Evaluating the Theory of Mind Hypothesis of Autism. Current

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Evaluating the Theory of Mind Hypothesis of Autism. Current CURRENT DIRECTIONS IN PSYCHOLOGICAL SCIENCE Evaluating the Theory-of-Mind Hypothesis of Autism Helen Tager-Flusberg Boston University School of Medicine ABSTRACT—Two decades ago, the theory-of-mind hypoth- Two decades ago, Baron-Cohen and his colleagues revolu- esis of autism was introduced by Baron-Cohen and his tionized autism research when they introduced the theory- colleagues; this theory provided a unified cognitive expla- of-mind hypothesis to explain the main behavioral symptoms nation for the key social and communication symptoms in that characterize this neurodevelopmental disorder. Their initial that disorder. I evaluate the theory-of-mind hypothesis in studies showed that most children with autism whose mental and light of studies that have addressed several key questions: verbal abilities were well beyond the 4-year-old level never- Do children with autism develop theory-of-mind concepts? theless failed the Sally–Anne task and other related tasks How can we explain why some children with autism pass (Baron-Cohen, Leslie, & Frith, 1985). Deficits in the acquisition theory-of-mind tasks? Do deficits in theory of mind account of a theory of mind provided a plausible explanation for the major for the major impairments that characterize autistic dis- symptoms of autism, especially impairments in social reci- order? Current research supports the view that autism procity and communication, thus providing the first integrated involves delays and deficits not only in the development of account of the cognitive mechanisms that might underlie several a theory of mind but also in additional aspects of social- key behaviors that define the disorder. The original studies have affective information processing that extend beyond the been replicated many times by different research teams, and traditional boundaries of theory of mind. there is little doubt that children with autism have difficulty attributing mental states to themselves or to other people. KEYWORDS—autism; theory of mind; social cognition; com- Yet despite the robustness of the empirical findings, there is munication now less excitement and increasing skepticism among many investigators about the significance of the theory-of-mind hy- Daily social life depends on the ability to evaluate the behavior pothesis of autism. Questions about the universality and of other people on the basis of their mental states, such as their uniqueness of theory-of-mind impairments in autism, and about goals, emotions, and beliefs. This is accomplished by dedicated how this hypothesis could account for the earliest manifestations cognitive systems, collectively referred to as theory of mind.By of autistic symptoms, have been raised (Tager-Flusberg, 2001). age four, children normally pass tasks that tap mental-state Autism is generally defined on the basis of impairments not only understanding, including the hallmark false-belief tasks that in social and communicative functioning but also in restricted require a child to distinguish between the world as it really is and or repetitive behavior patterns. The theory-of-mind hypothesis the way it might be represented (incorrectly) in the mind of does not extend to explaining these areas of impairment; nor another person. In the classic Sally–Anne false-belief task, a does it explain some of the strengths that are characteristic of child is told the following story, accompanied by supporting people with autism, such as their superior visual-attention skills. pictures or toy props: Sally places her ball in a basket and goes The past decade has witnessed an exponential increase in out to play; while she is gone, Anne takes the ball from the basket research on autism. Today, autism is clearly understood to be a and hides it inside a box. The child is then asked where Sally will complex and heterogeneous set of related developmental dis- look for the hidden ball (or where she thinks it will be located) orders in which no single cognitive mechanism or cause can when she returns to play with it again (see Fig. 1). account for the variety of symptoms and range in their expres- sion. Even the social-communication impairments cannot be explained exclusively on the basis of theory-of-mind impair- ments. Nevertheless, current research supports the view that Address correspondence to Helen Tager-Flusberg, Department of Anatomy & Neurobiology, Boston University School of Medicine, 715 children and adults with autism have problems processing Albany Street L-814, Boston, MA 02118; e-mail: [email protected]. mental-state information; that when they are able to infer mental Volume 16—Number 6 Copyright r 2007 Association for Psychological Science 311 Theory-of-Mind Hypothesis of Autism pass false-belief tasks. At the same time, research has shown that older children with different disorders (e.g., nonsigning deaf children; Peterson, Wellman, & Liu, 2005) fail these tasks— evidence that challenges the notion that theory-of-mind deficits are universal and specific to