Twelfth Century

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Twelfth Century TWELFTH CENTURY By the twelfth century, western European philosophy had enveloped Christianity risen from its first century beginnings and was now dominated by Roman Catholicism. Love of wisdom had come to mean love of God. Nevertheless, there was also a tum in the twelfth century back toward classical writings. The letters of Heloise and Abelard quoted the classical writings of Cicero, Seneca, and Ovid as well as Christian Scripture, Gregory, and Ambrose. The Greek works of Aristotle known mainly in Latin translation, were, however, mostly unavailable. Letter writing itself was growing in importance as a source of discourse. While the University of Paris was in its gestation, Bologna in Italy had already gained a reputation for its study of law and medicine. A leading thinker Abelard developed new methods of reasoning that would eventually be referred to as the Scholastic method, whereas Heloise emphasized human power, an stress that would became a mark of the Renaissance. Until the universities were fully instituted, convent schools for women expanded in twelfth century France alongside men's schools. Still, Heloise, who was educated in a convent school, proved to be like Pan Chao in first century China a singular intellect. Heloise's references display her familiarity with an impressive history of philosophy to include Aspasia and Origen, the Neo­ Platonists and Augustine of Hippo (354-430). 1 Augustine, a classical scholar, in systematizing Christian doctrine, had initiated the rise of medieval philosophy that conceived of knowledge as being subordinate to the ends of Christianity and viewed women as being subordinate to men. 2 If women were thought to be inferior to men, women in image were often portrayed as being superior. Prior to the twelfth century a tradition had developed of the image of woman depicting wisdom as in the Old Testament, Book of Siraach. The Greek and Roman Athena and Minerva-Goddesses of Wisdom­ were later transformed by Boethius (480-525) into Lady Philosophy. By empowering her with the role of healing teacher in the Consolations, Boethius 1 While Aspasia was one of the earliest known non-Christian philosophers dating from Periclean Greece, women scholars in the church date at least from 4th century CE Rome when Marcella offered instruction to women in Origen 's On First Principles. and Melania and Paula, Scripuralists, journeyed to Jerusalem and founded monasteries. (Monique Alexandre 1992 Early Christian women, A history of women in the west. P.S. Pantel, ed., Cambridge: Harvard UP): 409-44. 2 Mary T. Clark, RSCJ reminds us that despite Augustine's negative attitude toward women, he believed women to be "co-heirs of grace" and images of God in both mind and sense. 126 (1994, Augustine, London: Geoffrey Chapman.) 32 Twelfth Century personified philosophy as a woman. Boethius, a Roman senator and scholar, provided Medieval philosophy with translations of Greek Classics, such as Porphyry's introduction to Aristotle. Boethius' Lady Philosophy's mantle is referred to ironically by (H) Roswitha of Gandersheim (935-1 00 l) in her play "Sapientia" in which she replaced women as image with representative women philosophers: given ... a perspicacious mind, but one that lies fallow and idle when it is not cultivated ... I have been at pains, whenever I have been able to pick up some threads and scraps torn from the old mantle of philosophy, to weave them into the stuff of my own book ...that the creator of genius may be honoured since it is generally believed that a woman's intelligence is lower. 3 Boethius' portrayal of philosophy as a caring and dramatically alive instructor countered a history of many negative concepts adopted from the ancients forward. The following examples illustrate some of these negative perceptions. Pythagoras's principle that evil created chaos, darkness and woman and Aristotle's male principle that conceived woman as defective or not fully developed males were complimentary. These concepts superseded Plato's more positive perception of woman in the Republic and the Timeas. The interpretation of Eve being the transgressor was often at the root of Christian notions about women. Augustine rendered St. Paul's view of women as the "devil's gateway" to mean that sin originated through women. Other perceptions that persisted in philosophical arguments rested on women's being less rational and in that sense less spiritual. That woman's nature resides in her body rather than in her mind was emphasized in On the Divisions of Nature by John Scotus Erigena (81 0-877) and John of Salisbury's (d.ll80) theories. When St. Anselm of Canterbury (1033- 1109) argued that St. Paul and Jesus "are mothers ... giving birth to the soul," he figuratively gave women's "bodies" to men. 4 Hence, this brief outline demonstrates that the history of the perceptions of women by philosophers prior to the twelfth century often committed women to representative image, their minds to matter rather than to spirit, and their minds and bodies to an inferior position to their male counterparts. Medieval philosophy debated various perceptions of women. In the philosophical climate in which Heloise lived. Bernard of Chartres's "Natura," 3 Prudence Allen, 257 (1985, The concept ofwom en, Montreal: Eden). 