Our Informationally Disabled Courts Frederick Schauer

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Our Informationally Disabled Courts Frederick Schauer Our Informationally Disabled Courts Frederick Schauer Abstract: In order to carry out their functions of deciding particular cases and developing legal rules and principles, courts need information: not just information about the law, but also factual information about the particular matter in controversy and about the world in general. The way in which courts are structured, however, makes it more dif½cult for them to obtain the information they need than it is for most other public decision-making institutions. As the world becomes more complex, and as sophisticat- Downloaded from http://direct.mit.edu/daed/article-pdf/143/3/105/1830480/daed_a_00292.pdf by guest on 29 September 2021 ed scienti½c, technical, and ½nancial information becomes more central to litigation and to the judicial function, the systemic disabilities of the courts in obtaining the information they need become more apparent and increasingly more problematic. What makes a court a court? The question is im - por tant, but it lacks an obvious answer. We might distinguish courts from other decision-making institutions in terms of being staffed principally by those with legal training. And thus insofar as lawyers and judges occupy a sociologically discrete segment of professional culture,1 courts can be dis- tinguished by virtue of their sociological differenti- ation. Or we might begin with the fact that courts make decisions with procedures unlike those of FREDERICK SCHAUER, a Fellow of other decision-making environments. The modal the American Academy since 1993, number of parties in a court case is two; the modal is the David and Mary Harrison outcome has a winner and loser; and decisions are Distinguished Professor of Law at typically made by judges or other arbiters with no the University of Virginia. Previ- interest in the outcome. In these and various other ously, he was for eighteen years the Frank Stanton Professor of the ways, courts’ procedures differ from those of legis- First Amendment at the Harvard latures, administrative agencies, executive of½cials, Ken nedy School. His publications the military, and private corporations. Additionally, in clude Free Speech: A Philosopical or perhaps alternatively, law schools purport to train Enquiry (1982), Playing By the Rules: their students in the arcane art of thinking like a A Philosophical Examination of Rule- lawyer,2 and so what differentiates courts may be the Based Decision-Making in Law and in fact that they reach their decisions via methods of Life (1991), Pro½les, Probabilities, and Stereotypes (2003), Thinking Like a thinking and reasoning that differ from those we see Lawyer: A New Introduction to Legal in other environments. Reasoning (2009), and The Force of Each of these ways of differentiating courts–socio - Law (forthcoming 2014). logical, procedural, and methodological–constitutes © 2014 by the American Academy of Arts & Sciences doi:10.1162/DAED_a_00292 105 Our part of a complete account of how we have been stipulated or decided long be - Informa - should characterize and understand them, fore a case gets to the highest courts. But we tionally Disabled but my focus here will be on still another ought not to forget, for reasons we will Courts criterion, one we can call informa tional explore, that basic controversies of raw fact dif ferentiation: the array of information must be resolved before appellate deci- courts use in making decisions. This es - sion-making can take place. Long before say will concern a particular di men sion of Miranda v. Arizona reached the Su preme informational differentiation–the meth- Court and provided the platform for the ods by which courts obtain factual, scien- Court’s holding that suspects must be ti½c, and technical in for mation, and the informed of certain constitutional rights potential flaws inherent in those methods. prior to questioning, someone had to de - It is common to think of courts in terms cide that it was Ernesto Miranda who had Downloaded from http://direct.mit.edu/daed/article-pdf/143/3/105/1830480/daed_a_00292.pdf by guest on 29 September 2021 of their outputs: the decisions they make been arrested, that Mr. Miranda had made and the opinions they write. But these deci - statements that were used against him to sions are based on inputs, which fall into his disadvantage, and that he had not in two broad categories. The ½rst of these is fact been given the warnings that the the law. For some lawyers, judges, and Supreme Court held were constitutionally schol ars, the category of law is (and should mandated.5 Beneath virtually all appellate be) narrow, encompassing little more than decisions, therefore, are seemingly mun- statutes, constitutional provisions, report- dane factual questions that comprise