autism. More recent studies have taken a developmental approach by including a wider range of tasks that tap a child’s ability to reason about mental states from the early preschool years to adoles- cence. For example, Steele, Joseph, and Tager-Flusberg (2003) conducted a longitudinal study in a large sample of children with autism; the participants were administered a battery of nine developmentally sequenced reasoning tasks ranging from tasks appropriate for toddlers (assessing the ability to understand the concept of pretense and the ability to attribute desire to others), young children (assessing the ability to correctly match others’ emotions to situations and to understand others’ knowledge and false beliefs), or older children and young adolescents (assessing understanding of others’ second-order false belief, nonliteral language, traits and intentions, and moral judgments). Over two thirds of the children made some gains over the course of 1 year, and although all the children were delayed relative to their age, a small number of the most able adolescents passed some of the more advanced tasks. Peterson and her colleagues (Peterson et al., 2005) used a set of five tasks that formed a coherent scale of theory-of-mind concepts, from desire to false belief and hid- den emotions. The children with autism were generally similar to the other groups in their ability to pass the tasks according to their developmental sequence, but unlike the other groups, children with autism found false belief harder than hidden Fig. 1. The Sally–Anne false-belief task. To test theory-of-mind skills, emotions. While children with autism develop some under- children are presented with a story in which (from the top frame to the bottom) Sally (left) has a basket and Ann (right) has a box; Sally puts her standing of desire and emotion, belief and other cognitive states marble in the basket; Sally leaves; Ann takes the marble from the basket seem to pose a unique challenge to this population. and puts it in the box; and Sally returns to look for the marble. Subjects are then asked whether Sally will look for the marble in the basket or the box. Reprinted from Autism: Explaining the Enigma, by U. Frith, 1989, EXECUTIVE FUNCTIONS, LANGUAGE, AND THEORY Blackwell Publishers, p. 83. Copyright 1989, Blackwell Publishers. OF MIND IN AUTISM Reprinted with permission. An important question that has generated considerable research states, they tend not to use the same neurocognitive systems as focuses on how some children with autism pass theory-of-mind do nonautistic people; and that performance on theory-of-mind tasks. For nonautistic children, performance on classic theory- tasks can account for some, though not all, of the severity of the of-mind tasks reflects intuitive social insights into people or social and communication symptoms that define this disorder. conceptual knowledge of mental states coupled with general cognitive skills that support the verbal processing, memory of A DEVELOPMENTAL PERSPECTIVE ON THEORY OF key narrative events, and inhibition of spontaneous responses MIND IN AUTISM that are central to the tasks. In contrast, studies of children with autism suggest that such children treat theory-of-mind tasks as Most studies investigating theory of mind in autism focused on logical-reasoning problems, relying primarily on language and the transition that takes place at the age of four, when children other nonsocial cognitive processes in lieu of social insight. typically first understand false belief. This narrow perspective Children with autism generally have executive-function appeared to reduce a complex social-cognitive developmental deficits that require planning, flexibility, or working memory progression to a categorical capacity indexed by passing or combined with inhibitory control (Ozonoff et al., 2004). Perfor- failing a single task, thus encouraging the notion that autism mance on false-belief tasks by both typically developing chil- could be defined as the ‘‘absence’’ of a theory of mind. Yet in all dren and children with autism is significantly related to these studies that have been conducted, some children with autism aspects of executive control (Joseph & Tager-Flusberg, 2004). 312 Volume 16—Number 6 Helen Tager-Flusberg Children with better planning skills and inhibitory control are theory of mind is not based on the same foundational social in- more likely to pass false-belief tasks, supporting the view that sights that are provided by a domain-specific theory-of-mind successful performance on false-belief tasks requires one to mechanism. This conclusion is consistent with functional neu- maintain a false representation of an event in working memory roimaging studies, which have shown that high-functioning while resisting the tendency to predict a person’s action on the adults with autism who pass theory-of-mind tasks activate basis of what one knows to be true. different brain regions when solving such problems. When Language ability has also been closely linked to the devel- nonautistic controls process theory-of-mind tasks they typically opment of theory-of-mind skills (see Astington & Baird, 2005).
