THE PRINCIPLE of LEGAL CERTAINTY in EC LAW Law and Philosophy Library

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

THE PRINCIPLE of LEGAL CERTAINTY in EC LAW Law and Philosophy Library THE PRINCIPLE OF LEGAL CERTAINTY IN EC LAW Law and Philosophy Library VOLUME 64 Managing Editors FRANCISCO J. LAPORTA, Department of Law, Autonomous University of Madrid, Spain ALEKSANDER PECZENIK, Department of Law, University of Lund, Sweden FREDERICK SCHAUER, John F. Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University, Cambridge, Mass., U.S.A. Former Managing Editors AULIS AARNIO, MICHEAL D. BAYLESt, CONRAD D. JOHNSONt, ALAN MABE Editorial Advisory Board AULIS AARNIO, Research Institute for Social Sciences, University of Tampere, Finland ZENON BANKOWSKI, Centre for Criminology and the Social and Philosophical Study of Law, University of Edinburgh PAOLO COMANDUCCI, University of Genoa, Italy ERNESTO GARZON VALDES, Institut fur Politikwissenschaft, Johannes Gutenberg Universitiit Mainz JOHN KLEINIG, Department of Law, Police Science and Criminal Justice Administration, John Jay College of Criminal Justice, City University of New York NEIL MacCORMICK, European Parliament, Brussels, Belgium WOJCIECH SADURSKI, European University Institute, Department of Law, Florence, Italy ROBERT S. SUMMERS, School of Law, Cornell University CARL WELLMAN, Department of Philosophy, Washington University THE PRINCIPLE OF LEGAL CERTAINTY IN EC LAW by JUHA RAITIO SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. A C.I.P Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-90-481-6264-2 ISBN 978-94-017-0353-6 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-0353-6 Printed on acid1ree paper All Rights Reserved © 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 2003 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover Ist edition 2003 No part of this publication may be reproduced Of utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, inc1uding photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements xiii Abbreviations xvii Tables xxi PART 1. EC, HISTORY, INTEGRATION, EC LAW, LEGAL CERTAINTY Ch. 1 Introductory Remarks 3 1.1 How Can the Principle of Legal Certainty be Studied in the Context of EC Law? 3 1.1.1 What is 'EC Law'? 5 1.1.2 Approaching the 'EC Law' from Different Angles 8 1.2 Ways of Approaching 'The Principle of Legal Certainty'? 10 1.3 Objections and Refutations 11 Ch.2 Some Remarks about the History of the European Community 15 2.1 The Genesis of the European Communities: the ECSC, EEC and Euratom Treaties 15 2.2 European Integration and the Intergovernmental Tendencies in the 1960s and 1970s 22 2.3 The Idea of an Internal Market and the Single European Act 33 2.4 Towards the Era After the Cold War and the Treaty on European Union 39 2.5 The Treaty of Amsterdam and Beyond 50 Ch. 3 Conclusions: Remarks about Theories of Integration, European Community and EC Law 59 3.1 Theories of European Integration: Nugent's Summary 59 3.2 European Community: Siedentop's View on European Democracy and the European Community 62 3.2.1 Why Constitutions and the Conception of the State are Important? 63 v TABLE OF CONTENTS 3.2.2 The Three Models of State. 64 3.2.3 Creating an Open Political Class and a Rights-based Political Culture in Europe - Mission Impossible ? 