Introduction to Algrbraic Topology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Introduction to Algrbraic Topology Introduction to Algrbraic Topology Ingo Waschkies September 27, 2010 Abstract Lecture notes of a course given at the Université de Nice - Sophia Antipolis in fall 2010 Contents 1 Category Theory 2 1.1 Categories and Functors . 2 1.2 Cartesian squares . 5 2 The fundamental groupoid 9 2.1 Connected spaces . 9 2.2 Construction of the fundamental groupoid . 11 2.3 Homotopy invariance . 14 3 Coverings 16 3.1 Fiber bundles . 16 3.2 Coverings . 19 3.3 Group actions and coverings . 22 3.4 Universal coverings and fundamental groupoid . 24 1 1 Category Theory 1.1 Categories and Functors Definition 1.1. A category C is given by the following data: (i) a class of objects Ob C, (ii) for any two objects X, Y ∈ Ob C a set HomC (X, Y) whose elements are called the morphisms (or arrows) from X to Y (iii) and for any three objects X, Y, Z ∈ Ob C a map ◦XYZ : HomC (X, Y) × HomC (Y, Z) − HomC (X, Z);(f, g) 7 g ◦XYZ f which is called composition map (the index XYZ→will be immediately omitted in the→ notations). such that the following two axioms are satisfied: (C1) For any object X ∈ Ob C there exists a morphism idX ∈ HomC (X, X) such that for any object Y and any morphisms f ∈ HomC (X, Y) we have f ◦ idX = f and idY ◦ f = f. (C2) The composition of morphisms is associative, i.e. for any objects X, Y, Z, W ∈ Ob C and any three morphisms f ∈ HomC (X, Y), g ∈ HomC (Y, Z) h ∈ HomC (Z, W) we have h ◦ (g ◦ f) = (h ◦ g) ◦ f. Let C be a category and X, Y ∈ Ob C two objects. Instead of f ∈ HomC (X, Y) we will usually write f : X Y, the object X is called the source of the morphism f and Y is called the target of f. An endomorphism is a morphism which has the same source and target. A morphism f : X Y is→ called an isomorphism if there exixts a morphism g : Y X such that g ◦ f = idX −1 and f◦g = idY . If such a morphism g exists it is unique and called the inverse morphism f of f. → → Let C be a category and X ∈ Ob C be an object. Then HomC (X, X) is a set endowed with a binary operation ◦ (the composition of morphisms) which is associative and has a unit element idX. Such a structure is called a monoid in basic algebra. It is not necessarily a group since mor- phisms need not be invertible. A category with only a single object ∗ is completely determined by the monoid HomC (∗, ∗), hence categories with one object are the same as monoids. In this sense a category is a generalization of the algebraic notion of monoid. We have already mentioned that in order to have a group structure on HomC (X, X) we need to impose that every endomorphism of X is invertible. So similarly to the monoid situation we can state that a category with a single object such that every morphism is an isomorphism is the same as a group. This leads to the following generalization of the algebraic notion of group: Definition 1.2. A groupoid is a category such that every morphism in G is an isomorphism. We will see soon that in some sense a groupoid is actually just a collection of groups, a collection that need not be a set. It will be convenient to introduce the opposite category C◦ of a category C. The category C◦ has the same objects as C but source and target of morphisms are formally exchanged, i.e. a morphism f : X Y in C◦ is a morphism f : Y X in C. More precisely: → →2 Definition 1.3. Let C be a category. Its opposite category C◦ is given by the following data: (i) Ob C◦ = Ob C, ◦ (ii) for any two objects X, Y ∈ Ob C we set HomC◦ (X, Y) = HomC (Y, X) (iii) and for any three objects X, Y, Z ∈ Ob C◦ the map op ◦ : HomC◦ (X, Y) × HomC◦ (Y, Z) − HomC◦ (X, Z) is given by g ◦op f = f ◦ g (note that f, g are morphism f : Y X, g : Z Y in C so the → composition is well defined). Note that if we have a monoid (i.e. a category with just a single object),→ then the→ opposite cate- gory is given by the monoid with the opposite structure. Definition 1.4. Let C, D be two categories. A functor F : C D is given by the following data (i) for each object X ∈ Ob C an object F(X) ∈ Ob D, → (ii) for any two objects X, Y ∈ Ob C a map (for which we will always omit the index XY ) FXY : HomC (X, Y) − HomD (F(X),F(Y)) such that the following axioms hold → (F1) for any X ∈ Ob C we have F(idX) = idF(X) (F2) for any X, Y, Z ∈ Ob C and any morphisms f : X Y, g : Y Z we have F(g) ◦ F(f) = F(g ◦ f) → → The axioms (F1) and (F2) are often called the functoriality axioms, and a functor is often just referred to as a correspondance F : Ob C Ob D ; X 7 F(X) which is functorial (or natural) in X. This always means that there are maps as in (ii) which satisfy (F1) and (F2). In practical situations, correspondances→F : Ob C Ob→D ; X 7 F(X) will sometimes be natural in X but will invert the direction of arrows (and therefore are not functors in the sense of the above definition). The perhaps easiest example→ is the duality→ for vector spaces: a linear ∗ ∗ ∗ ∗ ∗ ∗ ∗ ∗ map f : V W defines a linear map f : W V with idV = idV and (g ◦ f) = f ◦ g . This is what is called a contravariant functor. → → Definition 1.5. A contravariant functor F : C D is a functor F : C◦ D. This means, that it is given by the following data (i) for each object X ∈ Ob C an object F(X) ∈ Ob→D, → (ii) for any two objects X, Y ∈ Ob C a map F : HomC (X, Y) − HomD (F(Y),F(X)) such that the following axioms hold → (F’1) for any X ∈ Ob C we have F(idX) = idF(X) (F’2) for any X, Y, Z ∈ Ob C and any morphisms f : X Y, g : Y Z we have F(f) ◦ F(g) = F(g ◦ f) → → 3 If we want to emphasize that a functor is not contravariant we sometimes say that it is covari- ant. The category Set whose objects are the sets and whose morphisms are maps between sets plays a special role in category theory. Every category C is automatically equipped with a collection of Hom-functors indexed by the objects of C HX = HomC (X, · ): C − Set ; Y 7 HomC (X, Y) 0 On morphisms HX is defined as follows: for any morphism f : Y Y we define HX(f) as the composition with f, more precisely → → 0 → HX(f): HomC (X, Y) − HomC (X, Y ); g 7 HX(f)(g) = f ◦ g It is easy to check the functor axioms. Obviously we can also put the X in the second variable and get the so-called Yoneda-functors→ → YX = HomC ( · ,X): C − Set ; Y 7 HomC (Y, X) On morphisms YX is again defined as the composition, but beware this time we get a con- travariant functor. → → Given two functors F : C D and G : D E we can define the composition G ◦ F : C E by (G ◦ F)(X) = G(F(X)) for any object X ∈ Ob C and (G ◦ F)(f) = G(F(f)) for any morphism f from C. It is easily checked→ that G ◦ F satisfies→ the functor axioms F1 and F2. We may also easily→ see that the identity maps on objects and morphisms are functorial and define the identity functor IdC : C C, and we can form the category Cat of all categories (which leads to some set-theoretical problems as the collection of functors between two categories is not a set). Therefore we get→ the notion of an isomorphism between categories as a functor F : C D such that there exists a functor G : D C with G ◦ F = IdC and F ◦ G = IdD. This means just that F is an isomorphism of categories if and only if it is bijective on objects and morphisms.→ It turns out that this notion is of little importance→ because isomorphisms between categories arise only very rarely. This is because many constructions that can be formalized in category theory are only unique up to isomorphism, hence we encounter more frequently the situation that we have functors F : C D. G : D C such that for any object X ∈ Ob C the object GF(X) is not equal but isomorphic to X. A good example is the dual functor defined on the category of finite-dimensional vector→ spaces: → f f ∗ ∗ : Vect (k) − Vect (k); V 7 V = Homk (V, k) It is well-known that V V∗∗ is an isomorphism, but it is not an equality, so ∗ is not an iso- morphism of categories, it is what→ is called an equivalence→ of categories. To make a precise definition we need the notion→ of morphisms between functors: Definition 1.6. Let F, F0 : C D be functors. A morphism of functors φ : F G is a collection of morphisms φX indexed by all objects X ∈ Ob C → 0 → φX : F(X) F (X) 0 such that for every morphism f : X Y in C we get F (f) ◦ φX = φX 0 ◦ F(f).
