After Totalitarianism: Hannah Arendt, Isaiah Berlin, and the Realization and Defeat of the Western Tradition

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

After Totalitarianism: Hannah Arendt, Isaiah Berlin, and the Realization and Defeat of the Western Tradition After Totalitarianism: Hannah Arendt, Isaiah Berlin, and the Realization and Defeat of the Western Tradition A Dissertation SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF UNIVERSITY OF MINNESOTA BY Ilya P. Winham IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Mary Dietz March 2015 © Ilya Winham 2015 Acknowledgements I could not have written this dissertation without the support and guidance of Mary Dietz and James Farr. I learned what political theory is or might be in their classes. I am also grateful for the help of my other committee members, Elizabeth Beaumont and David Haley. I would also like to thank all of the teachers who taught me about politics and various thinkers in the history of political thought: Frank Adler, Robert Albritton, Bruce Baum, George Comninel, Norman Dahl, Lisa Disch, Jean Elshtain, Chuck Green, Duchess Harris, Alison Kadlec, John P. McCormick, Martha Nussbaum and Bill Scheuerman. I would be remiss if I did not thank Kim and Nicolas David for all of their invaluable friendship and support since I arrived in Minnesota. i Dedication This thesis is dedicated to my grandparents, parents, and my wife, Emily Sahakian. ii Abstract This dissertation explores Hannah Arendt (1906-1975) and Isaiah Berlin’s (1909-1997) understanding of the Western tradition of political philosophy in the light of totalitarianism in their works of the late 1940s and 1950s. The total collapse of traditional political relations and regimes in the 1930s and 1940s put the entire discipline and tradition of political philosophy in question. As Arendt and Berlin reflected on the Western tradition of political philosophy, both decided that the tradition was not just defeated by Nazi and Communist totalitarianism, it was also in a sense realized in those regimes. In exploring their ambivalent attitude toward the tradition, this dissertation aims to illuminate how Arendt and Berlin contributed to the postwar imperative to think afresh about the Western tradition of political philosophy not only to expose its originating flaws, but also to reconstruct political philosophy on decidedly anti-totalitarian premises. This dissertation engages Arendt and Berlin with respect to the topics of totalitarianism, the tradition of political philosophy, the significance of Machiavelli for post-totalitarian political theory, human plurality as a mode of engaging politics, modern world alienation or agoraphobia and the midcentury zeitgeist of social adjustment. When read together— which political theorists as a rule almost never do—these topics emerge as important to the development of Arendt and Berlin’s respective bodies of anti-totalitarian and “pluralist” political thought. What is ultimately at stake for them in seeking to understand the complicated relationship between totalitarianism and the Western tradition of political philosophy is how to proceed in political theory in a fully post-totalitarian way. In addition to bringing Arendt and Berlin together and investigating some important thematic similarities between them, my dissertation advances our knowledge of both iii thinkers by revealing how deeply the concepts and issues of politics, pluralism, totalitarianism and the Western tradition of political philosophy are intertwined in their writings. Beyond Arendt and Berlin studies, this dissertation contributes to our knowledge of the endeavor to renovate or create political theory after totalitarianism and during the Cold War. iv Table of Contents Abbreviations vi Introduction 1 Chapter 1 36 Hannah Arendt and Isaiah Berlin’s “Monist” Interpretation of the Western Tradition of Political Philosophy Chapter 2 76 In Meinecke’s Shadow: Hannah Arendt and Isaiah Berlin’s Discovery of a “Pagan” Machiavelli in Christian Europe Chapter 3 125 Pluralism Rules the Earth Chapter 4 168 A World Unhinged Conclusion 202 Bibliography 211 v Abbreviations Works by Hannah Arendt listed in chronological order. NF “Nightmare and Flight” [1945], in Essays in Understanding 1930-1954. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1994, pp. 133-135. GP “Approaches to the ‘German Problem’” [1945], in Essays in Understanding 1930-1954. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1994, pp. 106-120. Existenz “What Is Existenz Philosophy?,” Partisan Review 13 (1946), pp. 34-56. FE “French Existentialism” [1946], in Essays in Understanding 1930-1954. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1994, pp. 188-193. DKJ “Dedication to Karl Jaspers” [1947], in Essays in Understanding 1930- 1954. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1994, pp. 212-216. Burden The Origins of Totalitarianism. First Edition. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company, 1951. Quest “The Spiritual Quest of Modern Man: The Answer of the Existentialists.” Lecture, New School for Social Research, New York, N.Y., 1952. Hannah Arendt Papers, Manuscript Division, Library of Congress, Washington, D.C. MT “Mankind and Terror” [1953], in Essays in Understanding 1930-1954. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1994, pp. 297-306. FHM “From Hegel to Marx” [1953], in The Promise of Politics. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 2005, pp. 70-80. RP “Religion and Politics” [1953], in Essays in Understanding 1930-1954. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1994, pp. 368-390. EC “The Ex-Communists” [1953], in Essays in Understanding 1930-1954. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1994, pp. 391-400. UC “Understanding Communism” [1953], in Essays in Understanding 1930- 1954. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1994, pp. 363-367. Reply “A Reply to Eric Voegelin” [1953], in Essays in Understanding 1930- 1954. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1994, pp. 401-408. NewSchool “The Great Tradition and the Nature of Totalitarianism” [1953]. Notes for six lectures, New School for Social Research, New York, NY, March 18 to April 22, 1953. Hannah Arendt Papers, Manuscript Division, Library of Congress, Washington, D.C. UP “Understanding and Politics (The Difficulties of Understanding)” [1953], in Essays in Understanding 1930-1954. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1994, pp. 307-327. This essay was the first of six lectures Arendt gave at the New School in the Spring of 1953, and then published in Partisan Review 20:4 (July-Aug. 1953), pp. 377-392. NT “On the Nature of Totalitarianism: An Essay in Understanding” [1953], in Essays in Understanding 1930-1954. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1994, pp. 328-360. This essay comprises lectures 2-4 of the six lectures Arendt gave at the New School in the Spring of 1953. vi IT “Ideology and Terror: A Novel Form of Government,” The Review of Politics 15:3 (July 1953), pp. 303-327. Preface “Preface” [1953] to the Christian Gauss Seminar in Criticism lectures at Princeton. Second Draft. Princeton University, Princeton, N.J., Oct. 8 to Nov. 12, 1953. Hannah Arendt Papers, Manuscript Division, Library of Congress, Washington, D.C. TMA “Tradition and the Modern Age” [1953], in Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought. New York: Penguin, 1968, pp. 17- 40. Originally the first of six lectures Arendt delivered as the Christian Gauss Seminar lecturer at Princeton in 1953 and then published in Partisan Review 21:1 (Jan.-Feb. 1954), pp. 53-75. TET “The End of Tradition” [1953], in The Promise of Politics. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 2005, pp. 81-92. This essay derives from KMPT. TPT “The Tradition of Political Thought” [1953], in The Promise of Politics. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 2005, pp. 40-62. GT1 “The Great Tradition: I. Law and Power” [1953], Social Research 74:3 (Fall 2007), pp. 713-726. GT2 “The Great Tradition: II. Ruling and Being Ruled” [1953], Social Research 74:4 (Winter 2007), pp. 941-954. KMPT “Karl Marx and the Tradition of Western Political Thought” [1953], Social Research 69:2 (Summer 2002), pp. 273-319. This material is drawn from lectures 3-5 of Arendt’s six Christian Gauss Seminar lectures at Princeton. CP “Concern with Politics in Recent European Philosophical Thought” [1954], in Essays in Understanding 1930-1954. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 1994, pp. 428-447. PP “Philosophy and Politics” [1954], Social Research 57:1 (Spring 1990), pp. 73-103. Socrates “Socrates” [1954], in The Promise of Politics. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 2005, pp. 5-39. This is a slightly different version of PP. Machiavelli “History of Political Theory” [1955] course, University of California, Berkeley, CA. Hannah Arendt Papers, Manuscript Division, Library of Congress, Washington, DC. Milan “The Rise and Development of Totalitarianism and Authoritarian Forms of Government in the Twentieth Century” [1955], in The Future of Freedom. The Congress for Cultural Freedom. Bombay, Usha, 1955, pp. 180-206. Broch “Hermann Broch: 1886-1951” [1955], trans. Richard Winston. In Men in Dark Times. New York: Harvest, 1968, pp. 111-151. Epilogue “Epilogue” [1955], in The Promise of Politics. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 2005, pp. 201-204. Authority “What Is Authority?” [1957], in Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought. New York: Penguin, 1968, pp. 91-141. vii Jaspers “Karl Jaspers: Citizen of the World?” [1957], trans. Clara and Richard Winston. In Men in Dark Times. New York: Harvest, 1968, pp. 81-94. IIP “Introduction into Politics” [1956-59], in The Promise of Politics. Edited by J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books, 2005, pp. 93-200. HC The Human Condition [1958]. Second Edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998. History “The Concept of History: Ancient and Modern” [1958], in Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought. New York: Penguin, 1968, pp. 41-90. Lessing “On Humanity in Dark Times: Thoughts About Lessing” [1959], trans. Clara and Richard Winston. In Men in Dark Times. New York: Harvest, 1968, pp. 3-32. CC “The Crisis in Culture: Its Social and Its Political Significance” [1960], in Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought.
Recommended publications
  • Geuss-On-Rorty.Pdf
    Richard Rorty at Princeton: Personal Recollections RAYMOND GEUSS When i arrived in Princeton during the 1970s my addiction to tea was already long-standing and very well entrenched, but I was so concerned about the quality of the water in town that I used to buy large containers of allegedly “pure” water at Davidson’s—the local supermarket, which seems now to have gone out of business. I didn’t, of course, have a car, and given the amount of tea I consumed, the trans- port of adequate supplies of water was a highly labor-inten- sive and inconvenient matter. Dick and Mary Rorty must have noticed me lugging canisters of water home, because, with characteristic generosity, they developed the habit of call- ing around at my rooms in 120 Prospect, often on Sunday mornings, offering to take me by car to fill my water bottles at a hugely primitive and highly suspicious-looking outdoor water tap on the side of a pumphouse which was operated by the Elizabethtown Water Company on a piece of waste land near the Institute Woods. This pumphouse with its copiously dripping tap was like something out of Tarkhovski’s film about Russia after a nuclear accident, Stalker, and the sur- rounding area was a place so sinister one half expected to be attacked by packs of dogs in the final stages of radiation sick- ness or by troops of feral children who had been left by their parents to fend for themselves while the parents went off to the library to finish their dissertations.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche and the Pathologies of Meaning
    Nietzsche and the Pathologies of Meaning Jeremy James Forster Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2016 © 2016 Jeremy James Forster All rights reserved ABSTRACT NIETZSCHE AND THE PATHOLOGIES OF MEANING Jeremy Forster My dissertation details what Nietzsche sees as a normative and philosophical crisis that arises in modern society. This crisis involves a growing sense of malaise that leads to large-scale questions about whether life in the modern world can be seen as meaningful and good. I claim that confronting this problem is a central concern throughout Nietzsche’s philosophical career, but that his understanding of this problem and its solution shifts throughout different phases of his thinking. Part of what is unique to Nietzsche’s treatment of this problem is his understanding that attempts to imbue existence with meaning are self-undermining, becoming pathological and only further entrenching the problem. Nietzsche’s solution to this problem ultimately resides in treating meaning as a spiritual need that can only be fulfilled through a creative interpretive process. CONTENTS Introduction 1 Chapter I: The Birth of Tragedy and the Problem of Meaning 30 Part I: Background 33 Part II: Meaningfulness in Artistic Cultures 45 Part III: Meaningfulness in Tragic Cultures 59 Part IV: Meaningfulness in Socratic Cultures 70 Conclusion: The Solution to Socratism 78 Chapter II: Meaning, Science, and the “Perceptions of Science
    [Show full text]
  • Review of Reflections on Hanging by Arthur Koestler