66 3.3 EC Law: The Jack-in-the-Box Theory of EC Law by Wilhelms son and Features of the Finnish Discussion 73 PART 2. EC LAW, PRINCIPLES OF EC LAW, GENERAL PRINCIPLES, LEGAL CERTAINTY Ch.4 The Sources, Objectives and Principles of EC Law 83 4.1 The Sources and Objectives of EC Law 83 4.1.1 The Relevant Sources of EC Law; Primary Law,Secondary Legislation and Case Law of the European Courts 83 4.1.2 The Objectives of the European Community 90 4.2 The Three Categories of the Principles Applied by the European Courts 94 4.2.1 Principles Derived from the EC Treaty 95 4.2.1.1 Principles of Loyalty, Proportionality,Non- discrimination and Equality 96 4.2.1.2 Principles of Legality, Subsidiarity and Flexibility 98 4.2.2 General Principles of EC law 101 4.2.3 Principles Based on the Case Law of the European Court of Justice 105 4.2.3.1 The Supremacy of EC Law 106 4.2.3.2 The Direct Effect and the Direct Applicability of EC Law 108 4.2.3.3 The Indirect Effect of EC Law and the State Liability 111 4.3 Problems in the Categorization of Principles and the Literal Approach 116 Ch.5 Legal Certainty in the Framework of Other General Principles ofEC Law 125 5.1 The Term 'Legal Certainty' in EC Law and the Intertwining of General Principles - A Literal Point of View 125 5.2 The Term 'Rule of Law', Legality and the Requirements of Democracy 130 5.2.1 The Terms 'Rule of Law' and 'Legal Certainty' in the Case Law of the ECJ and CFI 130 5.2.2 An Attempt to Interpret the Rule of Law 134 vi TABLE OF CONTENTS 5.3 The Principle of Revocability of Illegal Measures, the Term 'Deni de Justice' 146 5.4 The Good administration, Right to a Fair Hearing, Misuse of Powers, Proportionality and Openness. 148 5.5 The Concepts of Non Bis In Idem, Lis Pendens and Nulla Poena Sine Lege 156 5.6 'Access to Justice', the Right to an Effective Judicial Remedy and Legal Professional Privilege 160 5.7 Examples of the Material General Principles of EC Law 165 5.8 Fundamental Rights, Human Rights, Equality and the General Principles of EC Law 170 5.8.1 An Introduction to the History of the Case Law Concerning the Fundamental Rights and Human Rights in EC Law 170 5.8.2 Discrimination in the Context of Sexual Minorities as an Example of Equality, Non-discrimination and Human Rights in EC Law 176 Ch.6 The Principle of Legal Certainty Based on the Case Law of the European Court of Justice and the Court of First Instance 187 6.1 The Principle of Non-Retroactivity 187 6.1.1 The Concept of Retroactivity and the Immediate Application of EC Law 187 6.1.2 The Retroactivity of EC Legislation 190 6.1.3 The Retroactivity of ECl's Judgments, Especially the Preliminary Rulings under Article 234 EC 196 6.2 The Principle of Protection of Legitimate Expectations 200 6.2.1 The Conceptual Differences in Civil Law and Common Law Countries: The British and German Administrative Law as an Example. 200 6.2.1.1 The Estoppel Doctrine and Legitimate Expectations in English Administrative Law 200 6.2.1.2 The Estoppel Doctrine and Legitimate Expectations in EC Law: the Stork Amsterdam Case 204 6.2.1.3 Annulment of an Administrative Act in Germany and 'Vertrauenschutz' 214 6.2.2 Annulment of an Administrative Act and the Protection of Legitimate Expectations in EC law: a Case Study 217 6.2.2.1 Maenpaa's and Waelbroeck's Criteria Regarding the Protection of Legitimate Expectations 218 VB TABLE OF CONTENTS 6.2.2.2 Pinpointing the Set of Questions for the Protection of Legitimate Expectations under EC Law and the Actions of Annulment 220 6.2.2.3 The Revocation of Lawful Administrative Acts Conferring Benefits 227 6.2.2.4 The Withdrawal of Unlawful Administrative Acts Conferring Benefits 230 6.2.2.5 Special Characteristics of the Annulment of Administrative Measures Imposing Burdens 237 6.2.2.6 The Locus Standi of Article 230 EC, the Protection of Legitimate Expectations and Legal Certainty 240 6.2.3 Protection of Acquired Rights and Legitimate Expectations 252 6.3 Periods of Limitation and Legal Certainty 256 6.3.1 Prescribed Procedural Time-Limits and Indefinitely Delayed Actions Especially in the Framework of Articles 230, 232 and 234 Ee. 256 6.3.2 Sanctions Based on EC Law, Recovery of Charges and the Periods of Limitation 260 PART 3. NORMS, INTERPRETATION, LEGAL CERTAINTY Ch.7 Beyond Literalism - Conceptions and Theoretical Remarks about