The You-Turn in Philosophy of Mind: on the Significance of Experiences That Aren’T Mine

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The You-Turn in Philosophy of Mind: on the Significance of Experiences That Aren’T Mine THE YOU-TURN IN PHILOSOPHY OF MIND: ON THE SIGNIFICANCE OF EXPERIENCES THAT AREN’T MINE A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI‘I AT MĀNOA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2018 By Joshua Stoll Dissertation Committee: Arindam Chakrabarti, Chairperson Vrinda Dalmiya Ronald Bontekoe Joseph Tanke Jesse Knutson Ashley Maynard Acknowledgements I could not have written this dissertation without the help and support of others, including my family, my friends, and my professors at the UH Mānoa Department of Philosophy. My parents Luci and Howie Stoll have always been there to unwaveringly support my endeavors. They have been a great source of love, inspiration, and guidance. I owe them everything I have become. My brother Adam and his wife Lisa and their kids have also been a great source of love, inspiration, and guidance. And I’m thankful that my nieces and nephew really got me moving on this project by playfully asking me every Thanksgiving (perhaps with some prodding from my parents) if I have finished it yet. In addition, I’d like to thank my fellow graduate student colleague-friends in the department, in particular: Matt Izor, Elyse Byrnes, Ben Zenk, Brandon Underwood, Jane Allred, and Joel Label. More particularly, out of this group, I’d like to thank Sydney Morrow for being a close friend and great officemate, as well as Ian Nicolay, for being a close friend and great roommate. Our camaraderie and support of each other, the community we formed, truly made me feel at home here in Hawai‘i. Last but far from least, I would like to thank my professors at UH Mānoa for their guidance and support. This project would not have been possible without the patience, guidance, feedback, and support of my committee members in particular. They have shown me what it truly means to be a scholar. And most of all, I’d like to thank the chair of my committee Arindam Chakrabarti. His patient guidance, brilliance, and sense of humor gave me a scholarly ideal to strive for. I owe him, not just for invaluable philosophical insights – which often, and to my great delight, came in the form of puns and jokes – but for his great support and advocacy of my project. i Abstract This dissertation challenges a dominant way of thinking in philosophy of mind that gives rise to a variety of problems of other minds and, thus, different versions of the threat of solipsism. I contend that these problems arise because of a problematic philosophical starting point. For such ways of thinking start from the removed, contemplative position of a solitary individual, conceptually isolated from the world, trying to bridge the conceptual divide between himself or herself and the world at large. Appealing to a recent trend in cognitive science called enactivism, as well as the medieval Indian philosophy of Kaśmīr Śaivism, I suggest that we can dissolve these problems without entirely neglecting their significance if we take a different starting position for philosophy of mind: the lived position. In the lived position, the possibility of solipsism, for the most part, simply goes unconsidered since we are always already involved in participating with each other to make sense of the world. ii Table of Contents Acknowledgements……………………………………………………………………………………………………..i Abstract……………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….ii Introduction…………………………………………………………………………………………………………………1-8 CHAPTER 1 A Critical Review of Epistemological Problems of Other Minds A critical review of how certain conceptions of subjectivity and knowledge naturally lead to epistemological problems of other minds. Approaches to this so-called “problem” are articulated and critiqued. 1.1 Introduction…………………………………………………………………………………………...……….9-11 1.2 Inference and Knowing That You Exist…………………………………………………………….11-13 1.2.1 The Argument from Analogy……………………………………………………………………………13-19 1.2.2 The Argument from Remainder……………………………………………………………………….19-27 1.3 Folk Psychology: Knowing What You Think………………………………………………………27-29 1.3.1 Theory-Theory…………………………………………………………………………………………………29-35 1.3.2 Simulation Theory……………………………………………………………………………………………35-43 1.3.3 Some Problems with Folk Psychology………………………………………………………………43-48 CHAPTER 2 A Critical Review of the Conceptual Problem of Other Minds It is suggested that the epistemological problems discussed are grounded in a faulty conception of the subject and subjectivity. Approaches to these conceptual difficulties are articulated and critiqued. 