most ed court cases, and the conventional meth - of what the courts do: determining just ods of legal reasoning and interpretation who did what; and how, why, and when of standard legal materials.3 Others under - they did it. stand the law as including not only the Often the factual inputs to judicial de - fore going, but also a broad range of moral, cisions also include those matters of sci- political, and pragmatic factors.4 And al - enti½c and technical knowledge that en - though the divisions be tween those hold- able judges and jurors to draw inferences ing broad and narrow conceptions of law from the more basic who-did-what kind of are profoundly important, this should not fact. Does exposure to certain substan ces ob scure the equal or greater importance of cause cancer, and if so, in whom and un - the other broad category of court inputs: der what circumstances? If a ½n ger print the world of fact. resembling that of the defendant is found The factual inputs to judicial decisions at the scene of a crime, how likely is it fall into two broad types. The one most that the defendant was there when the familiar to the public–largely from tele- crime was committed? Do certain exter- vision and other media, but sometimes nal features of an automobile tire indicate from personal experience–is the simple defective manufacture and an in creased question of what happened. Who was it likelihood of tire failure under normal that approached the bank teller with a gun driving conditions?6 and demanded money? Who started the It is profoundly important to ask wheth er ½ght? Did the Ford enter the intersection courts as presently constituted–especially ½rst, or was it the Toyota? And how fast courts in common-law systems such as the was the Ford going at the time? If we United States–are the institutions best spend too much of our time focusing only suited to make factual determinations of on Supreme Court cases, or even on appel - the two types just sketched, especially the late litigation more broadly, we may ig nore determination of general scienti½c, techni - factual issues of this variety, for often they cal, ½nancial, and related fact.7 This ques - 106 Dædalus, the Journal ofthe American Academy of Arts & Sciences tion is crucial in part because it raises issues For all of these reasons, therefore, it is es - Frederick of how to allocate social and public deci - sential to examine whether courts are well Schauer l sion-making among institutions of var ious equipped to make the factual determina- t types; for example, is regulatory policy best tions that have important consequences made administratively or through litiga- for individual litigants and, increasingly, tion?8 However, we cannot even begin to for social policy as well. There are several address such questions un less we can reasons to be lieve that courts may not be evaluate the respective competences of the suited to the task of adequate factual deter - various can didate institutionsin making mination; I will discuss ½ve of them here. the factual, technical, and scienti½c deter- minations on which sound policy -making First, courts–especially common-law d must rest. courts operating with rules developed in Downloaded from http://direct.mit.edu/daed/article-pdf/143/3/105/1830480/daed_a_00292.pdf by guest on 29 September 2021 The question of fact-½nding competence the context of a system in which juries among institutions is also relevant to con - were prevalent12–make their factual de - cerns about the shrinking number of trials terminations in accordance with rules of in the United States and about the decreas - evidence that frequently make inadmissi- y ing access to courts as venues for dispute ble that which in other contexts would be resolution (concerns at the center of sever- relevant information.13 For example, al other contributions to this volume). Tri- while the exclusion of hearsay evidence t als serve many purposes,9 most of which ensures the opportunity to confront and t are predicated on the view that litigation in cross-examine opposing witnesses and general, and trials in particular, have large - guards against the risk of overvaluation ly positive epistemic foundations: they get of potentially unreliable evidence, it nev- the facts right. But if the epistemic advan- ertheless excludes a considerable amount tages of courts are smaller than is often of evidence that investigators in other supposed, the concerns about fewer trials contexts would ½nd to be of at least some and limited ac cess need to be seen in a dif - use. Similarly, the rules of evidence typi- f ferent light. And even though trials (espe- cally preclude evidence of character and cially civil trials10) are becoming few er in evidence of past practices from being used number, they are increasingly used as the to establish what someone may have done t venue for making broad determinations of on a particular occasion.