Norms, Validity, Interpretation, Judicial Activism and Legal Certainty 267 7.1 Theories of Norms - Ronald Dworkin's Theory of Law as a Starting-point 267 7.1.1 The Background to Dworkin's Essay 'The Model of Rules 1': a Challenge to Positivism and Utilitarianism 268 7.1.1.1 Hans Kelsen, the 'Grundnorm' and 'Stufenbau' 269 7.1.1.2 H.L.A. Hart and the 'Rule of Recognition' 272 7.1.2 Some Features of Dworkin's Theory of Law 275 7.1.2.1 Standards 275 7.1.2.2 Concept of Rights, the One Right Answer Thesis and Judicial Activism 281 7.1.3 Criticism against Dworkin's Theory of Law and Further Developments 285 7.1.3.1 The Difference between Rules and Principles 285 7.1.3.2 The One Right Answer Thesis and Values 288 7.1.3.3 The Difference between Principles and Policies 290 7.1.4 Siltala's Contribution: Summers' Levels of Legal Formality Combined with Dworkin's Theory of Law 294 viii TABLE OF CONTENTS 7.1.5 Norms, Interpretation and Justification in the Context of EC Law 298 7.1.5.1 The Emphasis on 'Proto-Norms' 298 7.1.5.2 Concepts and Conceptions 300 7.1.5.3 The Levels of Justification 301 7.2 The Judicial Argumentation and Interpretative Arguments 304 7.2.1 The Rational Reconstruction of Argumentation by the Bielefeld Circle 304 7.2.2 Basic Types of Legal Arguments 307 7.2.3 Patterns of Justification and the Logic of the Judicial Decisions as a Whole 311 7.2.4 The Interaction of Interpretative Arguments and Underlying Values 316 7.2.5 Justificatory Style of the Judicial Decisions 318 7.2.6 Justification in the Preliminary Rulings of the ECJ: Structure, Style and the Basic Arguments of the Decision 321 7.2.6.1 General Remarks about the Structure and Style of the Preliminary Rulings 321 7.2.6.2 Linguistic Arguments and the Problem of Translations in EC Law 324 7.2.6.3 Systemic, Teleological and Transcategorical Arguments in the ECJ 331 7.3 Legal Certainty 337 7.3.1 Concept of Legal Certainty - A Nordic Perspective 337 7.3.2 Expectation of Legal Certainty 340 Ch.S Predictability and Acceptability
Recommended publications
  • The European Court of Justice and the Scope of Workers' Freedom of Movement in the European Economic Community
    American University International Law Review Volume 6 | Issue 2 Article 2 1991 The urE opean Court of Justice and the Scope of Workers' Freedom of Movement in the European Economic Community David Stoelting Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.wcl.american.edu/auilr Part of the International Law Commons Recommended Citation Stoelting, David. "The urE opean Court of Justice and the Scope of Workers' Freedom of Movement in the European Economic Community." American University International Law Review 6, no. 2 (1991): 179-201. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Washington College of Law Journals & Law Reviews at Digital Commons @ American University Washington College of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in American University International Law Review by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ American University Washington College of Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE EUROPEAN COURT OF JUSTICE AND THE SCOPE OF WORKERS' FREEDOM OF MOVEMENT IN THE EUROPEAN ECONOMIC COMMUNITY David Stoelting* INTRODUCTION Since the adoption of the Treaty of Rome1 in 1957, the European Court of Justice has played an essential role in the drive toward Euro- pean unity. The European Court of Justice is the most successful of the European Economic Community's (EEC) institutions2 in implementing the Treaty's goal of economic integration.3 As the countries of the EEC4 work towards political and monetary union," the primary in- * Law Clerk for Judge Nathaniel R. Jones of the United States Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit. 1. Treaty Establishing the European Economic Community, Mar.