2.1 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………………………………49-51 2.2 Conceptual Problems………………………………………………………………………………………..51-55 2.3 The Problem of Generality…………………………………………………………………………………55-56 2.3.1 The Criteria-Based Approach……………………………………………………………………………..56-59 2.3.2 Imaginative Extension………………………………………………………………………………………..59-65 2.4 The Problem of Unity………………………………………………………………………………………….66 2.4.1 The Problem of Generality Misses the Point……………………………………………………….66-71 2.4.2 Action as Behavior Proper…………………………………………………………………………………..71-79 2.4.3 Emotions and Behavior……………………………………………………………………………………….79-84 2.4.4 Joel Smith’s Conceptual Problem of Other Bodies……………………………………………….84-86 iii CHAPTER 3 The Axiological Problem of Other Minds and a Critique of Cognitivism An axiologically relevant example of the conceptual difficulties discussed in the previous chapter is critically reviewed. The conceptual difficulties we’ve been discussing are diagnosed and two other possible ways of thinking about subjectivity in its intersubjective element are addressed. 3.1 Introduction…………………………………………………………………………………………………………….87-89 3.2 Caspar Hare and Other Less Important Subjects……………………………………………………...89 3.2.1 Egocentric Presentism, the Peacemaker, and Harmony…………………………………………...89-91 3.2.2 Egocentric Presentism and S-World Semantics…………………………………………………………91-94 3.2.3 The Grounding Problem……………………………………………………………………………………………94-96 3.2.4 The Generalization Problem……………………………………………………………………………………..97-100 3.2.5 The Problem of Irreducibly Egocentric Preferences…………………………………………………..100-102 3.2.6 A Critique of Egocentric Presentism………………………………………………………………………….102-110 3.3 A Critique of Cognitivism…………………………………………………………………………………………..110-111 3.3.1 Logocentric Intellectualism……………………………………………………………………………………….111-112 3.3.2 Epistemic Purity and Scientism About Other Minds…………………………………………………..112-114 3.3.3 Implausibly Thin Subjects…………………………………………………………………………………………..114-116 3.4 Going Beyond Cognitivism………………………………………………………………………………………….117-118 3.4.1 Indian Aesthetics and Affective Intersubjectivity………………………………………………………..118-122 3.4.2 Sartre and Ontological Intersubjectivity………………………………………………………………………122-127 CHAPTER 4 How to Do Things with Others It is argued that subjectivity in its intersubjective element is primarily conceived through sustained interactive practices of sense making. To this extent, others are recognized in their subjective element as fellow participants in understanding the world. This is constrained by the manners in which we address each other and what we address each other about. 4.1 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………………………………………..128-130 4.2 Recognition and Enactive Intersubjectivity………………………………………………………………….130-131 4.2.1 Embodied Concepts…………………………………………………………………………………………………….131-135 4.2.2 Autonomous Sense-Making…………………………………………………………………………………………136-140 4.2.3 Enactive Social Perception and Participatory Sense-Making…………………………………………140-150 4.2.4 Perception and Accessibility: Another Conceptual Problem………………………………………….150-158 4.2.5 Recognition and Availability………………………………………………………………………………………….158-164 4.3 Address and Situatedness: Enacting the Recognition of Other Minds……………………………164-165 4.3.1 Address: Situated Recognition………………………………………………………………………………………165-171 4.3.2 Between Us: Situating Minds and Norms………………………………………………………………………171-181 Conclusion………………………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….182-187 Bibliography……………………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….188-195 iv Introduction “My resistance to solipsism – which is as lively as any I should offer to doubt the cogito – proves that I have always known that the Other existed… Since the Other is not a representation nor a system of representations nor a necessary unity of our representations, he cannot be probable: he cannot at first be an object.” _Jean-Paul Sartre_1 Well before we can conceive of ourselves in the first-person, we are addressed second- persons. We are talked to prior to talking to others; we are looked at, gestured towards, and readily responsive to these looks and gestures of others before we are consciously focusing to look at or gesture towards anyone. From this starting point of being a second-person first, I seamlessly graduate to recognizing myself as already recognized by others as being “one of us,” and as being addressed as such. My sense of myself as myself arises out of my having been a “you” for someone else. Self-consciousness is thus read through a socialized or intersubjective lens. In the words of Emmanuel Levinas, there is no escaping the appeal of the neighbor.2 Yet, on the other hand, as we become aware of being a center of consciousness, as the first-person point of view takes hold of our psychophysical lives – perhaps with a little nudge from Cartesian meditations – we can find ourselves stuck in a conundrum regarding others. For the first-person sense of experience implies an exclusiveness of experience: Dasein, as Heidegger said, is in each case mine.
