss-On-Rorty.Pdf
    Richard Rorty at Princeton: Personal Recollections RAYMOND GEUSS When i arrived in Princeton during the 1970s my addiction to tea was already long-standing and very well entrenched, but I was so concerned about the quality of the water in town that I used to buy large containers of allegedly “pure” water at Davidson’s—the local supermarket, which seems now to have gone out of business. I didn’t, of course, have a car, and given the amount of tea I consumed, the trans- port of adequate supplies of water was a highly labor-inten- sive and inconvenient matter. Dick and Mary Rorty must have noticed me lugging canisters of water home, because, with characteristic generosity, they developed the habit of call- ing around at my rooms in 120 Prospect, often on Sunday mornings, offering to take me by car to fill my water bottles at a hugely primitive and highly suspicious-looking outdoor water tap on the side of a pumphouse which was operated by the Elizabethtown Water Company on a piece of waste land near the Institute Woods. This pumphouse with its copiously dripping tap was like something out of Tarkhovski’s film about Russia after a nuclear accident, Stalker, and the sur- rounding area was a place so sinister one half expected to be attacked by packs of dogs in the final stages of radiation sick- ness or by troops of feral children who had been left by their parents to fend for themselves while the parents went off to the library to finish their dissertations.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche and the Pathologies of Meaning
    Nietzsche and the Pathologies of Meaning Jeremy James Forster Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2016 © 2016 Jeremy James Forster All rights reserved ABSTRACT NIETZSCHE AND THE PATHOLOGIES OF MEANING Jeremy Forster My dissertation details what Nietzsche sees as a normative and philosophical crisis that arises in modern society. This crisis involves a growing sense of malaise that leads to large-scale questions about whether life in the modern world can be seen as meaningful and good. I claim that confronting this problem is a central concern throughout Nietzsche’s philosophical career, but that his understanding of this problem and its solution shifts throughout different phases of his thinking. Part of what is unique to Nietzsche’s treatment of this problem is his understanding that attempts to imbue existence with meaning are self-undermining, becoming pathological and only further entrenching the problem. Nietzsche’s solution to this problem ultimately resides in treating meaning as a spiritual need that can only be fulfilled through a creative interpretive process. CONTENTS Introduction 1 Chapter I: The Birth of Tragedy and the Problem of Meaning 30 Part I: Background 33 Part II: Meaningfulness in Artistic Cultures 45 Part III: Meaningfulness in Tragic Cultures 59 Part IV: Meaningfulness in Socratic Cultures 70 Conclusion: The Solution to Socratism 78 Chapter II: Meaning, Science, and the “Perceptions of Science
    [Show full text]
  • Deep Contextualism and Radical Criticism: the Argument for a Division of Labor
    1 Deep Contextualism and Radical Criticism: The Argument for a Division of Labor Mathias Thaler [email protected] Abstract: Raymond Geuss has recently argued for a “realist” re‐orientation of political theory. This argument is based on a devastating critique of what he calls the “ethics first”‐approach, that is, an approach to politics that is essentially derived from, and thus tributary to, ethics. Geuss’s own account of realist political theory urges us to engage in two distinct activities: (1) embracing some form of deep contextualism and (2) exploiting the potential for radical criticism. This paper argues that these imperatives cannot be fully synthesized because they impose completely different requirements on the philosopher: the former forces the philosopher to immerse herself into the analysis of the real world so as to tailor her normative judgments to the particularities of the situation under scrutiny, while the latter might actually be served better if the principles of justice remained untainted by any considerations of the real world. To illustrate this claim about the structural incompatibility, I will start by unfolding a continuum of various positions in the debate about the relationship between deep contextualism and radical criticism. This continuum has at one extreme Michael Walzer’s notion of “immanent criticism”, and on the other extreme we can find G. A. Cohen’s suggestion that principles of justice should remain “fact‐insensitive”. The final part of this paper suggests that we best conceive of deep contextualism and radical criticism not as mutually exclusive, but rather as reciprocally complimentary. This idea is encapsulated in the notion that we need a division of labor between idealizing and realist approaches to politics.