    [Show full text]
  • Summary of Academical Accomplishments 1. Christoph-Eric
    Summary of academical accomplishments 1. Christoph-Eric Mecke 2. Diploma of general studies of French law (“Diplôme d'Études Juridiques Générales Françaises”) at the Faculty of Law and Economics of the University of Tours (France) obtained in 1986 after completing studies in France during one year. Diploma after legal studies at the Faculty of Law at the Georg August University in Göttingen obtained in 1991 (first state law examination). Diploma after a two-year law application in courts, public administration, public prosecutor's office and private law offices, conferral of the title of an assessor of law (entitles in Germany to practice as judge, prosecutor and attorney) granted by the High Court of Lower Saxony in Celle in 2007 (second state law examination). Degree of a Doctor of Legal Science awarded by the Council of the Faculty of Law at the Georg August University in Göttingen on July 17, 2007 on the basis of a comprehensive law examination (“Rigorosum”) and the presented monographic dissertation entitled Begriff und System des Rechts bei Georg Friedrich Puchta [= Concept and legal system in the legal thought of Georg Friedrich Puchta] marked with the highest possible final grade “summa cum laude”. 3. Information on employment in academic positions: 1991-1993 - junior researcher at the Department of Legal Theory at the Faculty of Law at the Georg August University in Göttingen; from February 1, 2008 to March 31, 2016 – researcher at the Department of Civil Law and History of Law and lecturer at the Faculty of Law at the Leibniz University in Hanover, there I’m still an academic teacher in the field of legal history from April 15, 2016 to December 31, 2017 – researcher at the Department of Roman Law and Pandetics at the Faculty of Law of the Georg August University in Göttingen; from January 1, 2018 until today – researcher and lecturer at the Brunswick European Law School at the Ostfalia University of Applied Sciences in Brunswick (Braunschweig).
    [Show full text]
  • Against Certainty
    Florida State University College of Law Scholarship Repository Scholarly Publications Fall 2012 Against Certainty Shawn J. Bayern Florida State University College of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.law.fsu.edu/articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Shawn J. Bayern, Against Certainty, 41 HOFSTRA L. REV. 53 (2012), Available at: https://ir.law.fsu.edu/articles/43 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Scholarly Publications by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. AGAINST CERTAINTY Shawn J. Bayern* I. INTRODUCTION In legal argumentation, appeals to certainty and predictability have enormous rhetorical power. This Article argues that their use outstrips their legitimate role in legal analysis. The Article is not literally ―against certainty‖ in the sense that it promotes uncertainty as a good thing in itself;1 it is just a skeptical consideration of the role of appeals to certainty in legal theory. The Article‘s principal contention is that arguments about certainty are often mistaken, that certainty itself is often misunderstood, and that many defenses of certainty in legal rules are tautological, irrelevant, or substantively overstated.2 There are many reasons that certainty has at least a superficial appeal in legal reasoning. For one thing, it may comport with analytical philosophers‘ desires for conceptual clarity; a pragmatic or pluralist mode of analysis may appear unprincipled, intellectually incoherent, or simply unhelpful to those who promote formal argumentation.3 For * Assistant Professor, Florida State University College of Law.
    [Show full text]
  • The Law of the European Union
    levasseur EU2e p1 00 fmt 7/9/13 8:58 AM Page iii The Law of the European Union second edition Alain A. Levasseur Hermann Moyse Senior Professor of Law, Director, European Studies Louisiana State University Paul M. Hebert Law Center Richard F. Scott Distinguished Professor of International Law, Thomas Jefferson School of Law Arnaud Raynouard Professor, Université Paris-Dauphine Christine A. Corcos Associate Professor of Law and an Associate Professor of Women’s and Gender Studies, Louisiana State University Law Center Joël Monéger Professor of Law, Université Paris-Dauphine Jean-Claude Piris Former Legal Counsel, Director General, European Union Legal Service Carolina Academic Press Durham, North Carolina levasseur EU2e p1 00 fmt 7/9/13 8:58 AM Page iv Copyright © 2013 Carolina Academic Press All Rights Reserved ISBN 978-1-59460-899-5 LCCN 2012950550 Carolina Academic Press 700 Kent Street Durham, North Carolina 27701 Telephone (919) 489-7486 Fax (919) 493-5668 www.cap-press.com Printed in the United States of America levasseur EU2e p1 00 fmt 7/9/13 8:58 AM Page v Dedications To my beloved petits-enfants: Francis, Gabriel, John Paul, Bridget, Peter Daniel, Libby Kate, Mary Benton, and Helen Quinn – Alain Levasseur For my wife Lorraine, our children Karen, Jeffrey and Holly, and our grandchildren Chelsea, Michael and Paul, with love and admiration – Richard Scott For Cullen and Avery – Christine Corcos levasseur EU2e p1 00 fmt 7/9/13 8:58 AM Page vii Summary of Contents Foreword lxvii Acknowledgements lxx Table of Cases lxv Table of European
    [Show full text]
  • Robert P Merges What Kind of Rights Are Intellectual Property Rights?