Recommended publications
  • What the Problem of Other Minds Really Tells Us About Descartes
    What the Problem of Other Minds Really Tells us about Descartes Gideon Manning The College of William and Mary Ever since the first generation Cartesian Gerauld de Cordemoy wrote a self- standing book dedicated to the problem of other minds philosophers have proceeded as though Descartes’ work entails some version of the problem.1 In this paper I evaluate Descartes’ own contribution to creating and answering skepticism about other minds. It is my contention, first, that for most of his working life Descartes did not see the problem as distinct from the problem of the external world. Second, that when he was finally presented with the problem in a late letter from Henry More, Descartes looked not to behavior, but to a body’s origins as a guide to who does and does not have a mind. Specifically, the response Descartes offers to More appeals to a shared “nature,” something which has struck many readers as an ineffectual response, even as a response which begs the question. On the contrary, and this is my third contention, Descartes’ response is a fairly plausible one when read as utilizing the meaning of “nature” as complexio found in Meditation Six.2 Though it may be translated as “complex,” complexio is really a technical Latin term coming from the medical tradition, likely introduced into the lexicon at Salerno in the tenth- or eleventh-century. It means, roughly, a unique composition of elements or qualities distinguishing species (and individual members of a species) from one another. By emphasizing our shared complexio Descartes is telling More that having resolved the problem of the external world we can rely on God’s uniform action in the world to entail joining a mind to members of our species.
    [Show full text]
  • Stellar 08 Cover Page
    Stellar Undergraduate Research Journal Oklahoma City University Volume 2, 2008 Stellar Oklahoma City University’s Undergraduate Research Journal Inside are 2007-08 research papers spanning the disciplines at OCU, including criminology, English, economics, music, philosophy, political science, and psychology, representing the exceptional undergraduate research happening at Oklahoma City University. Editor-in-Chief: Gina Jennings Faculty Sponsor: Dr. Terry Phelps Stellar is published annually by Oklahoma City University. Opinions and beliefs herein do not necessarily reflect those of the university. Submissions are accepted from undergraduate students. Address all correspondence to: Stellar c/o The Learning Enhancement Center, 2501 N. Blackwelder Ave., Oklahoma City, OK 73106. All submissions are subject to editing. 2 Contents Because I Do Not Hope to Turn Again:T.S. Eliot as the First Confessional Poet Kristin May……………………………………………………………3 Who Goes First Does Matter Unless No One Goes First: Personal Dyadic Space and Order Amy D. Simpson and Stacie Abla………….………………………...11 The Relationship Between Black Farmers and the United States Department of Agriculture Zachary L. Newland…..........................................................................19 Don’t Be Afraid of the Ball! Wittgenstein on Knowledge of Other Minds Jacob Coleman......................................................................................28 The Effects of Culture, Gender, and Recipient of Money on Moral Comfort Dashala Cubit, Lacey Novinska, and Danny Gering…………………39
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Mind As Inverse Reinforcement Learning. Current
    Available online at www.sciencedirect.com ScienceDirect Theory of mind as inverse reinforcement learning 1,2 Julian Jara-Ettinger We review the idea that Theory of Mind—our ability to reason think or want based on how they behave. Research in about other people’s mental states—can be formalized as cognitive science suggests that we infer mental states by inverse reinforcement learning. Under this framework, thinking of other people as utility maximizers: constantly expectations about how mental states produce behavior are acting to maximize the rewards they obtain while mini- captured in a reinforcement learning (RL) model. Predicting mizing the costs that they incur [3–5]. Using this assump- other people’s actions is achieved by simulating a RL model tion, even children can infer other people’s preferences with the hypothesized beliefs and desires, while mental-state [6,7], knowledge [8,9], and moral standing [10–12]. inference is achieved by inverting this model. Although many advances in inverse reinforcement learning (IRL) did not have Theory of mind as inverse reinforcement human Theory of Mind in mind, here we focus on what they learning reveal when conceptualized as cognitive theories. We discuss Computationally, our intuitions about how other minds landmark successes of IRL, and key challenges in building work can be formalized using frameworks developed in a human-like Theory of Mind. classical area of AI: model-based reinforcement learning 1 Addresses (hereafter reinforcement learning or RL) . RL problems 1 Department of Psychology, Yale University, New Haven, CT, United focus on how to combine a world model with a reward States function to produce a sequence of actions, called a policy, 2 Department of Computer Science, Yale University, New Haven, CT, that maximizes agents’ rewards while minimizing their United States costs.