Recommended publications
  • Theory of Mind As Inverse Reinforcement Learning. Current
    Available online at www.sciencedirect.com ScienceDirect Theory of mind as inverse reinforcement learning 1,2 Julian Jara-Ettinger We review the idea that Theory of Mind—our ability to reason think or want based on how they behave. Research in about other people’s mental states—can be formalized as cognitive science suggests that we infer mental states by inverse reinforcement learning. Under this framework, thinking of other people as utility maximizers: constantly expectations about how mental states produce behavior are acting to maximize the rewards they obtain while mini- captured in a reinforcement learning (RL) model. Predicting mizing the costs that they incur [3–5]. Using this assump- other people’s actions is achieved by simulating a RL model tion, even children can infer other people’s preferences with the hypothesized beliefs and desires, while mental-state [6,7], knowledge [8,9], and moral standing [10–12]. inference is achieved by inverting this model. Although many advances in inverse reinforcement learning (IRL) did not have Theory of mind as inverse reinforcement human Theory of Mind in mind, here we focus on what they learning reveal when conceptualized as cognitive theories. We discuss Computationally, our intuitions about how other minds landmark successes of IRL, and key challenges in building work can be formalized using frameworks developed in a human-like Theory of Mind. classical area of AI: model-based reinforcement learning 1 Addresses (hereafter reinforcement learning or RL) . RL problems 1 Department of Psychology, Yale University, New Haven, CT, United focus on how to combine a world model with a reward States function to produce a sequence of actions, called a policy, 2 Department of Computer Science, Yale University, New Haven, CT, that maximizes agents’ rewards while minimizing their United States costs.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Language in Theory of Mind Development
    Top Lang Disorders Vol. 34, No. 4, pp. 313–328 Copyright c 2014 Wolters Kluwer Health | Lippincott Williams & Wilkins The Role of Language in Theory of Mind Development Jill G. de Villiers and Peter A. de Villiers Various arguments are reviewed about the claim that language development is critically connected to the development of theory of mind. The different theories of how language could help in this process of development are explored. A brief account is provided of the controversy over the capacities of infants to read others’ false beliefs. Then the empirical literature on the steps in theory of mind development is summarized, considering studies on both typically developing and various language-delayed children. Suggestions are made for intervention by speech language pathologists to enhance the child’s access to understanding the minds of others. Key words: conversation, false beliefs, false complements, language, narrative, theory of mind N THIS ARTICLE, we review arguments on interactions between language and ToM I and evidence for the claim that children’s in both typically developing and language- language acquisition is crucially connected to delayed children. We end with suggestions their development of a theory of mind (ToM). for using language interventions to facilitate Theory of mind refers to the child’s ability to children’s understanding of their own mental understand that other people have minds, and states as well as the minds of others. those minds contain beliefs, knowledge, de- sires, and emotions that may be different from THEORIES OF THE RELATIONSHIP those of the child. If the child can figure out BETWEEN LANGUAGE AND ToM those contents, then other people’s behavior will begin to make sense and, therefore, be Many writers have made a convincing case predictable and explainable.
    [Show full text]
  • Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory?
    Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory? Keywords: Consciousness, Higher-Order Theories, Theory of Mind, Mind-reading, Metacognition. 1 Introduction Many of our mental states are phenomenally conscious. It feels a certain way, or to borrow Nagel's expression, there is something it is like to be in these states. Examples of phenomenally conscious states are those one undergoes while looking at the ocean or at a red apple, drinking a glass of scotch or a tomato juice, smelling coee or the perfume of a lover, listening to the radio or a symphonic concert, or feeling pain or hunger. A theory of consciousness has to explain the distinctive properties that phe- nomenally conscious states have and other kind of states lack. Higher-Order Representational (HOR) theories1 attempt to provide such an explanation. Ac- coding to these theories, phenomenally conscious states are those that are the objects of some kind of higher-order process or representation. There is some- thing higher-order, a meta-state, in the case of phenomenal conscious mental states, which is lacking in the case of other kind of states. According to these theories, consciousness depends on our Theory of Mind. A Theory of Mind, henceforth ToM, is the ability of humans to identify their own mental states and attribute mental states dierent from their owns to others. Such an ability can, at least conceptually, be decomposed into another two: mindreading and metacognition. Human beings are able to entertain representations of other people men- tal states thanks to the mindreading ability. We attribute beliefs, perceptions, feelings or desires to other people and predict and explain their behaviour ac- cordingly.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Mind for a Humanoid Robot
    Theory of Mind for a Humanoid Robot Brian Scassellati MIT Artificial Intelligence Lab 545 Technology Square – Room 938 Cambridge, MA 02139 USA [email protected] http://www.ai.mit.edu/people/scaz/ Abstract. If we are to build human-like robots that can interact naturally with people, our robots must know not only about the properties of objects but also the properties of animate agents in the world. One of the fundamental social skills for humans is the attribution of beliefs, goals, and desires to other people. This set of skills has often been called a “theory of mind.” This paper presents the theories of Leslie [27] and Baron-Cohen [2] on the development of theory of mind in human children and discusses the potential application of both of these theories to building robots with similar capabilities. Initial implementation details and basic skills (such as finding faces and eyes and distinguishing animate from inanimate stimuli) are introduced. I further speculate on the usefulness of a robotic implementation in evaluating and comparing these two models. 1 Introduction Human social dynamics rely upon the ability to correctly attribute beliefs, goals, and percepts to other people. This set of metarepresentational abilities, which have been collectively called a “theory of mind” or the ability to “mentalize”, allows us to understand the actions and expressions of others within an intentional or goal-directed framework (what Dennett [15] has called the intentional stance). The recognition that other individuals have knowl- edge, perceptions, and intentions that differ from our own is a critical step in a child’s development and is believed to be instrumental in self-recognition, in providing a perceptual grounding during language learning, and possibly in the development of imaginative and creative play [9].