    Robert P Merges What Kind of Rights Are Intellectual Property Rights? Forthcoming in Rochelle C Dreyfuss & Justine Pila (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Intellectual Property Law © RP Merges 2017 Table of Contents 1. Intellectual Property as a Right 1.1 Intellectual Property Rights Are Property Rights 1.2 The Basic Features of Intellectual Property as Property 1.2.1 The Right to Control Uses 1.2.2 The Right to Transfer 1.2.3 The Special Case of Waiver 1.3 Limitations on Intellectual Property Rights 2. What Kind of Rights? Hohfeld and Intellectual Property 2.1 Claim Right/Duty 2.2 Privilege/No Claim 2.3 Power/Liability 2.4 Immunity/Disability 2.5 Hohfeld: Conclusion 3. Obstacles to Conceiving Intellectual Property as Property 3.1 Intellectual Property Acquisition and Misunderstandings About What it Means to be a Right 3.2 What, No Automatic Injunction? That’s Not Property! 3.3 Why Intellectual Property Rights Are Not ‘Regulation’ 3.3.2 The Second Sense of ‘Regulation’ 3.3.3 Freedom and Permission 3.3.4 Freedoms in Historical Perspective 3.4 Intellectual Property Rights as Property Rights: Summing Up 4. Problems With Conceiving Intellectual Property as Property 4.1 Group Ownership 4.2 Intellectual Property As Constitutional Property: The Takings Problem 5. Conclusion 1. Intellectual Property Rights as Rights Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2959073 The phrase is common enough that it rolls off the tongue: intellectual property rights. It even has a well-known acronym, ‘IPRs.’1 But are they really rights? And if so, what kind of rights? Most importantly, what difference does it make that they are rights – what practical import does this carry? These are the questions I take up here.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Law Revisited
    Michigan Law Review Volume 94 Issue 6 1996 The Concept of Law Revisited Leslie Green Osgoode Hall Law School, York University Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr Part of the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation Leslie Green, The Concept of Law Revisited, 94 MICH. L. REV. 1687 (1996). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol94/iss6/15 This Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Law Review at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. IBE CONCEPT OF LAW REVISITED Leslie Green* THE CONCEPT OF LAW. Second Edition. By H.L.A. Hart. With a Postscript edited by Penelope A. Bulloch and Joseph Raz. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 1994. Pp. xii, 315. $26. Law is a social construction. It is a historically contingent fea­ ture of certain societies, one whose emergence is signaled by the rise of a systematic form of social control and elite domination. In one way it supersedes custom, in another it rests on it, for law is a system of primary social rules that direct and appraise behavior, together with secondary social rules that identify, change, and en­ force the primary rules. Law may be beneficial, but only in some contexts and always at a price, at the risk of grave injustice; our appropriate attitude to it is therefore one of caution rather than celebration.