4 Joan Gibson, 88 (1989 Herrad ofHohenbourg Waithe, M. E., ed. A history ofwom en philosophers. v. 2/500-1600, Dordrecht, Netherlands, Kluwer): 85-98. Twelfth Century 33 personifies woman as philosophy notably differently. 5 According to Peter Dronke, she is one of a triad of goddesses, "a cosmic power" with a "philosophical name" who offers "spiritual nourishment." Some years after Heloise's death, Abbess Herrad ofLandesberg's Hortus Delciarum (1185) presented a personified "human wisdom" to inform and nourish all knowledge through the seven liberal arts, but in profiling a portion of the century's philosophical canon with Augustine, Anselm, Boethius, and Peter Lombard, Herrad includes a woman, Hildegard of Bingen. Hence, the elevated image of woman as philosophy, knowledge, creatrix or virgin mother of God was countered by the concepts of woman in the natural order as inferior, woman guilty merely by being woman. These contrasting views of woman with occasional exceptions were celebrated in the Middle Ages in both hymns to immaculate Mary and in troubadour's songs celebrating illicit sexual and romantic encounters.6 While some women in the twelfth century in France had access to convent education few philosophical writings by women were preserved, and those that were, were apt not to be acknowledged.7 Following the entertaining Prologue to her poetry advising people to study and heed the models and axioms for moral guidance: "which philosophers did find/ And wrote about and kept in mind ... ," Marie de France made note of this problem in the Epilogue: "And it may hap that many a clerk/Will claim as his what is my work. "8 At times singular scholars envisioned afresh, traditional issues in medieval philosophy. One example was the mysticism as a method for acquiring new knowledge. This spiritual discipline aimed at attaining union with God through contemplation, and it particularly allowed women a voice in matters of the mind. Hildegard of Bingen ( 1098-1179), a contemporary of Heloise ( 1100-1164) of France, was one of the greatest of the medieval mystics. Her works, often the descriptions and interpretations of visions, are of considerably greater number than are the writings of Heloise.9 Hildegard, a Benedictine abbess, honored with the ' Peter Dronke, 41-47 (1992, Intellectuals and poets in medieval Europe. Rome: Edizioni di Storia E. Letteratura. Chartres, the seat of Platonism, was also the center for study of the natural world. ' Countess Dia, a woman troubadour sang such words as, "I should like to hold my knight/Naked in my anns at eve," 96 (194, R.T. Hill and T. G. Berg, eds., Anthology of provencal troubadours. New Haven: Yale UP). Hildegard's liturgical choral compositions are currently available on tape. 7 Fourth century Makrina's On the Soul and Resurrection, which for some time was attributed to her brother Gregory of Nyssa, is an example. Makrina occupied herself with "philosophy;" her concept of soul rejected the loss of the soul's rational character at the death of the body. Cornelia Wolfskeel. Makrina, 163 (1987, A history of women philosophers. v.l600/500, M.E. Waithe, ed., Dordrecht, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff): 139-68. 8 Harriet Spiegel, 29 (1987. Marie de France: Fables. University of Toronto Press). 9 Beer, 2-3 Heloi"se wrote only "a sixth of what remains of Hrotswitha's work" and "little more than a hundredth of Hildegard's" 109 (1984. Peter Dronke, Women writers of the middle ages.London: 34 Twelfth Century epithet "Sibyl of the Rhine," practiced medical science and healing, taught the secular seven liberal arts to her "daughters," wrote on cosmology, theology, science, and ethics, composed music, produced art, and late in life lectured abroad. While her works were preserved, translation was not begun for seven hundred years. Poignantly, the advice Hildegard sought in a letter to the mystic Bernard of Clairvaux on whether to publish or keep silent about her first book Scivias, her labor of ten years, would continue to be sought by others more than seven centuries later. Hildegard began the letter in the humility "topos" or stance, "wretched in my existence as a wornan." 10 This "humility stance," was a rhetorical opening, used by writers as early as the first century C. E. by Pan Chao to as late as Petrarch, but used regularly as a commonplace denoting inferior status by women writers until the nineteenth century. While both Hildegard and Heloise gave voice to divergent philosophy, they both demonstrated a familiarity with philosophy of the medieval canon, and they both wrote with great command of language.
