Introduction 1

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Introduction 1 Notes Introduction 1. Oscar Wilde, “A Chinese Sage,” in Reviews, ed. by Robert Ross (London: Metheuen and Co., 1908), 533–534. 2. Wang Fuzhi , Chuanshan Quanshu , Volume 10 (Changsha: Yuelu Shushe, 1998), 613–614. 3. It should be noted that I am not taking what Michael Puett has called a “contrastive approach” to early Chinese thought where I understand texts to be representative of entire cultures or ways of life. Rather, my methodological aim is to complicate the categories of compari- son by illuminating the contexts and histories of interpretation in the background of much comparative work, revealing how certain “uni- versal yardsticks” like “morality” connote meanings which are more parochial. Thus, while the Zhuangzi may strike an unfamiliar chord in regard to received wisdom in the history of Western philosophy, the differences are not absolute and can be interpreted (not transcended) through thick description and historical sensitivity. See Michael Puett, To Become a God: Cosmology, Sacrifice, and Self-Divinization in Early China (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002). 4. Jeffrey Stout, Ethics After Babel: The Languages of Morals and Their Discontents (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001), 60. 5. Sima Qian , Shi ji gu shi xuan yi (Beijing: Zhonghua shu ju, 1959), 2144. 6. See A. C. Graham, “How Much of Chuang-tzu Did Chuang-tzu Write?” in Studies in Chinese Philosophy and Philosophical Litera- ture (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1990), 283–321. See also Liu Xiaogan, Classifying the Zhuangzi Chapters (Ann Arbor: Center for Chinese Studies, The University of Michigan, 1994); and Guan Feng , “Zhuangzi waizapian chutan” ,inZhuangzi neip- ian yijie he pipan (Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1960), 319–358. 7. See Fukunaga Mitsuji , S¯oshi (Tokyo: Asahi, 1978). 8. Holmes Welch, Taoism: The Parting of the Way (Boston: Beacon Press, 1957), 88. 9. Ibid. 10. In other words, although texts like the Zhuangzi and Huainanzi repeatedly make use of terms like dao and daoshu (“techniques 140 Notes of the Way”), none employ Tan’s phrase daojia (“school of the Way”) nor speak of a self-identifying school of thought, even in the limited sense that Confucians and Mohists do during the fourth and third centuries. See Kidder Smith, “Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism, ‘Legalism’, et cetera,” The Journal of Asian Studies 62.1 (February 2003), 129–156. 11. Shiji, 3289. Sima Tan’s appellation of “Daoism” militates against the received view, initially promulgated during the Wei and Jin dynasties by Neo-Daoists and held by more recent scholars (e.g., Fung Yulan, Herlee Creel), that a foundational “Lao-Zhuang” lineage of Daoist philosophy, exclusively concerned with mystical and cosmological interests, existed prior to Sima Tan’s classification. 12. Jens Østergard Peterson, “Which Books Did the First Emperor of Ch’in Burn? On the Meaning of Pai Chia in Early Chinese Sources,” Monumenta Serica 43 (1995), 34. 13. Mark Edward Lewis, Writing and Authority in Early China (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1999); and Michael Puett, To Become a God. See also Nathan Sivin, “On the Word ‘Taoist’ as a Source of Perplexity, With Special Reference to the Relations of Science and Religion in Traditional China,” History of Religions 17 (1978), 303–330. 14. Puett, To Become a God, 25. 15. Mark Csikszentmihalyi, “Traditional Taxonomies and Revealed Texts in the Han,” in Daoist Identity: History, Lineage, and Ritual, ed. by Livia Kohn and Harold D. Roth (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 2002), 83–84. 16. On the notion of “inventing traditions,” see Eric Hobsbawm and Terence Ranger, eds., The Invention of Tradition (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1983). One also calls to mind Foucault’s notion of a “discursive formation.” See Michel Foucault, The Order of Things: An Archeology of the Human Sciences (New York: Vintage, 1994). 17. See Harold Roth, Original Tao: Inward Training and the Foundations of Taoist Mysticism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1999), 173–203. 18. Andrew Meyer, “The Altars of the Soil and Grain are Closer than Kin : The Qi Model of Intellectual Participa- tion and the Jixia Patronage Community,” Early China 33–34 (2010–2011), 38. 19. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, Third Edition, trans. by G. E. M. Anscombe (Oxford: Blackwell, 2001), §66. 20. Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, Third Edi- tion (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2007), 222. 21. A. C. Graham, Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argument in Ancient China (LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 1989), 31. Notes 141 Chapter 1 1. Michael Walzer, Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994), xi. 2. Ibid. 3. See James Legge, Confucianism in Relation to Christianity (London: Trubner, 1877), 9. 