    [Show full text]
  • Perju Ages of European
    Draft for NYU Colloquium (October 2015). Do not cite or circulate without permission. THE AGES OF EUROPEAN LAW Vlad Perju∗ Prologue: Habermas on the Transnationalization of Democracy European integration poses fundamental challenges to political and legal thought. Over the past two decades, Jürgen Habermas has been engaged in a bold and influential project of articulating the normative foundations of political integration in Europe. Habermas’s starting point is that the pacification of European states created the preconditions for political decision-making beyond the national level. Once state power was tamed, and states accordingly “civilized”, national governments could pursue common policies in response to the pressures of economic globalization. The problem, however, is that the preconditions for political life at the supranational level have not been properly realized. Habermas sees a growing disconnect between the demands of integrated markets, which form one part of the larger, systemic integration of world society, and lingering political fragmentation in Europe. Perhaps the diagnosis of political fragmentation seems surprising given that the member states of the European Union have over the decades consented to ever-greater transfers of powers to the supranational political institutions. But the reality is more complex. The political crises of the past ∗ Associate Professor, Boston College Law School and Director, Clough Center for the Study of Constitutional Democracy. 1 decade, and most notably the recent “crucifixion”1 of Greece in the recent debt negotiations, reveals a state of affairs where the European Council – that “complete anomaly”, as Habermas calls it2 – remains central to the EU’s political life. This development is both unfortunate and unnecessary.
    [Show full text]
  • On Neil Maccormick's ‘Universalisable Particular Thesis’ Jingjing Wu
    Document generated on 09/25/2021 10:28 p.m. Informal Logic Justifying Particular Reasoning in a Legal Context On Neil MacCormick's ‘Universalisable Particular Thesis’ Jingjing Wu Volume 40, Number 3, 2020 Article abstract Particular reasoning is arguably the most common type of legal reasoning. Neil URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1071501ar MacCormick proposed that, in a legal context, justifiable particular reasoning DOI: https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v40i30.5994 has to be universalizable. This paper aims to: (1) investigate MacCormick’s thesis; (2) explain how a particular can ever be universal by drawing See table of contents inspiration from Scott Brewer’s formula on reasoning by analogy; (3) further comprehend MacCormick’s thesis by considering some of the arguments advanced by its opponents; (4) use the ‘pilot-judgement procedure’ developed Publisher(s) by the European Court of Human Rights as an example to illustrate the relevance of the universalizable particular thesis in today’s legal practices. Informal Logic ISSN 0824-2577 (print) 2293-734X (digital) Explore this journal Cite this article Wu, J. (2020). Justifying Particular Reasoning in a Legal Context: On Neil MacCormick's ‘Universalisable Particular Thesis’. Informal Logic, 40(3), 423–441. https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v40i30.5994 Copyright (c), 2020 Jingjing Wu This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit. Érudit is a non-profit inter-university consortium of the Université de Montréal, Université Laval, and the Université du Québec à Montréal.
    [Show full text]
  • Certainty and Uncertainty in Tax Law: Do Opposites Attract?
    laws Article Certainty and Uncertainty in Tax Law: Do Opposites Attract? Alexander V. Demin Law Institute, Siberian Federal University, 660075 Krasnoyarsk, Russia; [email protected] Received: 14 October 2020; Accepted: 26 November 2020; Published: 4 December 2020 Abstract: The principle of certainty of taxation is the dimension of a general requirement of certainty in the legal system. The purpose of this article is to argue the thesis that uncertainty in tax law is not always an absolute evil, sometimes it acts as a means of the most optimal (and in some cases the only possible) settlement of relations in the field of taxes. On the contrary, uncertainty and fragmentation in tax law are colossal problems subject to overcome by the efforts of scientists, legislators, judges, and practicing lawyers. Uncertainty in tax law is manifested in two ways: on the one hand, negatively—as a defect (omission) of the legislator and, on the other hand, positively—as a set of specific legal means and technologies that are purposefully used in lawmaking and law enforcement. In this context, relatively determined legal tools are an effective channel for transition from uncertainty to certainty in the field of taxation. A tendency towards increased use of relatively determined legal tools in lawmaking processes (for example, principles, evaluative concepts, judicial doctrines, standards of good faith and reasonableness, discretion, open-ended lists, recommendations, framework laws, silence of the law, presumptive taxation, analogy, etc.), and involving various actors (courts, law enforcement agencies and officials, international organizations, citizens, organizations and their associations) allow making tax laws more dynamic flexible, and adequate to changing realities of everyday life.