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER4: Private Language Argument and the Problem of Other Minds
    84 CHAPTER4: Private Language Argument and the Problem of Other Minds The problem of other minds is an age old predicament in the history of philosophy. It existed during the time of Plato and still remains a quandary in philosophical discussions at length. We find in Plato's Theaetetus the question: "Are you quite certain that the several colours .appear to a dog or to any animal whatever as they appear to you? ... Or that anything appears the same to you as to another man?"lls This problem is a kind of other minds dilemma. The problem of other minds is found in Wittgenstein' s philosophy too. As far as Wittgenstein is concerned, the problem arises due to the self- centred perception of knowledge. When one thinks that he can have knowledge of his own psychological states and on that basis he constructs the world from his own private experiences or sense data, problem of other minds take place. This is a major issue which Wittgenstein strikes to resolve. This issue originally came up from the Cartesian Meditations where Descartes takes his own self as the being to doubt, by his method arrives at the conclusion that one has the best possible access to his own private self. Wittgenstein. believes that it is a ns Benjamin Jowett (tr.), Plato's Theaetetus: With Introduction and Analysis (Rockville, Maryland: Serenity Publishers, 2009), p. 102. 85 false idea to construct the world view in this way. His private language argument is related to the problem of other minds in a quite integrated way.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Language in Theory of Mind Development
    Top Lang Disorders Vol. 34, No. 4, pp. 313–328 Copyright c 2014 Wolters Kluwer Health | Lippincott Williams & Wilkins The Role of Language in Theory of Mind Development Jill G. de Villiers and Peter A. de Villiers Various arguments are reviewed about the claim that language development is critically connected to the development of theory of mind. The different theories of how language could help in this process of development are explored. A brief account is provided of the controversy over the capacities of infants to read others’ false beliefs. Then the empirical literature on the steps in theory of mind development is summarized, considering studies on both typically developing and various language-delayed children. Suggestions are made for intervention by speech language pathologists to enhance the child’s access to understanding the minds of others. Key words: conversation, false beliefs, false complements, language, narrative, theory of mind N THIS ARTICLE, we review arguments on interactions between language and ToM I and evidence for the claim that children’s in both typically developing and language- language acquisition is crucially connected to delayed children. We end with suggestions their development of a theory of mind (ToM). for using language interventions to facilitate Theory of mind refers to the child’s ability to children’s understanding of their own mental understand that other people have minds, and states as well as the minds of others. those minds contain beliefs, knowledge, de- sires, and emotions that may be different from THEORIES OF THE RELATIONSHIP those of the child. If the child can figure out BETWEEN LANGUAGE AND ToM those contents, then other people’s behavior will begin to make sense and, therefore, be Many writers have made a convincing case predictable and explainable.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Other Minds: a Yoruba Hermeneutic Deconstruction of the Logical Behaviourist Approach
    The Problem of Other Minds: A Yoruba Hermeneutic Deconstruction of the Logical Behaviourist Approach by Babalola Joseph Balogun [email protected] Department of Philosophy Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile-Ife, Nigeria : Abstract Using the hermeneutics of the Yoruba linguistic framework, the paper reconsiders the scepticism about other minds, especially from the logical behaviourist perspectives. As a theory, logical behaviourism equates other minds with the overt movements of other bodies. The paper advances arguments against logical behaviourism, particularly on the ground that it blurred our traditional concept of mind as something different from the body. The paper concludes by proposing a search for an appropriate methodological approach through which the logical behaviourist account could be improved to properly incorporate the role of the mind in the production of physical behaviour of the body. Keywords: Other Minds, Logical Behaviourism, Yoruba, hermeneutics Introduction Our intention in this paper is not to set out a theory of other minds that will explain the theoretical flaws inherent in the existing theories. Rather, it is a demonstration of the inadequacy of one of the earliest theories of other minds, namely, logical behaviourism. Hence, the paper is essentially a critique. This critique is basically aimed at arousing the need for a search for a better theory of other minds that will take into consideration some of the identified shortcomings of the existing theories, especially as they are somewhat reducible to the behaviourist attitude. It should be noted that such exercise is not new, as several contemporary commentators have amply shown. However, the novelty of the present paper derives from the fact that it is the first time an objection to any of the theories of other minds would be attempted using an African language, especially Yoruba language.