Recommended publications
  • Math 5853 Homework Solutions 36. a Map F : X → Y Is Called an Open
    Math 5853 homework solutions 36. A map f : X → Y is called an open map if it takes open sets to open sets, and is called a closed map if it takes closed sets to closed sets. For example, a continuous bijection is a homeomorphism if and only if it is a closed map and an open map. 1. Give examples of continuous maps from R to R that are open but not closed, closed but not open, and neither open nor closed. open but not closed: f(x) = ex is a homeomorphism onto its image (0, ∞) (with the logarithm function as its inverse). If U is open, then f(U) is open in (0, ∞), and since (0, ∞) is open in R, f(U) is open in R. Therefore f is open. However, f(R) = (0, ∞) is not closed, so f is not closed. closed but not open: Constant functions are one example. We will give an example that is also surjective. Let f(x) = 0 for −1 ≤ x ≤ 1, f(x) = x − 1 for x ≥ 1, and f(x) = x+1 for x ≤ −1 (f is continuous by “gluing together on a finite collection of closed sets”). f is not open, since (−1, 1) is open but f((−1, 1)) = {0} is not open. To show that f is closed, let C be any closed subset of R. For n ∈ Z, −1 −1 define In = [n, n + 1]. Now, f (In) = [n + 1, n + 2] if n ≥ 1, f (I0) = [−1, 2], −1 −1 f (I−1) = [−2, 1], and f (In) = [n − 1, n] if n ≤ −2.
    [Show full text]
  • A Grothendieck Site Is a Small Category C Equipped with a Grothendieck Topology T
    Contents 5 Grothendieck topologies 1 6 Exactness properties 10 7 Geometric morphisms 17 8 Points and Boolean localization 22 5 Grothendieck topologies A Grothendieck site is a small category C equipped with a Grothendieck topology T . A Grothendieck topology T consists of a collec- tion of subfunctors R ⊂ hom( ;U); U 2 C ; called covering sieves, such that the following hold: 1) (base change) If R ⊂ hom( ;U) is covering and f : V ! U is a morphism of C , then f −1(R) = fg : W ! V j f · g 2 Rg is covering for V. 2) (local character) Suppose R;R0 ⊂ hom( ;U) and R is covering. If f −1(R0) is covering for all f : V ! U in R, then R0 is covering. 3) hom( ;U) is covering for all U 2 C . 1 Typically, Grothendieck topologies arise from cov- ering families in sites C having pullbacks. Cover- ing families are sets of maps which generate cov- ering sieves. Suppose that C has pullbacks. A topology T on C consists of families of sets of morphisms ffa : Ua ! Ug; U 2 C ; called covering families, such that 1) Suppose fa : Ua ! U is a covering family and y : V ! U is a morphism of C . Then the set of all V ×U Ua ! V is a covering family for V. 2) Suppose ffa : Ua ! Vg is covering, and fga;b : Wa;b ! Uag is covering for all a. Then the set of composites ga;b fa Wa;b −−! Ua −! U is covering. 3) The singleton set f1 : U ! Ug is covering for each U 2 C .
    [Show full text]
  • On Sheaf Theory
    Lectures on Sheaf Theory by C.H. Dowker Tata Institute of Fundamental Research Bombay 1957 Lectures on Sheaf Theory by C.H. Dowker Notes by S.V. Adavi and N. Ramabhadran Tata Institute of Fundamental Research Bombay 1956 Contents 1 Lecture 1 1 2 Lecture 2 5 3 Lecture 3 9 4 Lecture 4 15 5 Lecture 5 21 6 Lecture 6 27 7 Lecture 7 31 8 Lecture 8 35 9 Lecture 9 41 10 Lecture 10 47 11 Lecture 11 55 12 Lecture 12 59 13 Lecture 13 65 14 Lecture 14 73 iii iv Contents 15 Lecture 15 81 16 Lecture 16 87 17 Lecture 17 93 18 Lecture 18 101 19 Lecture 19 107 20 Lecture 20 113 21 Lecture 21 123 22 Lecture 22 129 23 Lecture 23 135 24 Lecture 24 139 25 Lecture 25 143 26 Lecture 26 147 27 Lecture 27 155 28 Lecture 28 161 29 Lecture 29 167 30 Lecture 30 171 31 Lecture 31 177 32 Lecture 32 183 33 Lecture 33 189 Lecture 1 Sheaves. 1 onto Definition. A sheaf S = (S, τ, X) of abelian groups is a map π : S −−−→ X, where S and X are topological spaces, such that 1. π is a local homeomorphism, 2. for each x ∈ X, π−1(x) is an abelian group, 3. addition is continuous. That π is a local homeomorphism means that for each point p ∈ S , there is an open set G with p ∈ G such that π|G maps G homeomorphi- cally onto some open set π(G).