4. Bryan Van Norden has suggested recently that we do not need exact lexical correspondences to make philosophical comparisons between traditions so long as we can “look at the particulars of the two lan- guages being compared in order to determine whether the presence or absence of a particular term is significant.” While I would agree with Van Norden that responsible comparisons can be made even when there are no lexical counterparts, the question that I am rais- ing concerns those instances where we seem to have surface lexical compatibility but the depth grammar of the terms reveals something thicker and more culturally loaded. See Bryan Van Norden, Virtue Ethics and Consequentialism in Early Chinese Philosophy (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 22. 5. N. J. Girardot, “ ‘Finding the Way’: James Legge and the Victorian Invention of Taoism,” Religion 29.2 (April 1999), 118. 6. Anna Seidel, “Taoism: The Unofficial High Religion of China,” Taoist Resources 7.2 (1997), 40. 7. This should not be construed as a broadside against those working in the fields of Daoist studies, religious studies, or comparative religious ethics in regard to their interpretations of Daoism. My aim is merely to highlight why Daoism receives less attention than even other schools of early Chinese thought (e.g., Confucianism, Legalism) in regard to its moral philosophy and how we can bring Daoism into conversation as a specifically moral tradition, not only with other schools of thought in ancient China but also potentially with moral traditions in the West. 8. Herlee G. Creel, What Is Taoism? And Other Studies in Chinese Cultural History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), 3, 4, 43. 9. Norman Girardot suggests that the contemporary Western under- standing of Daoism owes many of its guiding assumptions to the late Victorian invention of Daoism by sinologists such as James Legge (1815–1897) who tended to locate a “pure” form of Daoism in cer- tain “sacred texts” (e.g., the Laozi) in opposition to ritualistic or “magical” elements of the later tradition. The Leggian picture of Daoism survives in Creel’s work, on my reading, as two dichotomies which structure his entire discussion of Daoism—namely, the dis- tinction between “philosophical” and “religious” Daoism and the contrast between the “contemplative” and the “purposive” aspects of Daoism. It is my contention that both dualisms, along with 142 Notes uncritical assumptions about the nature of morality, contribute to Creel’s blindness to the moral dimensions of Daoism. 10. Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), 174–175. 11. See Elizabeth Anscombe, “Modern Moral Philosophy,” Philosophy 33.124 (January 1958), 1. 12. I will from now on be using “morality” to refer to the special sys- tem of obligations and the “ethical” to denote the larger realm of the moral life. 13. For a helpful guide on the controverted nature of “morality” in comparative contexts, see David Wong, “Comparative Philosophy: Chinese and Western,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition); Edward N. Zalta, ed., http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/fall2011/entries/comparphil-chiwes/. As Wong notes, crit- ics of “morality” like Bernard Williams have tended, perhaps unfairly, to confine “morality” to Kant’s moral philosophy. Although Kant did exert a tremendous amount of influence on contemporary moral phi- losophy, I think there are other dimensions of our received notion of “morality” (listed above) that go beyond Kant. 14. Charles Taylor, “Iris Murdoch and Moral Philosophy,” in Iris Murdoch and the Search for Human Goodness, ed. by Maria Antonaccio and William Schweiker (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), 3. 15. Alan Gewirth, “Common Morality and the Community of Rights,” in Prospects for a Common Morality, ed. by Gene Outka and John P. Reeder, Jr. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), 30. It should be noted that there are a small number of ethicists working within the tradition of “morality” who recognize that it does not cover the entire playing field of ethics. To take one recent example, T. M. Scanlon suggests that the narrow domain of morality having to do with our duties to other people (e.g., requirements to aid, prohi- bitions against harming and killing), “what we owe to each other,” comprises a “distinct subject matter, unified by a single manner of reasoning and by a common motivational basis. By contrast, it is not clear that morality in the broader sense is a single subject that has a similar unity.” See his What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 7. 16. Arthur Danto, Mysticism and Morality: Oriental Thought and Moral Philosophy (New York: Columbia University Press, 1988), 114. 17. Danto explicitly states that he is referring to morality “as such, not this or that moral system.” See Ibid., 119. 18. Ibid., 115. 19. Ibid., 118. 20. Hans-Georg Moeller, The Moral Fool: A Case for Amorality (New York: Columbia University Press, 2009). Notes 143 21. On amoralism, see Ronald D. Milo, “Amorality,” Mind 92.368 (1983), 482: “To say that a person is amoral is to say that moral considerations play no role in his practical deliberations and that moral beliefs form no part of his motivation for acting as he does.