    [Show full text]
  • Dewey and the Project of Critical Social Theory*
    ..··:.:r.·.'· , DEWEY AND THE PROJECT OF CRITICAL ·,····.·.,·,·.·,1··,···",::·' :~ F. ~. r SOCIAL THEORY* ·',:1: ROBERT J. IZENT University of Kansas Social Thought & Research, 2000, Vol. 23, 1&2 Abstract The project of critical social theory shares with progressive (bllt not classical, free 1Harket) liberalism a value-orientation composed ofan egalitarian conception of socialjustice; a positive, delJelopmental vie1v of libertY as selfrealization; and a participatory notion of democracy. Differentiating critical theory fro»: all strains of liberalism is the comsction that capitalism cannot StljJport theinstitutionalieation of this value-orientation, and that tinder modern conditions onlY some form of democratic socialism can. Given thisualue-orientation, thispaperoutlines the mission and struaur: of theproject of critical theory. In its RJOSt recent retreat to the academy, practitioners have losttoud: not onlY 1vith its mission but also lvith the level ofhistorical specificity at wbicb the project can RIOSt effectivelY bepracticed. TIl/O proposals aresuggestedfor recoverilJg and executing its mission. Thefirst is to address citizens in particular societies about the mora! and political significance of contemporary social change. The second is that theory, description, critique, and vision should proceed at a level ofabstraction I callregi1lle analYsis. Here the object ofanalYsis is a specific society with its own history, institutionalfeatures; and cultura! identity. It is suggested that John Dewey': proposals for the retitalization of philosophy are relevant to the recovery of theproject of critical social theory. Following Dewf!Y j • For theirpatience and support over the years I wish to thank my friends Tom Skrtic, Bob Antonio, Mohamed El-Hodiri, Bardwell Smith, and the late Clifford Griffin. This work was supported in part by Grant No.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche on Morality
    Copyrighted Material-Taylor & Francis Copyrighted Material-Taylor & Francis Nietzsche on Morality Both an introduction to Nietzsche’s moral philosophy, and a sustained commentary on his most famous work, On the Genealogy of Morality, this book has become the most widely used and debated secondary source on these topics over the past dozen years. Many of Nietzsche’s most famous ideas – the “slave revolt” in morals, the attack on free will, perspectivism, “will to power,” and the “ascetic ideal”–are clearly analyzed and explained. The first edition established the centrality of nat- uralism to Nietzsche’s philosophy, generating a substantial scholarly literature to which Leiter responds in an important new Postscript. In addition, Leiter has revised and refreshed the book throughout, taking into account new scholarly literature, and revising or clarifying his treatment of such topics as the objectivity of value, epiphenomenalism and consciousness, and the possibility of “autonomous” agency. Brian Leiter is the Karl N. Llewellyn Professor of Jurisprudence and Director of the Center for Law, Philosophy and Human Values at the University of Chicago, USA, where he teaches and writes about moral, political, and legal philosophy in both the Anglophone and Continental European traditions. Copyrighted Material-Taylor & Francis This page intentionally left blank Copyrighted Material-Taylor & Francis Nietzsche on Morality Second Edition Brian Leiter ROUTLEDGE Routledge~~o~;!~n~~~up LONDON AND NEW YORK Copyrighted Material-Taylor & Francis First published as Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Nietzsche on Morality 2002 by Routledge This edition published as Nietzsche on Morality 2015 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN and by Routledge 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 2002, 2015 Brian Leiter The right of Brian Leiter to be identified as the author of this work has been asserted by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
    [Show full text]
  • Impure Theorizing in an Imperfect World: Politics, Utopophobia and Critical Theory in Geuss's Realism
    This is a repository copy of Impure theorizing in an imperfect world: Politics, utopophobia and critical theory in Geuss’s realism. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/137091/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Verovsek, P.J. (2019) Impure theorizing in an imperfect world: Politics, utopophobia and critical theory in Geuss’s realism. Philosophy and Social Criticism, 45 (3). pp. 265-283. ISSN 0191-4537 https://doi.org/10.1177/0191453718794745 © 2018 The Author(s). This is an author produced version of a paper subsequently published in Philosophy and Social Criticism. Uploaded in accordance with the publisher's self-archiving policy. Article available under the terms of the CC-BY-NC-ND licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/). Reuse This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs (CC BY-NC-ND) licence. This licence only allows you to download this work and share it with others as long as you credit the authors, but you can’t change the article in any way or use it commercially. More information and the full terms of the licence here: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Impure Theorizing in an Imperfect World: Politics, Utopophobia and Critical Theory in Geuss’s Realism1 Peter J.