    [Show full text]
  • LECTURE 1. Differentiable Manifolds, Differentiable Maps
    LECTURE 1. Differentiable manifolds, differentiable maps Def: topological m-manifold. Locally euclidean, Hausdorff, second-countable space. At each point we have a local chart. (U; h), where h : U ! Rm is a topological embedding (homeomorphism onto its image) and h(U) is open in Rm. Def: differentiable structure. An atlas of class Cr (r ≥ 1 or r = 1 ) for a topological m-manifold M is a collection U of local charts (U; h) satisfying: (i) The domains U of the charts in U define an open cover of M; (ii) If two domains of charts (U; h); (V; k) in U overlap (U \V 6= ;) , then the transition map: k ◦ h−1 : h(U \ V ) ! k(U \ V ) is a Cr diffeomorphism of open sets in Rm. (iii) The atlas U is maximal for property (ii). Def: differentiable map between differentiable manifolds. f : M m ! N n (continuous) is differentiable at p if for any local charts (U; h); (V; k) at p, resp. f(p) with f(U) ⊂ V the map k ◦ f ◦ h−1 = F : h(U) ! k(V ) is m differentiable at x0 = h(p) (as a map from an open subset of R to an open subset of Rn.) f : M ! N (continuous) is of class Cr if for any charts (U; h); (V; k) on M resp. N with f(U) ⊂ V , the composition k ◦ f ◦ h−1 : h(U) ! k(V ) is of class Cr (between open subsets of Rm, resp. Rn.) f : M ! N of class Cr is an immersion if, for any local charts (U; h); (V; k) as above (for M, resp.
    [Show full text]
  • When Is a Local Homeomorphism a Semicovering Map? in This Section, We Obtained Some Conditions Under Which a Local Homeomorphism Is a Semicovering Map
    When Is a Local Homeomorphism a Semicovering Map? Majid Kowkabia, Behrooz Mashayekhya,∗, Hamid Torabia aDepartment of Pure Mathematics, Center of Excellence in Analysis on Algebraic Structures, Ferdowsi University of Mashhad, P.O.Box 1159-91775, Mashhad, Iran Abstract In this paper, by reviewing the concept of semicovering maps, we present some conditions under which a local homeomorphism becomes a semicovering map. We also obtain some conditions under which a local homeomorphism is a covering map. Keywords: local homeomorphism, fundamental group, covering map, semicovering map. 2010 MSC: 57M10, 57M12, 57M05 1. Introduction It is well-known that every covering map is a local homeomorphism. The converse seems an interesting question that when a local homeomorphism is a covering map (see [4], [8], [6].) Recently, Brazas [2, Definition 3.1] generalized the concept of covering map by the phrase “A semicovering map is a local homeomorphism with continuous lifting of paths and homotopies”. Note that a map p : Y → X has continuous lifting of paths if ρp : (ρY )y → (ρX)p(y) defined by ρp(α) = p ◦ α is a homeomorphism for all y ∈ Y, where (ρY )y = {α : [0, 1] → Y |α(0) = y}. Also, a map p : Y → X has continuous lifting of homotopies if Φp : (ΦY )y → (ΦX)p(y) defined by Φp(φ)= p ◦ φ is a homeomorphism for all y ∈ Y , where elements of (ΦY )y are endpoint preserving homotopies of paths starting at y. It is easy to see that any covering map is a semicovering. qtop The quasitopological fundamental group π1 (X, x) is the quotient space of the loop space Ω(X, x) equipped with the compact-open topology with respect to the function Ω(X, x) → π1(X, x) identifying path components (see [1]).