Recommended publications
  • Skepticism and Pluralism Ways of Living a Life Of
    SKEPTICISM AND PLURALISM WAYS OF LIVING A LIFE OF AWARENESS AS RECOMMENDED BY THE ZHUANGZI #±r A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2004 By John Trowbridge Dissertation Committee: Roger T. Ames, Chairperson Tamara Albertini Chung-ying Cheng James E. Tiles David R. McCraw © Copyright 2004 by John Trowbridge iii Dedicated to my wife, Jill iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS In completing this research, I would like to express my appreciation first and foremost to my wife, Jill, and our three children, James, Holly, and Henry for their support during this process. I would also like to express my gratitude to my entire dissertation committee for their insight and understanding ofthe topics at hand. Studying under Roger Ames has been a transformative experience. In particular, his commitment to taking the Chinese tradition on its own terms and avoiding the tendency among Western interpreters to overwrite traditional Chinese thought with the preoccupations ofWestern philosophy has enabled me to broaden my conception ofphilosophy itself. Roger's seminars on Confucianism and Daoism, and especially a seminar on writing a philosophical translation ofthe Zhongyong r:pJm (Achieving Equilibrium in the Everyday), have greatly influenced my own initial attempts to translate and interpret the seminal philosophical texts ofancient China. Tamara Albertini's expertise in ancient Greek philosophy was indispensable to this project, and a seminar I audited with her, comparing early Greek and ancient Chinese philosophy, was part ofthe inspiration for my choice ofresearch topic. I particularly valued the opportunity to study Daoism and the Yijing ~*~ with Chung-ying Cheng g\Gr:p~ and benefited greatly from his theory ofonto-cosmology as a means of understanding classical Chinese philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • L Rathnam Dissertation
    The Politics of Skepticism: Montaigne and Zhuangzi on Freedom, Toleration, and the Limits of Government by Lincoln Edward Ford Rathnam A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science University of Toronto © Copyright by Lincoln Edward Ford Rathnam 2018 ii The Politics of Skepticism: Montaigne and Zhuangzi on Freedom, Toleration, and the Limits of Government Lincoln Rathnam Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science 2018 Abstract: Contemporary political discourse often centers on a shared set of normative commitments: freedom, toleration, and limited government. This dissertation examines the theoretical basis for these commitments, through a comparative study of two eminent skeptics: Michel de Montaigne and Zhuangzi. Both develop forms of skepticism that are rooted in analyses of the phenomena of diversity and disagreement. They contend that our inability to reach convergence on central philosophical questions demonstrates the fundamental limitations of human knowledge. I argue that both offer novel and powerful arguments connecting these skeptical epistemological theses with the relevant normative commitments. In particular, both take skepticism to advance human freedom, by clearing away obstacles to effective action. As beings who are raised within a particular community, we inevitably acquire certain habits that constrain the forms of thought and action open to us. Skepticism helps us to recognize the contingency of those forms. In the interpersonal realm, both writers contend that skepticism generates an attitude of toleration towards others who live differently. This is because it undermines the theoretical claims upon which most forms of intolerance are constructed. I defend this claim with reference to the various forms of intolerance that existed in each writer’s context, Warring States era China and France during the Wars of Religion.