Recommended publications
  • Medieval Western Philosophy: the European Emergence
    Cultural Heritage and Contemporary Change Series I, Culture and Values, Volume 9 History of Western Philosophy by George F. McLean and Patrick J. Aspell Medieval Western Philosophy: The European Emergence By Patrick J. Aspell The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy 1 Copyright © 1999 by The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy Gibbons Hall B-20 620 Michigan Avenue, NE Washington, D.C. 20064 All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Aspell, Patrick, J. Medieval western philosophy: the European emergence / Patrick J. Aspell. p.cm. — (Cultural heritage and contemporary change. Series I. Culture and values ; vol. 9) Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Philosophy, Medieval. I. Title. III. Series. B721.A87 1997 97-20069 320.9171’7’090495—dc21 CIP ISBN 1-56518-094-1 (pbk.) 2 Table of Contents Chronology of Events and Persons Significant in and beyond the History of Medieval Europe Preface xiii Part One: The Origins of Medieval Philosophy 1 Chapter I. Augustine: The Lover of Truth 5 Chapter II. Universals According to Boethius, Peter Abelard, and Other Dialecticians 57 Chapter III. Christian Neoplatoists: John Scotus Erigena and Anselm of Canterbury 73 Part Two: The Maturity of Medieval Philosophy Chronology 97 Chapter IV. Bonaventure: Philosopher of the Exemplar 101 Chapter V. Thomas Aquinas: Philosopher of the Existential Act 155 Part Three: Critical Reflection And Reconstruction 237 Chapter VI. John Duns Scotus: Metaphysician of Essence 243 Chapter
    [Show full text]
  • St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death
    The University of Akron IdeaExchange@UAkron Williams Honors College, Honors Research The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors Projects College Spring 2020 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death Christopher Choma [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects Part of the Christianity Commons, Epistemology Commons, European History Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, Metaphysics Commons, Philosophy of Mind Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Please take a moment to share how this work helps you through this survey. Your feedback will be important as we plan further development of our repository. Recommended Citation Choma, Christopher, "St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death" (2020). Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects. 1048. https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects/1048 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors College at IdeaExchange@UAkron, the institutional repository of The University of Akron in Akron, Ohio, USA. It has been accepted for inclusion in Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects by an authorized administrator of IdeaExchange@UAkron. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. 1 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death By: Christopher Choma Sponsored by: Dr. Joseph Li Vecchi Readers: Dr. Howard Ducharme Dr. Nathan Blackerby 2 Table of Contents Introduction p. 4 Section One: Three General Views of Human Nature p.