Recommended publications
  • Judicial Supremacy and the Modest Constitution
    Judicial Supremacy and the Modest Constitution Frederick Schauert INTRODUCTION Judicial supremacy is under attack. From various points on the politi- cal spectrum, political actors as well as academics have challenged the idea that the courts in general, and the Supreme Court in particular, have a spe- cial and preeminent responsibility in interpreting and enforcing the Constitution. Reminding us that treating Supreme Court interpretations of the Constitution as supreme and authoritative has no grounding in constitu- tional text and not much more in constitutional history, these critics seek to relocate the prime source of interpretive guidance. The courts have an important role to play, these critics acknowledge, but it is a role neither greater than that played by other branches, nor greater than the role to be played by "the people themselves."' The critics' understanding of a more limited function for the judiciary in constitutional interpretation appears to rest, however, primarily on a highly contestable conception of the point of having a written constitution in the first place. According to this conception, a constitution, and espe- cially the Constitution of the United States, is the vehicle by which a de- mocratic polity develops its own fundamental values. A constitution, therefore, becomes both a statement of our most important values and the vehicle through which these values are created and crystallized. Under this conception of the role of a written constitution, it would indeed be a mis- take to believe that the courts should have the preeminent responsibility for interpreting that constitution. For this task of value generation to devolve Copyright © 2004 California Law Review, Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problematic Legacy of Cardozo
    Oregon Law Review Winter 2000 - Volume 79, Number 4 (Cite as: 79 Or. L. Rev. 1033) DAN SIMON* The Double-Consciousness of Judging: The Problematic Legacy of Cardozo Copyright © 2000, University of Oregon; Dan Simon INTRODUCTION There is a growing awareness in legal scholarship that a crisis of sorts pervades the legal field. In the now famous The Lost Lawyer, Dean Anthony Kronman has identified an adverse transformation of the character of the legal profession. n1 Professor Mary Anne Glendon has put forth a critique of the rights-based rhetoric that predominates legal discourse. n2 Professor Steven Smith has both broadened and deepened these discouraging observations by suggesting that the legal community is suffering from a crisis of faith. As Smith astutely points out, there is a fundamental problem with the integrity of legal discourse in that legal actors operate in a state of discordance between their beliefs and practices. Participants in this discourse have come to take for granted that the reasons they present in support of their positions are quite distinct from the "real reasons" that underlie [*1034] them. n3 Smith coined this duplicity a "schizophrenic condition," suggesting that it is a "sign of something deeply wrong in modern legal thought." n4 This paper explores the possibility that judicial reasoning might be one of the causes of this state of duplicity. This proposition is explored through an analysis of the work of Benjamin Nathan Cardozo, an exemplary and distinguished inhabitant of the American judicial pantheon. I will briefly review recent scholarship that champions his legacy as the product of renaissance-like qualities: encompassing brilliant judicial performance and insightful writing about judging.
    [Show full text]
  • Viewpoint Discrimination Marjorie Heins
    Hastings Constitutional Law Quarterly Volume 24 Article 3 Number 1 Fall 1996 1-1-1996 Viewpoint Discrimination Marjorie Heins Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/ hastings_constitutional_law_quaterly Part of the Constitutional Law Commons Recommended Citation Marjorie Heins, Viewpoint Discrimination, 24 Hastings Const. L.Q. 99 (1996). Available at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/hastings_constitutional_law_quaterly/vol24/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hastings Constitutional Law Quarterly by an authorized editor of UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Viewpoint Discrimination By MARJORIE HEINS* Table of Contents I. The Semantics of Suppression .......................... 105 A. Viewpoint Neutrality ................................ 105 B. Rules About Content ............................... 110 C. Political, Controversial, and Religious Speech ...... 115 II. Sex, Vulgarity, and Offensiveness ....................... 122 m. Government Benefits and Property ..................... 136 IV. Government Speech .................................... 150 V. Public Education: The Pico Paradox .................... 159 Conclusion ..................................................... 168 Introduction "If there is any fixed star in our constitutional constellation, it is that no official, high or petty, can prescribe what shall be orthodox in poli- tics, nationalism, religion, or other matters of opinion, or force citizens to confess by word or act their faith therein."1 With these words, Jus- * Director, American Civil Liberties Union Arts Censorship Project; Senior Staff Counsel, ACLU Legal Department; J.D., Harvard University, 1978; author, SEx, SIN, AND BLASPHEMY: A GuIDE TO AMERICA'S CENSORSHIP WARS (1993). The author participated in several of the cases or controversies mentioned in this Article.