    [Show full text]
  • Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory?
    Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory? Keywords: Consciousness, Higher-Order Theories, Theory of Mind, Mind-reading, Metacognition. 1 Introduction Many of our mental states are phenomenally conscious. It feels a certain way, or to borrow Nagel's expression, there is something it is like to be in these states. Examples of phenomenally conscious states are those one undergoes while looking at the ocean or at a red apple, drinking a glass of scotch or a tomato juice, smelling coee or the perfume of a lover, listening to the radio or a symphonic concert, or feeling pain or hunger. A theory of consciousness has to explain the distinctive properties that phe- nomenally conscious states have and other kind of states lack. Higher-Order Representational (HOR) theories1 attempt to provide such an explanation. Ac- coding to these theories, phenomenally conscious states are those that are the objects of some kind of higher-order process or representation. There is some- thing higher-order, a meta-state, in the case of phenomenal conscious mental states, which is lacking in the case of other kind of states. According to these theories, consciousness depends on our Theory of Mind. A Theory of Mind, henceforth ToM, is the ability of humans to identify their own mental states and attribute mental states dierent from their owns to others. Such an ability can, at least conceptually, be decomposed into another two: mindreading and metacognition. Human beings are able to entertain representations of other people men- tal states thanks to the mindreading ability. We attribute beliefs, perceptions, feelings or desires to other people and predict and explain their behaviour ac- cordingly.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Mind for a Humanoid Robot
    Theory of Mind for a Humanoid Robot Brian Scassellati MIT Artificial Intelligence Lab 545 Technology Square – Room 938 Cambridge, MA 02139 USA [email protected] http://www.ai.mit.edu/people/scaz/ Abstract. If we are to build human-like robots that can interact naturally with people, our robots must know not only about the properties of objects but also the properties of animate agents in the world. One of the fundamental social skills for humans is the attribution of beliefs, goals, and desires to other people. This set of skills has often been called a “theory of mind.” This paper presents the theories of Leslie [27] and Baron-Cohen [2] on the development of theory of mind in human children and discusses the potential application of both of these theories to building robots with similar capabilities. Initial implementation details and basic skills (such as finding faces and eyes and distinguishing animate from inanimate stimuli) are introduced. I further speculate on the usefulness of a robotic implementation in evaluating and comparing these two models. 1 Introduction Human social dynamics rely upon the ability to correctly attribute beliefs, goals, and percepts to other people. This set of metarepresentational abilities, which have been collectively called a “theory of mind” or the ability to “mentalize”, allows us to understand the actions and expressions of others within an intentional or goal-directed framework (what Dennett [15] has called the intentional stance). The recognition that other individuals have knowl- edge, perceptions, and intentions that differ from our own is a critical step in a child’s development and is believed to be instrumental in self-recognition, in providing a perceptual grounding during language learning, and possibly in the development of imaginative and creative play [9].
    [Show full text]
  • Seeing Souls: Wittgenstein and Cavell on the “Problem of Other Minds”
    Seeing Souls: Wittgenstein and Cavell on the “Problem of Other Minds” JÔNADAS TECHIO The human body is the best picture of the human soul. LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN, Philosophical Investigations […] not to believe there is such a thing as the human soul is not to know what the human body is […] CAVELL, The Claim of Reason Introduction The so-called “Part I” of Philosophical Investigations (PI) contains many claims con- cerning the grammar of psychological predicates, and particularly about the condi- tions for ascribing them to others. The following are some of the most well-known (and also most representative) among such claims: (i) “only of a living human being and what resembles (behaves like) a living human being can one say: it has sensa- tions; it sees; is blind; hears; is deaf; is conscious or unconscious”;1 (ii) “An ‘inner process’ stands in need of outward criteria.”2 The content of these and other kindred remarks has led a great number of readers to ascribe some kind of “externalistic”3 ac- count to the author of the Investigations. !!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!! 1. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. P. M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 2009), §281. 2. Ibid., §580. 3. I mean this in a very broad sense, so as to cover many different attempts of including in the analysis of the content of (presumably “inner”) mental states some features of the subject’s larger. (“external”) environment, such as her behavior, her community’s standards, the constitution of the objects with which she relates, etc. CONVERSATIONS 1 64! Now, “externalism” comes in many flavors.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind Perception Daniel R. Ames Malia F. Mason Columbia