    [Show full text]
  • Mind Perception Daniel R. Ames Malia F. Mason Columbia
    Mind Perception Daniel R. Ames Malia F. Mason Columbia University To appear in The Sage Handbook of Social Cognition, S. Fiske and N. Macrae (Eds.) Please do not cite or circulate without permission Contact: Daniel Ames Columbia Business School 707 Uris Hall 3022 Broadway New York, NY 10027 [email protected] 2 What will they think of next? The contemporary colloquial meaning of this phrase often stems from wonder over some new technological marvel, but we use it here in a wholly literal sense as our starting point. For millions of years, members of our evolving species have gazed at one another and wondered: what are they thinking right now … and what will they think of next? The interest people take in each other’s minds is more than idle curiosity. Two of the defining features of our species are our behavioral flexibility—an enormously wide repertoire of actions with an exquisitely complicated and sometimes non-obvious connection to immediate contexts— and our tendency to live together. As a result, people spend a terrific amount of time in close company with conspecifics doing potentially surprising and bewildering things. Most of us resist giving up on human society and embracing the life of a hermit. Instead, most perceivers proceed quite happily to explain and predict others’ actions by invoking invisible qualities such as beliefs, desires, intentions, and feelings and ascribing them without conclusive proof to others. People cannot read one another’s minds. And yet somehow, many times each day, most people encounter other individuals and “go mental,” as it were, adopting what is sometimes called an intentional stance, treating the individuals around them as if they were guided by unseen and unseeable mental states (Dennett, 1987).
    [Show full text]
  • Machine Theory of Mind
    Machine Theory of Mind Neil C. Rabinowitz∗ Frank Perbet H. Francis Song DeepMind DeepMind DeepMind [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Chiyuan Zhang S. M. Ali Eslami Matthew Botvinick Google Brain DeepMind DeepMind [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Abstract 1. Introduction Theory of mind (ToM; Premack & Woodruff, For all the excitement surrounding deep learning and deep 1978) broadly refers to humans’ ability to rep- reinforcement learning at present, there is a concern from resent the mental states of others, including their some quarters that our understanding of these systems is desires, beliefs, and intentions. We propose to lagging behind. Neural networks are regularly described train a machine to build such models too. We de- as opaque, uninterpretable black-boxes. Even if we have sign a Theory of Mind neural network – a ToM- a complete description of their weights, it’s hard to get a net – which uses meta-learning to build models handle on what patterns they’re exploiting, and where they of the agents it encounters, from observations might go wrong. As artificial agents enter the human world, of their behaviour alone. Through this process, the demand that we be able to understand them is growing it acquires a strong prior model for agents’ be- louder. haviour, as well as the ability to bootstrap to Let us stop and ask: what does it actually mean to “un- richer predictions about agents’ characteristics derstand” another agent? As humans, we face this chal- and mental states using only a small number of lenge every day, as we engage with other humans whose behavioural observations.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Mind by Margaret Alic Updated on Dec 23, 2009 From
    Theory of Mind By Margaret Alic Updated on Dec 23, 2009 from http://www.education.com/reference/article/theory-of-mind/ Theory of mind (ToM) is the intuitive understanding of one's own and other people's minds or mental states— including thoughts, beliefs, perceptions, knowledge, intentions, desires, and emotions—and of how those mental states influence behavior. Sometimes called intuitive psychology, folk psychology, or even mind-reading, ToM is an innate human ability. The understanding that others have mental states different from one's own makes it possible to infer what others are thinking and to predict their behavior. This ability to recognize one's own state of mind and those of others is central to human consciousness. The study of ToM and identification of the skills comprising ToM is a rapidly changing the field