    [Show full text]
  • MATH 552 C. Homeomorphisms, Manifolds and Diffeomorphisms 2020-09 Bijections Let X and Y Be Sets, and Let U ⊂ X Be a Subset. A
    MATH 552 C. Homeomorphisms, Manifolds and Diffeomorphisms 2021-09 Bijections Let X and Y be sets, and let U ⊆ X be a subset. A map (or function) f with domain U takes each element x 2 U to a unique element f(x) 2 Y . We write y = f(x); or x 7! f(x): Note that in the textbook and lecture notes, one writes f : X ! Y; even if the domain is a proper subset of X, and often the domain is not specified explicitly. The range (or image) of f is the subset f(U) = f y 2 Y : there exists x 2 U such that y = f(x) g: A map f : X ! Y is one-to-one (or is invertible, or is an injection) if for all x1, x2 in the domain, f(x1) = f(x2) implies x1 = x2 (equivalently, x1 6= x2 implies f(x1) 6= f(x2)). If f is one-to-one, then there is an inverse map (or inverse function) f −1 : Y ! X whose domain is the range f(U) of f. A map f : X ! Y is onto (or is a surjection) if f(U) = Y . We will say a map f : X ! Y is a bijection (or one-to-one correspondence) from X onto Y if its domain is all of X, and it is one-to-one and onto. If f is a bijection, then its inverse map f −1 : Y ! X is defined on all of Y . Homeomorphisms Let X and Y be topological spaces. Examples of topological spaces are: i) Rn; ii) a metric space; iii) a smooth manifold (see below); iv) an open subset of Rn or of a smooth manifold.
    [Show full text]
  • A CATEGORICAL INTRODUCTION to SHEAVES Contents 1
    A CATEGORICAL INTRODUCTION TO SHEAVES DAPING WENG Abstract. Sheaf is a very useful notion when defining and computing many different cohomology theories over topological spaces. There are several ways to build up sheaf theory with different axioms; however, some of the axioms are a little bit hard to remember. In this paper, we are going to present a \natural" approach from a categorical viewpoint, with some remarks of applications of sheaf theory at the end. Some familiarity with basic category notions is assumed for the readers. Contents 1. Motivation1 2. Definitions and Constructions2 2.1. Presheaf2 2.2. Sheaf 4 3. Sheafification5 3.1. Direct Limit and Stalks5 3.2. Sheafification in Action8 3.3. Sheafification as an Adjoint Functor 12 4. Exact Sequence 15 5. Induced Sheaf 18 5.1. Direct Image 18 5.2. Inverse Image 18 5.3. Adjunction 20 6. A Brief Introduction to Sheaf Cohomology 21 Conclusion and Acknowlegdment 23 References 23 1. Motivation In many occasions, we may be interested in algebraic structures defined over local neigh- borhoods. For example, a theory of cohomology of a topological space often concerns with sets of maps from a local neighborhood to some abelian groups, which possesses a natural Z-module struture. Another example is line bundles (either real or complex): since R or C are themselves rings, the set of sections over a local neighborhood forms an R or C-module. To analyze this local algebraic information, mathematians came up with the notion of sheaves, which accommodate local and global data in a natural way. However, there are many fashion of introducing sheaves; Tennison [2] and Bredon [1] have done it in two very different styles in their seperate books, though both of which bear the name \Sheaf Theory".
    [Show full text]
  • On Semicovering, Subsemicovering, and Subcovering Maps
    Archive of SID Journal of Algebraic Systems Vol. 7, No. 2, (2020), pp 227-244 ON SEMICOVERING, SUBSEMICOVERING, AND SUBCOVERING MAPS M. KOWKABI , B. MASHAYEKHY AND H. TORABI∗ Abstract. In this paper, by reviewing the concept of subcover- ing and semicovering maps, we extend the notion of subcovering map to subsemicovering map. We present some necessary or suffi- cient conditions for a local homeomorphism to be a subsemicover- ing map. Moreover, we investigate the relationship between these conditions by some examples. Finally, we give a necessary and sufficient condition for a subsemicovering map to be semicovering. 1. Introduction and Motivation Steinberg [8, Section 4.2] defined a map p : X~ ! X of locally path connected spaces as a subcovering map if there exist a covering map p0 : Y~ ! X and a topological embedding i : X~ ! Y~ such that p0 ◦ i = p. He presented a necessary and sufficient condition for a local homeomorphism p : X~ ! X to be subcovering. More precisely, he proved that a continuous map p : X~ ! X of locally path connected and semilocally simply connected spaces is subcovering if and only if p : X~ ! X is a local homeomorphism and any path f in X~ with p ◦ f null homotopic (in X) is closed, that is, f(0) = f(1) (see [8, Theorem 4.6]). Brazas [2, Definition 3.1] extended the concept of covering mapto semicovering map. A semicovering map is a local homeomorphism with continuous lifting of paths and homotopies. We simplified the notion of MSC(2010): Primary: 57M10; Secondary: 57M12, 57M05. Keywords: Local homeomorphism, fundamental group, covering map, semicovering map subcovering map, subsemicovering map.