    [Show full text]
  • The Status of Cosmic Principle (Li) in Neo-Confucian Metaphysics
    jeeloo liu THE STATUS OF COSMIC PRINCIPLE (LI) IN NEO-CONFUCIAN METAPHYSICS Introduction In this article, I attempt to make use of Western metaphysical notions to explicate the cosmological variances in Chinese philosophical thinking, with specific reference to the debates among the Neo- Confucian thinkers. While I do not presume and argue that Chinese philosophers dealt with the same Western issues, I do believe that a comparative study of this nature can point to a new direction of think- ing concerning metaphysical pondering in Neo-Confucianism. This article is divided into three parts. In Part I, I employ Robert Nozick’s notion of natural cosmic state to analyze the fundamental difference between the Confucian and Daoist cosmologies. Even though this notion of natural cosmic state has no comparable match in Chinese philosophy, it may serve as an analytic and explanatory device for our comparative study of Chinese cosmology. In Part II, I employ Nicholas Rescher’s distinction between “laws of nature” and “laws for nature” to analyze the debate on the status of cosmic prin- ciple (li)a between Zhou Dunyib and Zhu Xic on the one hand, and Zhang Zaid and Wang Fuzhie on the other.1 In Part III, I employ the notion of supervenience,as defined by Jaegwon Kim,to argue that in the debate on the status of cosmic principle, it is Zhang Zai and Wang Fuzhi’s view that better preserves the causal relevance of cosmic principle in a physicalistic universe.2 In light of the three notions borrowed from contemporary Western metaphysics, I hope to offer an analytic reconstruction of the age-old debate on the status of cosmic principle (li).
    [Show full text]
  • The Old Master
    INTRODUCTION Four main characteristics distinguish this book from other translations of Laozi. First, the base of my translation is the oldest existing edition of Laozi. It was excavated in 1973 from a tomb located in Mawangdui, the city of Changsha, Hunan Province of China, and is usually referred to as Text A of the Mawangdui Laozi because it is the older of the two texts of Laozi unearthed from it.1 Two facts prove that the text was written before 202 bce, when the first emperor of the Han dynasty began to rule over the entire China: it does not follow the naming taboo of the Han dynasty;2 its handwriting style is close to the seal script that was prevalent in the Qin dynasty (221–206 bce). Second, I have incorporated the recent archaeological discovery of Laozi-related documents, disentombed in 1993 in Jishan District’s tomb complex in the village of Guodian, near the city of Jingmen, Hubei Province of China. These documents include three bundles of bamboo slips written in the Chu script and contain passages related to the extant Laozi.3 Third, I have made extensive use of old commentaries on Laozi to provide the most comprehensive interpretations possible of each passage. Finally, I have examined myriad Chinese classic texts that are closely associated with the formation of Laozi, such as Zhuangzi, Lüshi Chunqiu (Spring and Autumn Annals of Mr. Lü), Han Feizi, and Huainanzi, to understand the intellectual and historical context of Laozi’s ideas. In addition to these characteristics, this book introduces several new interpretations of Laozi.