of developmental psychology. THE THEORY OF TOM The word theory in ToM refers to a person's tacit belief rather than to theory in the scientific sense. However, ToM is similar to a scientific theory in that it enables one to interpret and predict another's actions by evaluating their thoughts, beliefs, desires, or emotions. ToM also qualifies as a theory in the sense that the representations of reality generated by ToM are not directly observable. The ability to develop a ToM is a cognitive ability that develops by degrees from infancy through childhood and adolescence on into adulthood. It forms a basis for a child's acquisition of language and the development of appropriate social behavior and skills. ToM includes the ability to understand that the representations generated in one's mind do not necessarily reflect the real world and that other people may hold different representations.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Mind (Neural Basis)
    Theory of Mind (Neural Basis) Rebecca Saxe Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences, MIT In Press at: Encyclopedia of Consciousness The externally observable components of human actions carry only a tiny fraction of the information that matters. Human observers are vastly more interested in perceiving or inferring the mental states - the beliefs, desires and intentions - that lie behind the observable shell. If a person checks her watch, is she uncertain about the time, late for an appointment, or bored with the conversation? If a person shoots his friend on a hunting trip, did he intend revenge or just mistake his friend for a partridge? The mechanism people use to infer and reason about another person’s states of mind is called a ‘Theory of Mind’ (ToM). One of the most striking discoveries of recent human cognitive neuroscience is that there is a group of brain regions in human cortex that selectively and specifically underlie this mechanism. The importance of mental states for behavior prediction is especially clear when the person doing the behavior is misinformed: that is, when the actor has a false belief. False beliefs therefore figure heavily in the study of ToM. The original “False Belief task” was developed for use with pre-school aged children. In the basic design, a child watches while a puppet places an object in location A. The puppet leaves the scene and the object is transferred to location B. The puppet returns and the child is asked to predict where the puppet will look for the object. Three-year-olds say the puppet will look in location B, where the object actually is; older children say the puppet will look in location A, where the puppet last saw the object.
    [Show full text]
  • What Does the Study of Autism Tell Us About the Craft of Folk Psychology?
    See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/224930550 What does the study of autism tell us about the craft of folk psychology? CHAPTER · JANUARY 2008 CITATION READS 1 67 2 AUTHORS, INCLUDING: Richard Griffin Tufts University 11 PUBLICATIONS 286 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE Available from: Richard Griffin Retrieved on: 31 January 2016 Griffin, R. & Dennett, D.C. (2008). What does the study of autism tell us about the craft of folk attribution of "intentions" was at the basis of folk psychology has seen something of a psychology? In T. Striano & V. Reid (Eds.) Social Cognition: Development, Neuroscience, and resurgence. In the 1980s and 1990s, the child-development literature focused largely on Autism (pp. 254-280). Wiley-Blackwell. what Bennett (1978) called the "rockbottom issue" of mental-state-attribution - beliefs about beliefs - publishing hundreds of experiments on the topic (Wellman, Cross & Watson, 2001). Yet, with technical advances in probing the knowledge of infants and the ascendance of neuroimaging, the focus on belief has waned, and has shifted to the What Does the Study of Autism Tell us about the putatively "simpler" mental states of intentions, goals, and desires (Johnson, 2000). Craft of Folk Psychology? According to a recent New York Times article entitled "Cells that read minds" (Blakeslee 2006), Premack and Woodruff's initial claim appears to have been vindicated. The article touts the properties, or at least certain claims about the properties, of "mirror" Richard Griffin and Daniel C. Dennett neurons, first discovered in the premotor cortex of macaque monkeys (Gallese, Fadiga, Fogassi, & Rizzolatti, 1996).