    [Show full text]
  • The First Amendment As Ideology
    William & Mary Law Review Volume 33 (1991-1992) Issue 3 Article 5 March 1992 The First Amendment as Ideology Frederick Shauer Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmlr Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the First Amendment Commons Repository Citation Frederick Shauer, The First Amendment as Ideology, 33 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 853 (1992), https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmlr/vol33/iss3/5 Copyright c 1992 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmlr THE FIRST AMENDMENT AS IDEOLOGY FREDERICK SCHAUER* Not surprisingly, Learned Hand said it best. Writing for the Second Circuit in InternationalBrotherhood of Electrical Workers, Local 501 v. NLRB, 1 he captured beautifully the paradox I wish to explore here: The interest, which [the First Amendment] guards, and which gives it its importance, presupposes- that there are no ortho- doxies-religious, political, economic, or scientific-which are immune from debate and dispute. Back of that is the assump- tion-itself an orthodoxy, and the one permissible exception- that truth will be most likely to emerge, if no limitations are imposed upon utterances that can with any plausibility be regarded as efforts to present grounds for accepting or reject- 2 ing propositions whose truth the utterer asserts, or denies. I want to focus not on Hand's restatement of the standard marketplace-of-ideas principle that the value of freedom of speech lies in its instrumental value in (probabilistically) increasing the likelihood of identifying truth and rejecting falsehood.
    [Show full text]
  • ARISTOTLE and the CONCEPT of LAW John T. Valauri
    VALAURI_GALLEYS 5/10/2011 10:10:34 AM DIALECTICAL JURISPRUDENCE: ARISTOTLE AND THE CONCEPT OF LAW John T. Valauri* General theories of law struggle to do justice to the multiple dualities of the law.1 INTRODUCTION Western law, culture, and philosophy thought that they were say- ing goodbye to Aristotle as they entered into modernity, only now to find the ancient philosopher standing in wait as they leave mod- ernity and enter into post-modernity. But what use do we have for Aristotle at this time? He can perform a valuable service for us—he offers a therapy for the “bipolar disorder”2 in contemporary juris- prudence and philosophy.3 This disorder is manifested in the wide- spread tendency to approach and analyze philosophical topics as dueling dichotomies, incapable of resolution or reconciliation. It is all too often assumed at the outset that one is faced with a stark ei- ther/or sort of choice between alternatives, so participants in the philosophical debates arising out of this approach typically take one side of the dichotomy and see it as their task to marginalize and di- minish the other side of the dichotomy.4 H.L.A. Hart diagnosed one case of this disorder in his famous depiction of American jurispru- dence as torn between the noble dream that judges can always *- Professor of Law, Salmon P. Chase College of Law, Northern Kentucky University. B.A., 1972; J.D., 1975, Harvard. 1. JOSEPH RAZ, BETWEEN AUTHORITY AND INTERPRETATION 1 (2009). 2. In this Article, I will use the notion of a “bipolar disorder” in philosophy in a broader way to refer to a more general dichotomy problem common today in approaches to philoso- phical topics.
    [Show full text]
  • Of the First Amendment, John F
    +(,121/,1( Citation: 76 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 914 2007-2008 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Mon Nov 15 15:19:20 2010 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License -- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use: https://www.copyright.com/ccc/basicSearch.do? &operation=go&searchType=0 &lastSearch=simple&all=on&titleOrStdNo=0016-8076 Hohfeld's First Amendment Frederick Schauer* The First Amendment guarantees "the freedom of speech [and] of the press,"' but what exactly is the freedom that the First Amend- ment guarantees and that the First Amendment prohibits Congress (and, now, the states2) from abridging? What kinds of rights, structur- ally and not just substantively, are First Amendment rights? Who or what does the First Amendment protect, and against whom or what are they protected? These are hoary questions which lawyers, judges, and scholars have been wrestling with for generations, and so I will not pretend to be able to say very much that is substantially novel about the topic. Nevertheless, it may still be useful to look at the First Amendment through the lens of some large issues in the theory of rights, which is, of course, also a huge topic. To make things more manageable, therefore, I propose to examine the First Amendment in a Hohfeldian 3 way, looking at who might have First Amendment rights, whom those rights are rights against, and what duties or obliga- tions the existence of those rights imposes on others.