    [Show full text]
  • Neo-Confucianism: Metaphysics, Mind, and Morality
    Neo-Confucianism: Metaphysics, Mind, and Morality BOOK PROSPECTUS JeeLoo Liu CONTENTS: SUMMARY OF CHAPTERS Since these selected Neo-Confucians had similar philosophical concerns and their various philosophical positions were based on largely the same Confucian classics, the best way to capture their philosophical variances is to present their views thematically rather than chronologically. The structure of this book lays out the metaphysical foundations for Neo-Confucian theories of mind and morality. The major common themes in Neo- Confucianism include: 1) The relationship between the two constituents of the universe—cosmic principle (li) and cosmic force (qi); 2) The debate on whether human nature, or human mind, is the exemplification of this cosmic principle; 3) The analysis of the roots of human good and evil as a way to answer the question of what makes human morality possible. This book is divided into three parts, which deal with these three issues as they evolved from one Neo-Confucian philosopher to the next. The eight philosophers’ views are presented in three segments, as this arrangement best captures both the focus of their disagreements and the continuity of the philosophical development of Neo-Confucianism. Part I. Neo-Confucian Metaphysics: from Cosmology to Ontology Neo-Confucians were generally concerned with establishing a moralistic cosmology, or we can say what they developed was a form of moral metaphysics. In their view, there is a higher order governing the cosmos, which they call ‘heavenly principle’, and this higher order has many moral attributes. At the same time, Neo-Confucians also embraced the Chinese philosophical tradition (founded in Yijing) of positing a cosmic force (qi) as the material/physical foundation of the universe.
    [Show full text]
  • Selections from the Zhuangzi: Chapter 3, "The Secret of Caring for Life"
    Primary Source Document with Questions (DBQs) S E L E C T I O N F R O M T H E Z H U A N G Z I : C H A P T E R 3 , “ T H E S E C R E T O F C A R I N G F O R L I F E ” Introduction Zhuangzi (also called Zhuang Zhou) was an historically verifiable man who lived somewhere around 360-280 BCE. The long book that bears his name is a combination of material that represents his own thinking and of other writings incorporated by various compilers and editors. Like Confucius, Mencius, Han Fei and others, Zhuangzi lived during the time when the kings of the Zhou dynasty had little real power and the kingdom had disintegrated into feudal states that were constantly at war with each other in shifting patterns of alliances and enmities. During the Warring States period (480-221 BCE), Zhuangzi and Laozi were not considered to be part of a single school of thought. Zhuangzi is more concerned with escaping from the world; Laozi, with cunning ways of ruling it. During the Han dynasty, both works’ concern with the Dao (the “Way” of Heaven) and their mystical understanding of that term inspired historians to lump them together under the single category of “Daoism.” The name stuck. Zhuangzi and Laozi are now forever linked as the two great progenitors of Daoist philosophy and religion. Selected Document Excerpt with Questions From Sources of Chinese Tradition, compiled by Wm. Theodore de Bary and Irene Bloom, 2nd ed., vol.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of Zhuangzi and the Commentatorial Tradition of Guo Xiang
    THE PHILOSOPHY OF ZHUANGZI AND THE COMMENTATORIAL TRADITION OF GUO XIANG Desislava Damyanova Guo Xiang (also known as Kuo Hsiang or Zixuan) is the author of the most important commentary on Zhuangzi – one of the classical Daoist texts.1 He is also known as the person who implemented the current arrangement of thirty-three chapters divided into inner, outer and miscellaneous sections. Although Guo’s initial aim might have been to elucidate the ideas in the original text, his commentary on Zhuangzi represents a substantial philosophical achievement compared to the core text. It contains many original ideas and we shall examine the textual issues on which he is commenting in a try to get a deeper insight into their meaning. Guo Xiang2 practiced his philosophical pursuits this way – within the framework of the Daoist classic – and his manner has served as a blueprint for the later Neo-Confucian synthesis of the Chinese thought. 1 There is some controversy in the recent years over the true authorship of Guo’s commentary - the earliest source, the Jin Shu (Standard History of the Jin Dynasty), accuses Guo Xiang of plagiarizing all but two chapters of the commentary from Xiang Xiu (d. 300 CE, writing a generation earlier). “Current scholarship, while acknowledging that Guo made use of Xiang Xiu’s work and other earlier commentaries, still credits Guo as the principal author. The evidence for this recognition falls into three main areas. Firstly, the most innovative philosophical features in the commentary do not correspond with those in other works by Xiang Xiu. Secondly, in the early twentieth century, a postface to the commentary was discovered which details the work Guo carried out and finally, various linguistic analyses and references in other works suggest that Guo is the principal author.” <http://www.iep.utm.edu/guoxiang/>10.10.2012 2 Actually very little is known about the life of Guo Xiang: he lived in a time of great political upheaval and his own career was one of consistent and significant success.