    [Show full text]
  • The Catholic Intellectual Tradition Scholarship, Faith, and Higher Education
    ISSN 1941-8450 Journal of Religion & Society Supplement Series The Kripke Center Supplement 6 (2011) The Catholic Intellectual Tradition Scholarship, Faith, and Higher Education Edited by John J. O’Keefe, Gina Merys, and Bridget Keegan The Catholic Intellectual Tradition Medieval Lessons Frederick Christian Bauerschmidt, Loyola University Maryland Introduction [1] Whatever else a tradition is, it is something that connects us to a past, and not simply to a past fondly remembered, but one that continues to inform our present. So it seems not implausible that we might look to the past in order to gain insight into what it means to be engaged in the Catholic Intellectual Tradition today. And because Catholicism seems, for good or for ill, to have a particular connection to the Middle Ages – the “Age of Faith” – we might look to that particular past to see what lessons we can learn about what we mean when we speak of a Catholic Intellectual Tradition, about what challenges are posed to and posed by this tradition, and about how we foster and further this tradition. I will proceed by first making and exploring a distinction, and then proposing some points for consideration. 10 The Catholic Intellectual Tradition [2] Medieval scholastic thought proceeded largely by the making of distinctions, and thus it would warm the heart of our scholastic forbears if we begin with a distinction. I suggest we might distinguish between what we mean materially by the Catholic Intellectual Tradition, and what we mean formally. In other words, when we speak “materially” about the Catholic Intellectual Tradition, we mean those texts, works of art, figures, concepts, and so forth that are indispensable in preservation, transmission, and extension of that tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • Jewish Averroists Between Two Expulsions (1306-1492): from Conflict to Reconciliation
    JEWISH AVERROISTS BETWEEN TWO EXPULSIONS (1306-1492): FROM CONFLICT TO RECONCILIATION Basem Mahmud Freie Universität Berlin ABSTRACT This article investigates the intellectual production of Jewish authors influenced by Averroes in the 14th and 15th Centuries in northern Spain and southern France. The primary objective is to determine the main features of Jewish Averroism in this period, and to understand it within its socio-historical context. The outcomes suggest that there was a relationship between the new social and political trends toward democratization and reconciliation in the heart of Jewish communities on one hand, and the growing interest in Averroes’ original works on the other. Original here means the works that are not commentaries or summaries of other works. Key words: Aristotelianism, Averroes, Averroism, Jewish philosophy, Kabbalah, Maimonides, Scripture. INTRODUCTION «There is nothing worse in social government than a policy that makes one single society into several, just as there is no greater good in communities than a policy that joins and unifies» (Averroes)1 The 14th Century was a very difficult time for Jewish communities in northern Spain and southern France, they faced great threats from outside as well as significant domestic division. The domestic conflict emerged not only because of religious and philosophical issues, but also due to economic and social matters related to the distribution of wealth and power within Jewish communities.2 In addition, these communities lived in delicate conditions due to threats from the Christians. This situation also had an effect on demographics. Since the last years of 13th Century, the Jewish community started to encounter sizeable obstacles in its demographic development.3 Under these conditions, Hebraic Averroism continued its development which had begun in XIII century.
    [Show full text]
  • Albert Schweitzer: a Man Between Two Cultures
    , .' UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I LIBRARY ALBERT SCHWEITZER: A MAN BETWEEN TWO CULTURES A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN LANGUAGES AND LITERATURES OF • EUROPE AND THE AMERICAS (GERMAN) MAY 2007 By Marie-Therese, Lawen Thesis Committee: Niklaus Schweizer Maryann Overstreet David Stampe We certify that we have read this thesis and that, in our opinion, it is satisfactory in scope and quality as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts in Languages and Literatures of Europe and the Americas (German). THESIS COMMITIEE --~ \ Ii \ n\.llm~~~il\I~lmll:i~~~10 004226205 ~. , L U::;~F H~' _'\ CB5 .H3 II no. 3Y 35 -- ,. Copyright 2007 by Marie-Therese Lawen 1II "..-. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS T I would like to express my deepest gratitude to a great number of people, without whose assistance, advice, and friendship this thesis w0l!'d not have been completed: Prof. Niklaus Schweizer has been an invaluable mentor and his constant support have contributed to the completion of this work; Prof. Maryann Overstreet made important suggestions about the form of the text and gave constructive criticism; Prof. David Stampe read the manuscript at different stages of its development and provided corrective feedback. 'My sincere gratitude to Prof. Jean-Paul Sorg for the the most interesting • conversations and the warmest welcome each time I visited him in Strasbourg. His advice and encouragement were highly appreciated. Further, I am deeply grateful for the help and advice of all who were of assistance along the way: Miriam Rappolt lent her editorial talents to finalize the text; Lynne Johnson made helpful suggestions about the chapter on Bach; John Holzman suggested beneficial clarifications.