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO LAW REVIEW [VOL 25 Rutledge; Taney and Stone surely have little in common. One ends the book with a feeling that the great trait of the best judges is unselfishness, the capacity to see society clearly, without the distortion of vision that accom- panies the drive to succeed, to persuade, to gain power. We trust the justices of our Supreme Court with some of the greatest powers of government; we do so because they are characteristically beyond the desire for power. Much of their labor is disclaiming the exercise of power. In a society of frantic grasp- ing for influence, of shrill competing claims, of strident advertisement, the good judge is calm and quiet. In the troublesome days between 1935 and 1937 there was much discontent among the loquacious because judges were not more like legislators. But perhaps the reverse would be a more wholesome ideal for our time. ARTHUR SUTHERAND* 6 Professor of Law, Harvard University. Freedom, Virtue, and the First Amendment. By Walter F. Berns. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press. 1957. Pp. 264. $4.00. Professor Berns, of the Yale Political Science faculty, has written an un- usual book. In considering the function of the Supreme Court in American government,' he rejects the "libertarian" doctrine of "judicial restraint."' He also rejects the "libertarian" thesis that the freedoms of the Bill of Rights are ultimate and absolute values in our society.3 He would have the Court exer- cise all its power to decree the good, the true and the beautiful.4 Perhaps some day he will provide the touchstone so that we may all readily recognize these qualities.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Arendt's on Revolution After the Fall of the Wall
    Keeping the Republic: Reading Arendt’s On Revolution after the Fall of the Wall Dick Howard Introduction: From where do you speak, comrade? Two decades after the fall of the Wall seemed to announce – by default, as an unexpected gift – the triumph of democracy, optimism appears at best naïve, at worst an ideological manipulation of the most cynical type. The hope was that the twin forms of modern anti-politics – the imaginary planned society and the equally imaginary invisible hand of the market place – would be replaced by the rule of the demos; citizens together would determine the values of the commonwealth. The reality was at first the ‘New World Order’ of George H.W. Bush; then the indecisive interregnum of the Clinton years; and now the crass take over of democratic rhetoric by the neo-conservatives of George W. Bush. ‘Man is born free, yet everywhere he is in chains,’ wrote Rousseau at the outset of The Social Contract; how this came about was less important, he continued, than what made it legitimate: that was what needed explanation. So it is today; what is it about democracy that makes it the greatest threat to its own existence? In this context, it is well to reread Hannah Arendt’s On Revolution, published in 1963. On returning recently to my old (1965) paperback edition, I was struck by the spare red and black design of the cover, which was not (as I thought for a moment) a subtle allusion to the conflict of communism and anarchism for the realization of ‘true’ democracy, but simply the backdrop against which the editor stressed these sentences: ‘With nuclear power at a stalemate, revolutions have become the principal political factor of our time.
    [Show full text]
  • HE CONTRIBUTION of GEORGE ORWELL and ARTHUR KOESTLER to the POLIT- ICAL THEORY of TOTALITARIANISM ~Oland James Wensley
    ~HE CONTRIBUTION OF GEORGE ORWELL AND ARTHUR KOESTLER TO THE POLIT­ ICAL THEORY OF TOTALITARIANISM ~oland James Wensley ·A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts , Department of Economies and Political Science, McGill University, Montreal. August, 1964. TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE i-v CHAPTER I: The Men and the Age 1-18 Situation in the 1930's Pl-2; Koestler's personal background P3-6; Koestler's background related to his thought P6-10; Orwell's personal background Pl0-12; Orwell's background related to his thought Pl2-16; Koestler and Orwell compared in general terms Pl7-18. CHAPTER II: Spain 1937 - The Impact of Totalita­ rianism on Koestler and Orwell 19-34 Situation in Spain 1936-37, Pl9-20; Koestler's Spanish experience P21-26J Orwell's Spanish experience P26-30; meaning of the Spanish experience for Koestler and Orwell as defined in terms of ''li.m.ited '' and "luxuriant r• totalita­ rianism P31-34. CHAPTER III: Arthur Koestler and Limited Totalita­ rianism 35-61 Koestler's view of man and society P35-38J Koestler's idea of the genesis of totalitarianism P39-41; attraction of Communism for Koestler P41-43; Koestler's conception of Stalinism P44-48; Koestler's theory of history P47-48; Koestler's idea of totalita­ rianism P48-56; the meaning of '' limi ted '' totalitarianism in Koestler's work ex­ pounded P56-61. CHAPTER IV: George Orwell and Luxuriant Totalita­ rianism 62-83 Orwell's view of man and society P62-64; Orwell's ideas compared with Koestler's on this P65-69; Orwell's extension of the anomalies of the modern age P69-73; Orwell on totalitarian stability1 distortion of reality, and the in­ vasion of the human personality P73-80; Orwell's conception of luxuriant totalitarianism P80-83.