    [Show full text]
  • The Power of an Alleged Tradition: a Prophecy Flattering Han Emperor Wu and Its Relation to the Sima Clan*
    The Power of an Alleged Tradition: A Prophecy Flattering Han Emperor Wu and its Relation to the Sima Clan* by Dorothee Schaab-Hanke . es muß stets eine lange Übermittlerkette vorhanden sein, damit sich die Hinweise oder Gedanken, die Kommentare, wie immer man es nennt, dehnen. Sie müsen durch zehn Hirne hindurch, um einen Satz zu ergeben.** (Alexander Kluge) Introduction During the early reign of Liu Che ᄸ࿺, posthumously honored as Emperor Wu r. 141–87) of the Han, a severe struggle for infl uence and power seems to) ܹن have arisen among competing groups of experts concerned with the establishment of new imperial rites. This is at least the impression that the Shiji͑৩ (The Scribe’s Record) conveys to the reader in chapter 28, the “Treatise on the Feng and Shan Sacrifi ces” (Fengshan shuܱᑐए). According to the account given there, the compet- ing partners in this struggle were mainly the ru ኵ (here used in the sense of scholars who maintained that any advice in the question of ritual should entirely be based upon evidence drawn from the “Classics”) and a group of specialists called fangshī ʦ (a term which should be translated by “masters of techniques” rather than by the often used, but rather biased term magicians). * I am indebted to Prof. Dr. Hans Stumpfeldt (Hamburg), Dr. Achim Mittag (Essen) and Dr. Monique Nagel- Angermann (Münster) for their helpful and inspiring comments on the text. Special thanks to Dr. Martin Svens- son Ekström (Stockholm), Prof. Dr. E. Bruce Brooks and Dr. A. Taeko Brooks (Amherst, Mass.) as well as two anonymous readers for the BMFEA for their competent and engaged revising of the draft.
    [Show full text]
  • The “Masters” in the Shiji
    T’OUNG PAO T’oungThe “Masters” Pao 101-4-5 in (2015) the Shiji 335-362 www.brill.com/tpao 335 The “Masters” in the Shiji Martin Kern (Princeton University) Abstract The intellectual history of the ancient philosophical “Masters” depends to a large extent on accounts in early historiography, most importantly Sima Qian’s Shiji which provides a range of longer and shorter biographies of Warring States thinkers. Yet the ways in which personal life experiences, ideas, and the creation of texts are interwoven in these accounts are diverse and uneven and do not add up to a reliable guide to early Chinese thought and its protagonists. In its selective approach to different thinkers, the Shiji under-represents significant parts of the textual heritage while developing several distinctive models of authorship, from anonymous compilations of textual repertoires to the experience of personal hardship and political frustration as the precondition for turning into a writer. Résumé L’histoire intellectuelle des “maîtres” de la philosophie chinoise ancienne dépend pour une large part de ce qui est dit d’eux dans l’historiographie ancienne, tout particulièrement le Shiji de Sima Qian, qui offre une série de biographies plus ou moins étendues de penseurs de l’époque des Royaumes Combattants. Cependant leur vie, leurs idées et les conditions de création de leurs textes se combinent dans ces biographies de façon très inégale, si bien que l’ensemble ne saurait être considéré comme l’équivalent d’un guide de la pensée chinoise ancienne et de ses auteurs sur lequel on pourrait s’appuyer en toute confiance.