    [Show full text]
  • The Agent Intellect As" Form for Us" and Averroes's. Critique of Al-Farabi
    Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía ISSN: 0188-6649 [email protected] Universidad Panamericana México Taylor, Richard C. The Agent Intellect as "form for us" and Averroes's. Critique of al-Farabi Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía, núm. 29, 2005, pp. 29-51 Universidad Panamericana Distrito Federal, México Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=323027318003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative The Agent Intellect as "form for us" and Averroes's Critique of al-FarabT Richard C. Taylor Marquette University This article explicates Averroes's understanding of human knowing and abstraction in this three commentaries on Aristotle's De Anima. While Averroes's views on the nature of the human material intellect changes through the three commentaries until he reaches is famous view of the unity of the material intellect as one for all human beings, his view of the agent intellect as 'form for us' is sustained throughout these works. In his Long Commentary on the De Anima he reveals his dependence on al-Farabi for this notion and provides a detailed critique of the Farabian notion that the agent intellect is 'form for us' only as agent cause, not as our true formal cause. Although Averroes argues that the agent intellect must somehow be intrinsic to us as our form since humans 2tieper se rational and undertake acts of knowing by will, his view is shown to rest on an equivocal use of the notion of formal cause.
    [Show full text]
  • Agrippa Von Nettesheim, Heinrich Cornelius, 61, 62, 70, 91 Albert of Saxony, 44 Alberti, Leon Battista, 51 Albertus Magnus, 44
    INDEX Agrippa von Nettesheim, Heinrich Blumenberg, Hans, 114 Cornelius, 61, 62, 70, 91 Böhme, Jakob, 113 Albert of Saxony, 44 Botero, Giovanni, 72 Alberti, Leon Battista, 51 Brahe, Tycho, 89 Albertus Magnus, 44, 45 Brucker, Johann Jakob, 111 Alciato, Andrea, 64 Bruno, Giovanni, 1 Alexander of Aphrodisias, 2 Alsted, Johann Heinrich, 79, 110 Calvin, John, 10 Alvinczi, Peter, 109 Calvinism, Calvinists, 3, 10, 11, 26, Analogy, 17, 18, 23, 38, 40, 41, 83, 57, 79, 80, 106, 107, 109, 93 117, 118 Antitrinitarianism, 3, 10, 26 Campanella, Tommaso, 94, 96 Antonino of Fiesole, 5 Carrière, Moritz, 113 Aquarius, Matthias, 4, 45 Cassirer, Ernst, 114 Aquilecchia, Giovanni, 110 Castelnau, Michel de, 25, 26, 28, 29, Aquinas, Thomas, 4, 6, 7, 13, 16, 39, 69, 72, 117, 118 41, 46, 47, 50, 56, 57, 117 Catherine de’ Medici, 11 Aratus, 52 Catherine of Siena, 5 Arian heresy, 7, 8, 117 Cavalca, Domenico, 5 Ariosto, Ludovico, 3, 85, 103 Celestino da Verona, 101 Aristotle, Aristotelianism, Center, 1, 31, 33, 43, 50, 68, 97 Aristotelian, 2, 4, 6, 10, 11, Chambéry, 9, 117 15, 16, 19, 21, 22, 25, 27–29, Chaos, 38 36–38, 39, 41, 43, 44–47, 51, Christ, 3, 5, 8, 54, 55 59, 60, 61, 63, 64, 67, 71–79, Christian I of Saxony, 80 83, 86, 88, 89, 110, 117 Church Fathers, 7 Astronomy, 9, 11, 27, 32, 34, 38, 52, Cicala, 1 70, 117 Cicero, 13, 84 Atomism, 3, 50, 69, 71, 72, 96, 99, Clemens, Franz Jacob, 112 102, 110 Clement VIII, Pope, 102, 103 Augustine, 5, 7, 35, 38, 55, 66 Colle, Giovanni Vincenzo (Sarnese), Augustinians, 2 2 Augustus I of Saxony, 80 Combinatorics, 15, 20,
    [Show full text]
  • The Aristotelian Curriculum in Arabic and Hebrew
    1 The Aristotelian Curriculum (Excluding Mathematics) In Arabic and Hebrew (occasionally also Greek, Syriac, Persian, Latin) Handout for “Aristotle in the Middle Ages,” James Robinson, U. Chicago, Winter 2013 General background: Christina d’Ascona, “Greek Sources in Arabic and Islamic Philosophy,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy Online: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-greek/ M. Zonta, “The Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on Judaic Thought,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-judaic/ Dag Hasse, “The Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-influence/ Tony Street, “Arabic and Islamic Philosophy of Language and Logic,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-language/ J. McGinnis, “Arabic and Islamic Natural Philosophy and Natural Science,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-natural/ Alfred Ivry, “Arabic and Islamic Psychology and Philosophy of Mind,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-mind/ Amos Bertolacci, “Arabic and Islamic Metaphysics,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-metaphysics/ Useful Resources: Arist. semitico-latinus: http://www.brill.com/publications/aristoteles-semitico-latinus Online dictionary of Arabic philosophical terms: http://www.arabic-philosophy.com/dict Hans Daiber