    [Show full text]
  • Daniel Brick's Judisk Krönika
    Cultural Zionism in Sweden: Daniel Brick's Judisk Krönika Stephen Fruitman Umeå I. Introduction The present study examines the content of the pendence" . Spotlighting those years reveals an Swedish-Jewish Zionist periodical Judisk Krö- especially vibrant, if at times trying period in nika during its earliest years of publication, Swedish-Jewish debate. I consider this reading 1932 to 1950, under the editorship of its found- of Judisk Krönika to be the first step toward a er, Daniel Brick. The onus will be on how the more comprehensive study of cultural Zionism magazine, in its brightest and most ambitious in Sweden, which will include use of archival years, acted as a conduit through which the and secondary sources to provide a more com- ideas of cultural Zionism flowed into Sweden. plete picture of this instance in Swedish-Jewish Through essays, reports, editorial comm- intellectual history. ments, book reviews and debates, the circle of intellectuals grouped around Brick clamoured for a revivification of what they considered to be the moribund cultural life of Swedish Jewry, II. Judisk Krönika: An Overview the result (in their eyes) of decades of Reform dominance in communal life. Not wishing to make themselves any less "Swedish", the cul- tural Zionists nevertheless insisted that Jews Daniel Brick: Voice of a "Reflective Youth" in Sweden (and Norway, Denmark, and Fin- land) needed to adopt an international per- Daniel Brick (1903-87) was the son of an immi- spective, integrating the proposed idea for a grant from Lithuania, a man described as both Jewish national home in Palestine into their "deeply religious" and a "chovev-zionist [lover lives as a source of cultural pride and spiritual of Zion], warmly interested in the Jewish pio- renewal.
    [Show full text]
  • A Special Supplement: Reflections on Violence by Hannah Arendt | the New York Review of Books
    A Special Supplement: Reflections on Violence by Hannah Arendt | The New York Review of Books EMAIL Tweet Share A Special Supplement: Refections on Violence Hannah Arendt FEBRUARY 27, 1969 ISSUE I These reflections were provoked by the events and debates of the last few years, as seen against the background of the twentieth century. Indeed this century has become, as Lenin predicted, a century of wars and revolutions, hence a century of that violence which is currently believed to be their common denominator. There is, however, another factor in the present situation which, though predicted by nobody, is of at least equal importance. The technical development of implements of violence has now reached the point where no political goal could conceivably correspond to their destructive potential or justify their actual use in armed conflict. Hence, warfare—since times immemorial the final merciless arbiter in international disputes—has lost much of its effectiveness and nearly all of its glamor. “The apocalyptic” chess game between the superpowers, that is, between those that move on the highest plane of our civilization, is being played according to the rule: “if either ‘wins’ it is the end of both.”1 Moreover the game bears no resemblance to whatever war games preceded it. Its “rational” goal is mutual deterrence, not victory. Since violence—as distinct from power, force, or strength—always needs implements (as Engels pointed out long ago),2 the revolution in technology, a revolution in tool-making, was especially marked in warfare. The very substance of violent action is ruled by the question of means and ends, whose chief characteristic, if applied to human affairs, has always been that the end is in danger of being overwhelmed by the means, which it both justifies and needs.