    Mind Perception Daniel R. Ames Malia F. Mason Columbia University To appear in The Sage Handbook of Social Cognition, S. Fiske and N. Macrae (Eds.) Please do not cite or circulate without permission Contact: Daniel Ames Columbia Business School 707 Uris Hall 3022 Broadway New York, NY 10027 [email protected] 2 What will they think of next? The contemporary colloquial meaning of this phrase often stems from wonder over some new technological marvel, but we use it here in a wholly literal sense as our starting point. For millions of years, members of our evolving species have gazed at one another and wondered: what are they thinking right now … and what will they think of next? The interest people take in each other’s minds is more than idle curiosity. Two of the defining features of our species are our behavioral flexibility—an enormously wide repertoire of actions with an exquisitely complicated and sometimes non-obvious connection to immediate contexts— and our tendency to live together. As a result, people spend a terrific amount of time in close company with conspecifics doing potentially surprising and bewildering things. Most of us resist giving up on human society and embracing the life of a hermit. Instead, most perceivers proceed quite happily to explain and predict others’ actions by invoking invisible qualities such as beliefs, desires, intentions, and feelings and ascribing them without conclusive proof to others. People cannot read one another’s minds. And yet somehow, many times each day, most people encounter other individuals and “go mental,” as it were, adopting what is sometimes called an intentional stance, treating the individuals around them as if they were guided by unseen and unseeable mental states (Dennett, 1987).
    [Show full text]
  • Machine Theory of Mind
    Machine Theory of Mind Neil C. Rabinowitz∗ Frank Perbet H. Francis Song DeepMind DeepMind DeepMind [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Chiyuan Zhang S. M. Ali Eslami Matthew Botvinick Google Brain DeepMind DeepMind [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Abstract 1. Introduction Theory of mind (ToM; Premack & Woodruff, For all the excitement surrounding deep learning and deep 1978) broadly refers to humans’ ability to rep- reinforcement learning at present, there is a concern from resent the mental states of others, including their some quarters that our understanding of these systems is desires, beliefs, and intentions. We propose to lagging behind. Neural networks are regularly described train a machine to build such models too. We de- as opaque, uninterpretable black-boxes. Even if we have sign a Theory of Mind neural network – a ToM- a complete description of their weights, it’s hard to get a net – which uses meta-learning to build models handle on what patterns they’re exploiting, and where they of the agents it encounters, from observations might go wrong. As artificial agents enter the human world, of their behaviour alone. Through this process, the demand that we be able to understand them is growing it acquires a strong prior model for agents’ be- louder. haviour, as well as the ability to bootstrap to Let us stop and ask: what does it actually mean to “un- richer predictions about agents’ characteristics derstand” another agent? As humans, we face this chal- and mental states using only a small number of lenge every day, as we engage with other humans whose behavioural observations.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Mind by Margaret Alic Updated on Dec 23, 2009 From
    Theory of Mind By Margaret Alic Updated on Dec 23, 2009 from http://www.education.com/reference/article/theory-of-mind/ Theory of mind (ToM) is the intuitive understanding of one's own and other people's minds or mental states— including thoughts, beliefs, perceptions, knowledge, intentions, desires, and emotions—and of how those mental states influence behavior. Sometimes called intuitive psychology, folk psychology, or even mind-reading, ToM is an innate human ability. The understanding that others have mental states different from one's own makes it possible to infer what others are thinking and to predict their behavior. This ability to recognize one's own state of mind and those of others is central to human consciousness. The study of ToM and identification of the skills comprising ToM is a rapidly changing the field of developmental psychology. THE THEORY OF TOM The word theory in ToM refers to a person's tacit belief rather than to theory in the scientific sense. However, ToM is similar to a scientific theory in that it enables one to interpret and predict another's actions by evaluating their thoughts, beliefs, desires, or emotions. ToM also qualifies as a theory in the sense that the representations of reality generated by ToM are not directly observable. The ability to develop a ToM is a cognitive ability that develops by degrees from infancy through childhood and adolescence on into adulthood. It forms a basis for a child's acquisition of language and the development of appropriate social behavior and skills. ToM includes the ability to understand that the representations generated in one's mind do not necessarily reflect the real world and that other people may hold different representations.
    [Show full text]