    [Show full text]
  • John of Salisbury's Entheticus Maior and Minor, Edited by Jan Van Laarhoven
    Restoring Knowledge: John of Salisbury’s “Return to the Tree” by Gordon Gray M.F.A., University of California (Los Angeles), 1969 B.A., Stanford University, 1967 Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts in the Department of Humanities Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences Gordon Gray 2013 SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY Spring 2013 Approval Name: Gordon Gray Degree: Master of Arts (Humanities) Title of Thesis: Restoring Knowledge: John of Salisbury’s “Return to the Tree” Examining Committee: Chair: Anne-Marie Feenberg-Dibon Associate Professor and Graduate Chair Paul Edward Dutton Senior Supervisor Professor Christine Jones Supervisor Senior Lecturer Emily O’Brien External Examiner Assistant Professor Department of History Date Defended/Approved: April 24, 2013 ii Partial Copyright Licence iii Abstract In 1159 CE, the English diplomat and ecclesiastic John of Salisbury published two books, the Policraticus and the Metalogicon, the former a treatise on the nature of good governance, and the latter a defence of classical education. Believing that political leadership should be based on moral precepts, John observed that moral judgment seemed to have been largely replaced in both church and state by personal ambition for wealth and power. Believing further that the knowledge required for moral judgment should be gained through proper education, John reasoned that knowledge itself had become fractured, and that it was necessary to return to that point and rebuild knowledge anew. Concluding that the fracture occurred with Adam’s expulsion from paradise for eating from the tree of knowledge, John reasoned that mankind must “return to the tree.” This thesis analyzes John’s “return to the tree” within the intellectual context of the twelfth-century renaissance.
    [Show full text]
  • DEMONSTRATION and Scientific KNOWLEDGE in WILLIAM OF
    Longeway-000.FM 11/8/06 2:29 PM Page iii Demonstration and Scientific knowledge in william of ockham ATranslation of Summa Logicae III-II: De Syllogismo Demonstrativo, and Selections from the Prologue to the Ordinatio JO HN LEE LO NGEWAY University of Notre Dame Press Notre Dame, Indiana © 2007 University of Notre Dame Press Longeway-000.FM 11/8/06 2:29 PM Page iv Copyright © 2007 by University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana 46556 www.undpress.nd.edu All Rights Reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Longeway, John. Demonstration and scientific knowledge in William of Ockham : a translation of Summa Logicae III-II : De Syllogismo Demonstrativo, and selections from the Prologue to the Ordinatio / John Lee Longeway. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn-13: 978-0-268-03378-1 (cloth : alk. paper) isbn-10: 0-268-03378-1 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Knowledge, Theory of. 2. Science —Methodology. 3. Logic. 4. Aristotle. Posterior analytics. 5. William, of Ockham, ca. 1285– ca. 1349. Summa logicae. 6.William, of Ockham, ca. 1285– ca. 1349. I. Title. bd161.l66 2006 160 —dc22 2006032380 ∞This book is printed on acid-free paper. © 2007 University of Notre Dame Press Longeway-01.Intro 11/8/06 2:28 PM Page 1 introduction The medievalist needs no convincing that William of Ockham (ca. 1285–1347) is worthy of study. At one time Ockham’s views might have been regarded as a clever but uninstructed sign of the decay of Scholastic discourse, but, with the work of such scholars as Philotheus Boehner, Ernest Moody, and Marilyn McCord Adams, those days are now receding into the past.