    [Show full text]
  • Adorno's Politics
    This is the penultimate draft; the final version appears in Philosophy & Social Criticism 40.9 (November 2014): http://psc.sagepub.com/content/early/2014/08/05/0191453714545198.abstract; please cite that version. Adorno’s Politics: Theory and Praxis in Germany’s 1960s∗ Fabian Freyenhagen University of Essex [email protected] Adorno inspired much of Germany’s 1960s student movement, but he came increasingly into conflict with this movement about the practical implications of his critical theory. As early as 1964, student activist lamented what they saw as an unbearable discrepancy between his analysis and his actions.1 As one of his PhD students later expressed it: […] Adorno was incapable of transforming his private compassion towards the “damned of the earth” into an organized partisanship of theory engaged in the liberation of the oppressed. […] his critical option that any philosophy if it is to be true must be immanently oriented towards practical transformation of social reality, loses its binding force if it is not also capable of defining itself in organizational categories. […] Detachment […] drove Adorno […] into complicity with the ruling powers. […]. As he moved more and more away from historical ∗ This article was originally conceived as part of my Adorno’s Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), and should be considered as integral to it. My thanks go to all of those who have commented on earlier drafts, especially Gordon Finlayson, Raymond Geuss, Béatrice Han-Pile. Patrice Maniglier, Richard Raatzsch, Jörg Schaub, Dan Swain, and Dan Watts. 1 For example, they produced leaflets with passages from Adorno’s own work – passages such as the following: “There can be no covenant with this world; we belong to it only to the extent that we rebel against it” – and invited students to contact Adorno to complain that he did not act accordingly (see Esther Leslie, ‘Introduction to Adorno/Marcuse Correspondence on the German Student Movement’, New Left Review I/233, January- February 1999, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • 132 Raymond Geuss. Changing the Subject: Philosophy from Socrates
    Philosophy in Review XXXIX (August 2019), no. 3 Raymond Geuss. Changing the Subject: Philosophy from Socrates to Adorno. Harvard University Press 2017. 368 pp. $29.95 USD (Hardcover ISBN 9780674545724). When Gerry Cohen reflected on how he acquired his enviable skill-set as a philosopher, he concluded that ‘nobody ever told me how to do it.’ He also thought that it may be ‘impossible to explain to anybody how philosophy is to be done.’ In light of these and other reflections, he concluded that ‘[t]he only way to teach people how to do [philosophy] is by letting them watch, and listen, and imitate’ (G.A. Cohen, On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice, and Other Essays in Political Philos- ophy, Princeton University Press, 2011, 225). We might see introductory texts on philosophy as giv- ing their readers opportunities to listen, if not to watch and imitate. In Changing the Subject: Philos- ophy from Socrates to Adorno, Raymond Geuss plainly has aspirations of this sort. For he seeks to convey to his readers an understanding of the circumstances in which ‘[p]hilosophy takes place’ (5). Philosophers have approached this tricky task in a variety of ways. José Ortega y Gasset sought to do it by focusing on what he took to be philosophy’s essence. This is, on his account, a ‘surging impulse toward clarification’ that he traces back to ancient Greece and identifies as the enduring achievement of a group of philosophers he calls ‘magistrate[s] of thought’ (The Origin of Philosophy, University of Illinois Press, 2000 [1967], 24 and 109).
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosopher As Engaged Citizen : Habermas on the Role of the Public Intellectual in the Modern Democratic Public Sphere
    This is a repository copy of The philosopher as engaged citizen : Habermas on the role of the public intellectual in the modern democratic public sphere. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/172849/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Verovšek, P.J. (2021) The philosopher as engaged citizen : Habermas on the role of the public intellectual in the modern democratic public sphere. European Journal of Social Theory. ISSN 1368-4310 https://doi.org/10.1177/13684310211003192 Verovšek PJ. The philosopher as engaged citizen: Habermas on the role of the public intellectual in the modern democratic public sphere. European Journal of Social Theory. March 2021. Copyright © 2021 The Author. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/13684310211003192. Article available under the terms of the CC- BY-NC-ND licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/). Reuse This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs (CC BY-NC-ND) licence. This licence only allows you to download this work and share it with others as long as you credit the authors, but you can’t change the article in any way or use it commercially. More information and the full terms of the licence here: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ The Philosopher as Engaged Citizen: Habermas on the Role of the Public Intellectual in Modern Democratic Life* Peter J.