    [Show full text]
  • View: "Koestler"
    Books Book Review: "Koestler" The Literary and Political Odyssey of a Twentieth-Century Skeptic. By Michael Scammell '85GSAS. By Michael Kimmage | Winter 2009-10 Arthur Koestler in New York City. (Bettman / Corbis) When Arthur Koestler arrived in New York City in March 1948 to launch an American speaking tour, his visit was front-page news. An audience of 3000 filled Carnegie Hall, eager to hear Koestler’s thoughts on “the radical’s dilemma” and on America’s pressing need to confront Soviet communism. Koestler had gained worldwide fame for his novel Darkness at Noon, published in 1940. The hero of the novel is Nicholas Rubashov, a devout communist caught in Stalin’s net in the 1930s for straying from the party line. Before his inevitable execution, he is interrogated and forced to confess to ludicrous crimes. At the heart of his ordeal is an “absolute faith in History”: Stalin may be fallible, but the Soviet cause is infallible and can be made to justify countless deaths, including Rubashov’s own. The novel’s taut, philosophical style made it a staple of international literary culture, damaged the Communist Party’s global reputation, and made its author an icon of the engagé intellectual. For much of the Cold War, Koestler was a celebrity anti- communist. Yet when Koestler, the author of some 30 books, died in 1983, his chosen legacy was detached from political parties, movements, and causes. In his will, he left most of his estate to endow an academic chair in parapsychology. This unorthodox evolution can now be traced in Koestler: The Literary and Political Odyssey of a Twentieth-Century Skeptic, a new biography by Michael Scammell ’85GSAS, professor of creative writing at Columbia.
    [Show full text]
  • Arendt's Violence/Power Distinction and SARTRE's Violence/Counter-Violence Distinction: the Phenomenology of Violence in Co
    CHAPTER SIX ARENDT’S VIOLENCE/POWER DISTINCTION AND SARTRE’S VIOLENCE/COUNTER-VIOLENCE DISTINCTION: THE PHENOMENOLOGY OF VIOLENCE IN COLONIAL AND POST-ColonIAL CONTEXTS Kathryn T. Gines The theme of violence can be traced throughout Hannah Arendt’s major political writings such as The Human Condition and On Revolution where she draws connections between war, violence, and necessity (or libera- tion from necessity); The Origins of Totalitarianism where she examines Europe’s uses of violence in concentration camps, as well as massacre and imperialism in Africa; and, of course, On Violence where she condemns the violence of the Black Power movement and of anti-colonialism. The essay that follows will take as its starting point the violence/power dis- tinction and then the appropriate uses of violence versus non-violence as presented in Arendt’s On Violence. I argue that this distinction between violence and power is misapplied in Arendt’s critique of Jean-Paul Sar- tre and Frantz Fanon’s analyses of anti-colonial revolutionary violence in Algeria. Arendt wrongly interprets Sartre and Fanon’s analyses of violence and counter-violence in The Wretched of the Earth and Critique of Dialecti- cal Reason and her critique of violence proves to be unbalanced. On my view, she rejects their analyses because they argue for the use of violence by the oppressed to overcome the violent system of colonialism. I con- tend that it is because they argue for revolutionary violence (or counter- violence) against their oppressors that Sartre and Fanon are accused of glorifying violence for violence’s sake. In the concluding section of the essay, I briefly consider the possibil- ity that while Arendt’s critique of anti-colonial violence is misguided, her analysis might prove helpful when applied to the post-colonial context in which former anti-colonial leaders fighting for independence strike out violently against the people.