    [Show full text]
  • Averroes and His Using Plato's Republic in History
    Journal of Social Sciences and Humanities Vol. 1, No. 3, 2015, pp. 229-234 http://www.aiscience.org/journal/jssh Averroes and His Using Plato's Republic in History Mohammadreza Shahidipak * Faculty of Arts and humanity and literature, Department of History Islamic Republic of Iran, Islamic Azad University Central Tehran Branch, Tehran, Iran Abstract Classical Greek Social-political philosophy belongs to Plato and Aristotle and is based on the paradigm of liberty of human wisdom in presenting values in order to manage its life. Averroes (1126) re-examined the Greece philosophy and collected and explained the works and traces of Aristotle and this resulted in the development of philosophy and emergence a new global philosophy in Spain. In Averroes’s view, philosophy does not belong to Greece, and its universal truth has no limitation of nation, time or place. Representing the mentioned paradigm destroyed the cultural unity of the medieval world. Paper investigated the basic element of political philosophy as freedom, justice, ruler’s attributions, good life, philosophical description of cities and role of education and public law, right ,emotion, reason in facing of cities ;based on a commentary of Plato’s Republic by Averroes .He used terminology of political philosophy of Plato with Aristotelian view. Interpretation of social and political philosophy of Plato by Averroes in west of Islamic world is the most important cultural phenomenon in history of philosophy have conserved still his vast influence. Averroes is famous and remarkable philosopher and jurist believed in priority of reason and philosophy .He was excommunicated in eastern and western of Islamic world and in Europe but he still has any successors of Jew, Christians and Islamic philosophers and free scholar in the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Colleague, Critic, and Sometime Counselor to Thomas Becket
    JOHN OF SALISBURY: COLLEAGUE, CRITIC, AND SOMETIME COUNSELOR TO THOMAS BECKET By L. Susan Carter A DISSERTATION Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of History–Doctor of Philosophy 2021 ABSTRACT JOHN OF SALISBURY: COLLEAGUE, CRITIC, AND SOMETIME COUNSELOR TO THOMAS BECKET By L. Susan Carter John of Salisbury was one of the best educated men in the mid-twelfth century. The beneficiary of twelve years of study in Paris under the tutelage of Peter Abelard and other scholars, John flourished alongside Thomas Becket in the Canterbury curia of Archbishop Theobald. There, his skills as a writer were of great value. Having lived through the Anarchy of King Stephen, he was a fierce advocate for the liberty of the English Church. Not surprisingly, John became caught up in the controversy between King Henry II and Thomas Becket, Henry’s former chancellor and successor to Theobald as archbishop of Canterbury. Prior to their shared time in exile, from 1164-1170, John had written three treatises with concern for royal court follies, royal pressures on the Church, and the danger of tyrants at the core of the Entheticus de dogmate philosophorum , the Metalogicon , and the Policraticus. John dedicated these works to Becket. The question emerges: how effective was John through dedicated treatises and his letters to Becket in guiding Becket’s attitudes and behavior regarding Church liberty? By means of contemporary communication theory an examination of John’s writings and letters directed to Becket creates a new vista on the relationship between John and Becket—and the impact of John on this martyred archbishop.
    [Show full text]