    [Show full text]
  • The You-Turn in Philosophy of Mind: on the Significance of Experiences That Aren’T Mine
    THE YOU-TURN IN PHILOSOPHY OF MIND: ON THE SIGNIFICANCE OF EXPERIENCES THAT AREN’T MINE A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI‘I AT MĀNOA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2018 By Joshua Stoll Dissertation Committee: Arindam Chakrabarti, Chairperson Vrinda Dalmiya Ronald Bontekoe Joseph Tanke Jesse Knutson Ashley Maynard Acknowledgements I could not have written this dissertation without the help and support of others, including my family, my friends, and my professors at the UH Mānoa Department of Philosophy. My parents Luci and Howie Stoll have always been there to unwaveringly support my endeavors. They have been a great source of love, inspiration, and guidance. I owe them everything I have become. My brother Adam and his wife Lisa and their kids have also been a great source of love, inspiration, and guidance. And I’m thankful that my nieces and nephew really got me moving on this project by playfully asking me every Thanksgiving (perhaps with some prodding from my parents) if I have finished it yet. In addition, I’d like to thank my fellow graduate student colleague-friends in the department, in particular: Matt Izor, Elyse Byrnes, Ben Zenk, Brandon Underwood, Jane Allred, and Joel Label. More particularly, out of this group, I’d like to thank Sydney Morrow for being a close friend and great officemate, as well as Ian Nicolay, for being a close friend and great roommate. Our camaraderie and support of each other, the community we formed, truly made me feel at home here in Hawai‘i.
    [Show full text]
  • Artificial Intelligence and Its Applications in Theory of Mind
    المجلة اﻷكاديمية لﻷبحاث والنشر العلمي | اﻹصدار الرابع | تأريخ اﻹصدار: 9102-8-5 ISSN: 2706-6495 Artificial Intelligence and its Applications in Theory of Mind Hanan Mohammed al-qahtani King Fahd University Email: [email protected] Abstract The first use of the phrase “Artificial Intelligence” in 1956 is attributed to John McCarthy of the University of Massachusetts. It is a fairly new field which involves programming computers to play games, comprehend and respond to natural language, reproduce neural networks like those of humans and exhibit sensitivity (Hear, see, move, and react to the environment) like humans (this branch is termed robotics). First we must define Artificial Intelligence. A number of proposed definitions would be considered here. Keywords: Artificial Intelligence, Theory of Mind, AI www.ajrsp.com 1 المجلة اﻷكاديمية لﻷبحاث والنشر العلمي | اﻹصدار الرابع | تأريخ اﻹصدار: 9102-8-5 ISSN: 2706-6495 Introduction The first use of the phrase “Artificial Intelligence” in 1956 is attributed to John McCarthy of the University of Massachusetts. It is a fairly new field which involves programming computers to play games, comprehend and respond to natural language, reproduce neural networks like those of humans and exhibit sensitivity (Hear, see, move, and react to the environment) like humans (this branch is termed robotics). First we must define Artificial Intelligence. A number of proposed definitions would be considered here. It is the science and engineering of making intelligent machines, especially intelligent computer programs. The ability of a computer or other machine to perform actions thought to require intelligence… An intelligent machine would be more flexible than a computer and would engage in the kind of "thinking" that people actually do.
    [Show full text]
  • Machine Theory of Mind
    Machine Theory of Mind Neil C. Rabinowitz 1 Frank Perbet 1 H. Francis Song 1 Chiyuan Zhang 2 Matthew Botvinick 1 Abstract of others, such as their desires and beliefs. This ability is typically described as our Theory of Mind (Premack Theory of mind (ToM) broadly refers to humans’ & Woodruff, 1978). While we may also leverage our ability to represent the mental states of others, own minds to simulate others’ (e.g. Gordon, 1986; Gallese including their desires, beliefs, and intentions. & Goldman, 1998), our ultimate human understanding of We design a Theory of Mind neural network – other agents is not measured by a correspondence between a ToMnet – which uses meta-learning to build our models and the mechanistic ground truth, but instead such models of the agents it encounters. The by how much they enable prediction and planning. ToMnet learns a strong prior model for agents’ future behaviour, and, using only a small num- In this paper, we take inspiration from human Theory of ber of behavioural observations, can bootstrap Mind, and seek to build a system which learns to model to richer predictions about agents’ characteris- other agents. We describe this as a Machine Theory of tics and mental states. We apply the ToMnet Mind. Our goal is not to assert a generative model of to agents behaving in simple gridworld environ- agents’ behaviour and an algorithm to invert it. Rather, we ments, showing that it learns to model random, focus on the problem of how an observer could learn au- algorithmic, and deep RL agents from varied tonomously how to model other agents using limited data populations, and that it passes classic ToM tasks (Botvinick et al., 2017).
    [Show full text]