    [Show full text]
  • Berg on Neumann and Marcuse and Kirchheimer, 'Secret Reports on Nazi Germany: the Frankfurt School Contribution to the War Effort'
    H-German Berg on Neumann and Marcuse and Kirchheimer, 'Secret Reports on Nazi Germany: The Frankfurt School Contribution to the War Effort' Review published on Wednesday, October 15, 2014 Franz Neumann, Herbert Marcuse, Otto Kirchheimer. Secret Reports on Nazi Germany: The Frankfurt School Contribution to the War Effort. Edited by Raffaele Laudani. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2013. 704 pp. $45.00 (e-book), ISBN 978-1-4008-4646-7; $45.00 (cloth), ISBN 978-0-691-13413-0. Reviewed by Anne Berg (University of Michigan)Published on H-German (October, 2014) Commissioned by Chad Ross Legible Enemy When the news broke last November that Cornelius Gurlitt, the eighty-year-old son of a former Nazi art dealer, was sitting on more than 1,200 pieces of artwork confiscated by the Nazi regime, The New York Times somewhat indignantly reported that "the 1938 law"—on the basis of which the regime seized "thousands of other Modernist artworks deemed 'degenerate' because Hitler viewed them as un-German or Jewish in nature—remains on the books to this day."[1] The failure of the Federal Republic of Germany to effectively eradicate traces of Nazism from its laws is more easily seen in relation to Vergangenheitsbewältigung—Germany's attempts to come to terms with the Nazi past—rather than in the context of the postwar politics of occupation and reconstruction. But as Raffaele Laudani's collection of secret reports by members of the Frankfurt School working for the Research and Analysis Branch the Office of Strategic Services (OSS) illustrates, concrete suggestions about Germany's political and legal reconfiguration after defeat were already being discussed and planned by the Allies while the war was still raging in Europe.
    [Show full text]
  • Adorno's Politics: Theory and Praxis in Germany's 1960S∗
    This is the penultimate draft; the final version appears in Philosophy & Social Criticism 40.9 (November 2014): http://psc.sagepub.com/content/early/2014/08/05/0191453714545198.abstract; please cite that version. Adorno’s Politics: Theory and Praxis in Germany’s 1960s∗ Fabian Freyenhagen University of Essex [email protected] Adorno inspired much of Germany’s 1960s student movement, but he came increasingly into conflict with this movement about the practical implications of his critical theory. As early as 1964, student activist lamented what they saw as an unbearable discrepancy between his analysis and his actions.1 As one of his PhD students later expressed it: […] Adorno was incapable of transforming his private compassion towards the “damned of the earth” into an organized partisanship of theory engaged in the liberation of the oppressed. […] his critical option that any philosophy if it is to be true must be immanently oriented towards practical transformation of social reality, loses its binding force if it is not also capable of defining itself in organizational categories. […] Detachment […] drove Adorno […] into complicity with the ruling powers. […]. As he moved more and more away from historical ∗ This article was originally conceived as part of my Adorno’s Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), and should be considered as integral to it. My thanks go to all of those who have commented on earlier drafts, especially Gordon Finlayson, Raymond Geuss, Béatrice Han-Pile. Patrice Maniglier, Richard Raatzsch, Jörg Schaub, Dan Swain, and Dan Watts. 1 For example, they produced leaflets with passages from Adorno’s own work – passages such as the following: “There can be no covenant with this world; we belong to it only to the extent that we rebel against it” – and invited students to contact Adorno to complain that he did not act accordingly (see Esther Leslie, ‘Introduction to Adorno/Marcuse Correspondence on the German Student Movement’, New Left Review I/233, January- February 1999, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • The Idea of a Critical Political Theory
    Columbia University Center for Contemporary Critical Thought Fall 2015 Seminar The Idea of a Critical Political Theory Professor Linda Zerilli Monday Through Friday, October 19-23, 2015 Seminar Description Anyone who goes beyond procedural questions of a discourse theory of morality and ethics and, in a normative attitude . embarks on a theory of the well- ordered, or even emancipated, society will quickly run up against the limits of his own historical situation. --Habermas For some time now, a certain strand of contemporary critical theory has understood its task not in terms of providing a substantive critique of real world power relations, let alone an alternative normative conception of what social relations might be, but of how to justify critique as such: how to “justify those elements which critique owes to its philosophical origins” (Habermas), albeit in a nonfoundationalist manner. This focus on—if not obsession with—the theoretical problem of how to ground one’s own critique arose largely as an intervention into the now longstanding debate over positivism and scientism in figurations of the relation between theory and practice. As important as this intervention has been for exposing the dangers of, and social/political philosophy’s implication in, a purely technocratic order, it has not been without costs to the very idea of critique itself: namely the crucial connection between critique and social/political transformation. Seyla Benhabib has usefully characterized the two tasks of critical theory as “explanatory-diagnostic” and “anticipatory-utopian.” In this seminar we aim to explore what each of these tasks might be and how they are connected.
    [Show full text]