    [Show full text]
  • Honors 392, Cosmology, Self and Society: Prof B
    Question Authority...Question Reality...Question the Questioner...Question the act of Questioning… The ultimate questions as to the meaning of our actions and as to the meaning of life in general always tend to involve astronomical problems. Hans Reichenbach Honors 392, Cosmology, Self and Society: Prof B. McGrane Adventures in Cosmologies Fall 2018 Roosevelt 216 COSMOLOGY, SELF AND SOCIETY: ADVENTURES IN COSMOLOGIES (with deference to Whitehead’s Adventures of Ideas, 1933) OVERALL COURSE STRUCTURE: The Ancient Greeks, The Renaissance, The Enlightenment, The 20/21st Centuries First, some important philosophical, orienting general statements: "Had we never seen the stars, and the sun, and the heaven, none of the words which we have spoken about the universe would ever have been uttered. But now the sight of day and night, and the months and the revolutions of the years, have created number, and have given us a conception of time, and the power of inquiring about the nature of the universe; and from this source we have derived philosophy, than which no greater good ever was or will be given by the gods to mortal man." (Plato, Timaeus, 360 B.C., my emphasis, in Ferris p19) "Even before the start of history, the sky must have been commonly used as a compass, a clock, and a calendar...We know that the stars were used for similar purposes very early in history." (Weinberg, To Explain the World, 2015, p55) "Why do we need to know whether the sun revolves around the earth or vice versa? What business of ours is it, anyway? Can this knowledge
    [Show full text]
  • Deep Contextualism and Radical Criticism: the Argument for a Division of Labor
    1 Deep Contextualism and Radical Criticism: The Argument for a Division of Labor Mathias Thaler [email protected] Abstract: Raymond Geuss has recently argued for a “realist” re‐orientation of political theory. This argument is based on a devastating critique of what he calls the “ethics first”‐approach, that is, an approach to politics that is essentially derived from, and thus tributary to, ethics. Geuss’s own account of realist political theory urges us to engage in two distinct activities: (1) embracing some form of deep contextualism and (2) exploiting the potential for radical criticism. This paper argues that these imperatives cannot be fully synthesized because they impose completely different requirements on the philosopher: the former forces the philosopher to immerse herself into the analysis of the real world so as to tailor her normative judgments to the particularities of the situation under scrutiny, while the latter might actually be served better if the principles of justice remained untainted by any considerations of the real world. To illustrate this claim about the structural incompatibility, I will start by unfolding a continuum of various positions in the debate about the relationship between deep contextualism and radical criticism. This continuum has at one extreme Michael Walzer’s notion of “immanent criticism”, and on the other extreme we can find G. A. Cohen’s suggestion that principles of justice should remain “fact‐insensitive”. The final part of this paper suggests that we best conceive of deep contextualism and radical criticism not as mutually exclusive, but rather as reciprocally complimentary. This idea is encapsulated in the notion that we need a division of labor between idealizing and realist approaches to politics.
    [Show full text]
  • Reports the Maozedongism of Chinese Politics and the Xi Factor
    Reports The Maozedongism of Chinese Politics and the Xi Factor *Stein Ringen 26 April 2018 Al Jazeera Centre for Studies Tel: +974-40158384 [email protected] http://studies.aljazeera.n [Getty] As part of his critical paradigm of political systems in the West as well as in the East in the 21st century, sociologist and political scientist Stein Ringen proposes another nuanced reflection of a two-part study of the challenges of global democracy. Back in February, the first paper “When America’s Democracy Needs a Health-Check: Polarization and the Trump Factor” focused on the Trump factor in the decline of American democracy. Now, the second paper addresses how China has proceeded with its own political transformation in 2018. The Chinese Communist Party (CCP) has decided to add Chinese President Xi Jinping’s political thought and the National Supervision System into the country’s constitution.(1) As Ringen wrote in a recent publication, “the modern Chinese state does not rely on being forbidding to its people in their daily lives. Indeed, ordinary Chinese now have many freedoms that no one interferes with. But the state has its red lines and does forbid what cannot be accepted: interference in Party affairs and organizing outside of the Party apparatus.”(2) According to the author, Xi Jinping has proved himself the most formidable leader in China after Mao. The first bastion for Xi to topple was pragmatism. Under his watch, all the reins of dictatorship have been tightened. The second bastion to fall was collective leadership. At the Party Congress in October 2017, he had his “thought” inscribed in the Party’s Constitution, lifting himself on to the pedestal previously occupied only by Mao.
    [Show full text]