    [Show full text]
  • THE PRINCIPLE of LEGAL CERTAINTY in EC LAW Law and Philosophy Library
    THE PRINCIPLE OF LEGAL CERTAINTY IN EC LAW Law and Philosophy Library VOLUME 64 Managing Editors FRANCISCO J. LAPORTA, Department of Law, Autonomous University of Madrid, Spain ALEKSANDER PECZENIK, Department of Law, University of Lund, Sweden FREDERICK SCHAUER, John F. Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University, Cambridge, Mass., U.S.A. Former Managing Editors AULIS AARNIO, MICHEAL D. BAYLESt, CONRAD D. JOHNSONt, ALAN MABE Editorial Advisory Board AULIS AARNIO, Research Institute for Social Sciences, University of Tampere, Finland ZENON BANKOWSKI, Centre for Criminology and the Social and Philosophical Study of Law, University of Edinburgh PAOLO COMANDUCCI, University of Genoa, Italy ERNESTO GARZON VALDES, Institut fur Politikwissenschaft, Johannes Gutenberg Universitiit Mainz JOHN KLEINIG, Department of Law, Police Science and Criminal Justice Administration, John Jay College of Criminal Justice, City University of New York NEIL MacCORMICK, European Parliament, Brussels, Belgium WOJCIECH SADURSKI, European University Institute, Department of Law, Florence, Italy ROBERT S. SUMMERS, School of Law, Cornell University CARL WELLMAN, Department of Philosophy, Washington University THE PRINCIPLE OF LEGAL CERTAINTY IN EC LAW by JUHA RAITIO SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. A C.I.P Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-90-481-6264-2 ISBN 978-94-017-0353-6 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-0353-6 Printed on acid1ree paper All Rights Reserved © 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 2003 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover Ist edition 2003 No part of this publication may be reproduced Of utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, inc1uding photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Do Things with Hohfeld
    SCHLAG_BOOKPROOF-CROSS-REFERENCED_NEW_TOC (DO NOT DELETE) 3/5/2015 1:40 PM HOW TO DO THINGS WITH HOHFELD PIERRE SCHLAG* I. INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................... 186 II. SOME PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS............................................................. 187 A. Legal Conceptions as Relations of Form .............................................. 188 B. The Strands of Hohfeldian Thought ...................................................... 190 C. The Practicality of the Hohfeld’s Approach ......................................... 191 III. ERRORS OF TRANSPOSITION ........................................................................... 192 A. Of Ambiguity, Slippage, and Blending ................................................. 192 B. The Economic Import of Errors of Transposition ............................... 198 C. The Political Import of Errors of Transposition ................................... 199 IV. HOHFELD’S FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL RELATIONS ........................................ 200 V. ABUSE OF DEDUCTION—DERIVING RIGHTS FROM PRIVILEGES ............... 204 A. Missing the Excluded Middle—Eclipsing the Privilege–No Right Relation ................................................................................................... 206 B. Conceptual Abuse as Distorting Moral, Policy, and Political Argument ................................................................................................ 207 C. Distinguishing Injurious Interference in the Nonlegal
    [Show full text]
  • Towards an Institutional First Amendment Frederick Schauer
    University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Minnesota Law Review 2005 Towards an Institutional First Amendment Frederick Schauer Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/mlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Schauer, Frederick, "Towards an Institutional First Amendment" (2005). Minnesota Law Review. 682. https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/mlr/682 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Minnesota Law Review collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Article Towards an Institutional First Amendment Frederick Schauert How shall we subdivide the First Amendment? More spe- cifically, along which lines shall we carve free speech and free press doctrine? In designing the demarcations that are an in- evitable part of any area of legal doctrine, shall we locate those demarcations in distinctions among people, or among places, or among forms of behavior, or perhaps among something else? Subdivision is part and parcel of any body of law, and wisely creating the subdivisions is as central to First Amendment doc- trine as it is to torts, contracts, agency, antitrust, securities regulation, and of course much, much else. Traditionally, the First Amendment has been subdivided on the basis of the content of the communication. To put it dif- ferently, it has been traditionally supposed, roughly, that the First Amendment's Speech Clause protects speech. The First Amendment does not protect all speech, or even most speech, but the speech that it does protect is protected as speech, with relatively little regard for the identity of the speaker or the in- stitutional environment in which the speech occurs.