    [Show full text]
  • Constitutional Law Connotations of Legal Certainty in the Rule of Law
    CONSTITUTIONAL LAW CONNOTATIONS OF LEGAL CERTAINTY IN THE RULE OF LAW Emilian CIONGARU Abstract The Rule of law must accomplish the rule of law, both in its relations with citizens and in relations with the governing bodies. An main foundation of the Rule of law consists of the principle of legal security which implies that individuals, as beneficiaries of the law, to be able, without putting too much effort, to decide what is allowed and what is prohibited by the applicable law. To achieve this outcome, the legal norms adopted must be clear and understandable and not be subject over the time to so frequent and especially, unpredictable changes. The principle of legal security is also known as the principle of legal certainty because it consists of the uncertainty that the enforcement of legal norms in a given situation to be predictable, the incident legal norm to be easily to establish, its recipients to be certain a legal provision corresponding offense is applied, and not another one, and that it will be interpreted in a uniform manner and a legal norm which did not come to the notice of recipients can not be applied Key words: rule of law, legal security, legal certainty, constitutional order, political organization of society. JEL Classification: [K10] Throughout the historical evolution, the political organization of society, particularly through its main institution, the State, was realized more and more on perfecting the State structure in relation to natural or legal persons of the State and the rigorous legal norms, which set both their rights and freedoms, but also duties of the State bodies to act within the legal norms intendment.
    [Show full text]
  • Judicial Supremacy and the Modest Constitution
    Judicial Supremacy and the Modest Constitution Frederick Schauert INTRODUCTION Judicial supremacy is under attack. From various points on the politi- cal spectrum, political actors as well as academics have challenged the idea that the courts in general, and the Supreme Court in particular, have a spe- cial and preeminent responsibility in interpreting and enforcing the Constitution. Reminding us that treating Supreme Court interpretations of the Constitution as supreme and authoritative has no grounding in constitu- tional text and not much more in constitutional history, these critics seek to relocate the prime source of interpretive guidance. The courts have an important role to play, these critics acknowledge, but it is a role neither greater than that played by other branches, nor greater than the role to be played by "the people themselves."' The critics' understanding of a more limited function for the judiciary in constitutional interpretation appears to rest, however, primarily on a highly contestable conception of the point of having a written constitution in the first place. According to this conception, a constitution, and espe- cially the Constitution of the United States, is the vehicle by which a de- mocratic polity develops its own fundamental values. A constitution, therefore, becomes both a statement of our most important values and the vehicle through which these values are created and crystallized. Under this conception of the role of a written constitution, it would indeed be a mis- take to believe that the courts should have the preeminent responsibility for interpreting that constitution. For this task of value generation to devolve Copyright © 2004 California Law Review, Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • Alexy's Theory Of
    Over the years Robert Alexy has devel- the other dimensions of his system are pre- oped a systemic approach to legal theory, sented here, along with a contribution on Alexy’s Theory of Law an approach whose dimensions include human rights, one of Alexy’s more recent discourse theory, principles theory, and a foci. Alexy’s work is receiving ever greater Proceedings of the Special Workshop “Alexy’s Theory of Law” non-positivist conception of law. Principles attention, both at home, in Germany, and th theoryisfoundattheverycoreofAlexy’s abroad, with translations of his treatises held at the 26 World Congress of the International Association for system. Constitutional rights, he argues, and papers into many languages. The au- Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy in Belo Horizonte, 2013 are best understood as principles, and thors of the contributions aim to promote collisions between constitutional rights enquiry into Alexy’s project. While their – understood now as competing princi- general approach is that of analytical ju- ples – are resolved by balancing their re- risprudence, the individual contributions Edited by Júlio Aguiar de Oliveira / Stanley L. Paulson / spective weights. Critical examinations of reflect great variety in their respective as- Alexandre Travessoni Gomes Trivisonno Alexy’s work on principles theory and on sessments of Alexy’s seminal work. s Theory ofLaw ’ Alexy www.steiner-verlag.de ARSP ARSP Beiheft 144 Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie Franz Steiner Verlag Franz Steiner Verlag ISBN 978-3-515-11043-3 de Oliveira / Paulson / Trivisonno 9 7 8 3 5 1 5 1 1 0 4 3 3 Alexy’s Theory of Law Edited by Júlio Aguiar de Oliveira / Stanley L.
    [Show full text]