    [Show full text]
  • A Reconstruction of Zhuangzi's Philosophy on Transcendence
    religions Article The Big and the Great: A Reconstruction of Zhuangzi’s Philosophy on Transcendence Limei Jiang Center of Value & Culture, School of Philosophy, Beijing Normal University, Beijing 100875, China; [email protected] Received: 29 November 2018; Accepted: 25 December 2018; Published: 4 January 2019 Abstract: This essay attempts to demonstrate the logic of Zhuangzi in his different attitudes toward “debate on big and small” by bringing into discussion the two versions of translation in the English languages, which provide a new approach to analyze the difference in the controversial commentaries on Zhuangzi. This essay points out that the ideal of “free and easy wandering” is a type of positive pleasure. By means of rational thinking and imagination, one’s searching for the external values is turned into the internal pursuit for wisdom in the transformation of things. Zhuangzi’s theory of transcendence not only provides the subject with multi-perspectives, but also substitutes the self-identity with self-value. Through the interaction between self-awareness and self-reaction, the subject can be unified with the great Dao through purposive activities. However, Guo Xiang’s commentary cancels the necessity of self-cultivation and negates the purposefulness of the subject, which underestimates the value of Zhuangzi’s construction of transcendence. Keywords: positive pleasure; purposiveness; self-awareness; self-reflection; no-self 1. Introduction The “debate on big and small” (xiaoda zhi bian小'K¨) was raised in the first chapter, Free and Easy Wandering (xiaoyaoyou逍e8), of the Zhuangzi. It is also discussed in other chapters such as On Making Things Fit Together (qiwulunPiº) and Autumn Waters (qiushuiË4).
    [Show full text]
  • The Paradigm of Harmony in Zhang Zai's Philosophical System
    The Great Harmony : The Paradigm of Harmony in Zhang Zai’s Philosophical System Filippo Costantini TESI DOCTORAL UPF / 2016 DIRECTOR DE LA TESI Dr. Manel Ollé Rodriguez DEPARTAMENT D’HUMANITATS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to express my sincere gratitude to the people who helped to make the completion of this work possible. I am grateful to my academic advisor, Professor Manel Ollé generously offered guidance and direction allowing the completion of this work. I am also grateful to my former advisor Albert Galvany who helped at the beigninning of this journey, and unfortunately could not guide me to the end of this work. I am grateful to Professor José Antonio Cervera who gave me the opportunity to experience a period of this investigation in Mexico, and helped me in the publication of my first academic article. I also owe a debt of gratitude to Professor Gianluca Magi who has been a constant source of inspiration over the course of my undergraduate studies. I am thankful to my former Professors Alessandra Brezzi and Claudia Pozzana for their teachings and encouragement all along these years of my academic studies. I would also like to thank my fellow Roberto Figliulo who always helped me and encouraged me over these years. My dear friend Amorini Katjuscia who patiently helped me work through the editing process of this dissertation. Finally, I must thank Noemi Pucci and my family for their kind assistance and support throughout the years. iii iv Abstract Harmony is one of the most important concepts of the Confucian tradition. Along Confucianism, harmony represented most of the time the ultimate ideal that man needs to pursue.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ghosts of Monotheism: Heaven, Fortune, and Universalism in Early Chinese and Greco-Roman Historiography
    The Ghosts of Monotheism: Heaven, Fortune, and Universalism in Early Chinese and Greco-Roman Historiography FILIPPO MARSILI Saint Louis University [email protected] Abstract: This essay analyzes the creation of the empires of Rome over the Medi- terranean and of the Han dynasty over the Central Plains between the third and the second centuries BCE. It focuses on the historiographical oeuvres of Polybius and Sima Qian, as the two men tried to make sense of the unification of the world as they knew it. The essay does away with the subsequent methodological and conceptual biases introduced by interpreters who approached the material from the vantage point of Abrahamic religions, according to which transcendent per- sonal entities could favor the foundation of unitary political and moral systems. By considering the impact of the different contexts and of the two authors’ sub- jective experiences, the essay tries to ascertain the extent to which Polybius and Sima Qian tended to associate unified rule with the triumph of universal values and the establishment of superior, divine justice. All profound changes in consciousness, by their very nature, bring with them characteristic amnesias. Out of such oblivions, in specific historical circumstances, spring narratives.—Benedict Anderson1 The nation as the subject of History is never able to completely bridge the aporia between the past and the present.—Prasenjit Duara2 Any structure is the ingenuous re-proposition of a hidden god; any systemic approach might actually constitute a crypto-theology.—Benedetto Croce3 Introduction: Monotheism, Systemic Unities, and Ethnocentrism Scholars who engage in comparisons are often wary of the ethnocentric biases that lurk behind their endeavors.
    [Show full text]