    [Show full text]
  • Faculty Research Working Papers Series
    Faculty Research Working Papers Series Regulation by Generalization Frederick Schauer and Richard Zeckhauser August 2005 RWP05-048 This paper can be downloaded without charge from: http://ksgnotes1.harvard.edu/Research/wpaper.nsf/rwp/RWP05-048 or The Social Science Research Network: http://ssrn.com/abstract=896125 The views expressed in the KSG Faculty Research Working Paper Series are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect those of the John F. Kennedy School of Government or Harvard University. Copyright belongs to the author(s). Papers may be downloaded for personal use only. Draft – 07/29/2005 REGULATION BY GENERALIZATION 1 Frederick Schauer and Richard Zeckhauser “Where there’s smoke, there’s fire,” says a venerable adage that informs many of our everyday decisions. Although what looks smoke may have a cause other than fire, smoke is so often the indicator of fire that it is rarely a bad strategy to presume the presence of fire from the observation of smoke. Similarly, when a promised payment does not arrive we assume it was not sent, even though checks sometimes do get lost in the mail. When a road is slippery in winter we presume the cause is ice, even though it could be spilled oil. And when a physician sees yellowing skin and nausea she concludes that her patient has hepatitis, although some rare diseases produce identical symptoms. Yet although it is common to infer a cause from the presence of its typical indicator, much of legal and regulatory practice is to the contrary. In criminal, civil, and regulatory law, we are often more reluctant to take action based on the likely cause of an observed consequence than a physician is to prescribe treatment based on the likely cause of observed symptoms.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Distinction Between Speech and Action
    Emory Law Journal Volume 65 Issue 2 The 2015 Randolph W. Thrower Symposium — The New Age of Communication: Freedom of Speech in the 21st Century 2015 On the Distinction Between Speech and Action Frederick Schauer Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.emory.edu/elj Recommended Citation Frederick Schauer, On the Distinction Between Speech and Action, 65 Emory L. J. 427 (2015). Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.emory.edu/elj/vol65/iss2/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Emory Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Emory Law Journal by an authorized editor of Emory Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. SCHAUER GALLEYSPROOFS2 1/14/2016 2:26 PM ON THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN SPEECH AND ACTION ∗ Frederick Schauer Does the First Amendment rest on a mistake? More specifically, is the First Amendment’s necessary distinction between speech and action fundamentally unsustainable? The First Amendment, in relevant part, protects “the freedom of speech.”1 By contrast, the First Amendment does not protect simply “freedom,” or “liberty.” And thus it appears, initially and obviously, that the First Amendment’s protections extend to some acts or events or behaviors but not others. Indeed, not only the First Amendment but also any coherent principle of freedom of speech presupposes a meaningful distinction between the activities encompassed by the principle and those that are not. Loosely and preliminarily, we can label the former “speech” and the latter “action.”2 And because any non-vacuous account of a free speech principle is premised on the idea that being an act of speech in the relevant sense grants to that act a degree of protection from restriction not granted to non-speech acts causing equivalent consequences,3 some sort of distinction between speech and action is a ∗ David and Mary Harrison Distinguished Professor of Law, University of Virginia.
    [Show full text]
  • Lon Fuller, the Model Code, and the Model Rules John M.A
    University of Arkansas at Little Rock William H. Bowen School of Law Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives Faculty Scholarship 1996 Lon Fuller, the Model Code, and the Model Rules John M.A. DiPippa University of Arkansas at Little Rock William H. Bowen School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://lawrepository.ualr.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Legal Profession Commons Recommended Citation John M. A. DiPippa, Lon Fuller, the Model Code, and the Model Rules, 37 S. Tex. L. Rev. 303 (1996). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LON FULLER, THE MODEL CODE, AND THE MODEL RULES JOHN M. A. DIPIPPA* I. INTRODUCTION .......................................... 304 A. Jurisprudence as the Framework of Lawyer Codes .. 305 B. The Rise and Fall of Lon Fuller's Jurisprudence,the Model Code, and the Model Rules .................. 309 II. AN OVERVIEW OF FULLER'S THOUGHT ................. 313 A . Introduction......................................... 313 B. Fuller's Place in American Jurisprudence............ 314 C. Law as a Structure of Social Order ................. 315 D. Law as the Language of Social Interaction .......... 318 E. The Moralities of Duty and Aspiration .............. 320 F. Fuller's View of Lawyers ............................ 324 III. FULLER'S INFLUENCE ON THE ABA's MODEL CODE ... 327 A . Introduction......................................... 327 B. The Joint Conference Statement ..................... 328 C. Drafting the Model Code ........................... 330 D. The Structure of the Model Code and Fuller's Jurisprudence ......................................
    [Show full text]