    [Show full text]
  • On Fundamental Groups of Quotient Spaces ∗ Jack S
    Topology and its Applications 159 (2012) 322–330 Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect Topology and its Applications www.elsevier.com/locate/topol On fundamental groups of quotient spaces ∗ Jack S. Calcut a, , Robert E. Gompf b,1,JohnD.McCarthyc a Department of Mathematics, Oberlin College, Oberlin, OH 44074, United States b Department of Mathematics, University of Texas at Austin, 1 University Station C1200, Austin, TX 78712-0257, United States c Department of Mathematics, Michigan State University, East Lansing, MI 48824-1027, United States article info abstract Article history: In classical covering space theory, a covering map induces an injection of fundamental Received 7 March 2011 groups. This paper reveals a dual property for certain quotient maps having connected Received in revised form 22 September fibers, with applications to orbit spaces of vector fields and leaf spaces in general. 2011 © 2011 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. Accepted 26 September 2011 MSC: primary 54B15 secondary 57M05, 37C10, 55U10 Keywords: Vietoris mapping theorem Homotopy Fundamental group Quotient map Connected fiber Orbit space Hawaiian earring Semilocally simply-connected 1. Introduction Given a map f : X → Y of topological spaces, an important problem is to relate the homology of X with that of Y using properties of f . Vietoris pioneered the study of this problem with his mapping theorem. Theorem. (Vietoris [32, §III]) Let f : X → Y be a surjective map of compact metric spaces. If the (Vietoris) homology of each fiber −1 Hr ( f (y)) is trivial for 0 r n − 1, then the induced homomorphism f∗ : Hr (X) → Hr (Y ) is an isomorphism for r n − 1 and is surjective for r = n.
    [Show full text]
  • Local Mapping Relations and Global Implicit Function Theoremsc)
    LOCAL MAPPING RELATIONS AND GLOBAL IMPLICIT FUNCTION THEOREMSC) BY WERNER C. RHEINBOLDT Dedicated to Professor H. Goertler on his sixtieth birthday 1. Introduction. Consider the problem of solving a nonlinear equation (1) F(x,y) = z with respect to y for given x and z. If, for example, x, y, z are elements of some Banach space, then under appropriate conditions about F, the well-known implicit function theorem ensures the "local" solvability of (1). The question arises when such a local result leads to "global" existence theorems. Several authors, for example, Cesari [2], Ehrmann [5], Hildebrandt and Graves [8], and Levy [9], have obtained results along this line. But these results are closely tied to the classical implicit function theorem, and no general theory appears to exist which permits the deduction of global solvability results once a local one is known. The problem has considerable interest in numerical analysis. In fact, when an operator equation (2) Fy = x is to be solved iteratively for y, the process converges usually only in a neighborhood of a solution. If for some other operator F0 the equation F0y = x has been solved, then one may try to "connect" F and F0 by an operator homotopy H(t,y) such that 77(0, y) = F0y and H(l,y) = Fy, and to "move" along the solution "curve" y(t) of H(t,y)=x, O^i^l, from the known solution y(0) to the unknown y(l), for instance, by using a locally convergent iterative process. This is the so-called "continuation method".
    [Show full text]
  • Math 396. Quotients by Group Actions Many Important Manifolds Are
    Math 396. Quotients by group actions Many important manifolds are constructed as quotients by actions of groups on other manifolds, and this often provides a useful way to understand spaces that may have been constructed by other means. As a basic example, the Klein bottle will be defined as a quotient of S1 × S1 by the action of a group of order 2. (We will also see how this is related to the usual picture of the Klein bottle, to “justify” our definition.) Also, projective n-space as we defined it earlier will turn out to be the quotient of the standard n-sphere by the action of a group of order 2. The circle as defined concretely in R2 is isomorphic (in a sense to be made precise) to the the quotient of R by additive translation by Z (or 2πZ; it all comes to the same thing, as we shall see). We first work out some definitions and examples in a set-theoretic setting, then we introduce topologies. In the geometric (as opposed to set-theoretic) setup, we will restrict our attention to very nice cases where the group has essentially no geometric structure. In practice one must go beyond this to allow the group that acts to be a positive-dimensional manifold, but that would introduce a host of complications that we cannot adequately treat without more knowledge of the theory of manifolds. Nonetheless, even within the restricted setup that we consider, we will see many interesting examples. 1. Set-theoretic case Definition 1.1. Let X be a set and G a group.
    [Show full text]
  • Homeomorphisms Between Banach Spaces 171
    transactions of the american mathematical society Volume 200, 1974 HOMEOMORPHISMSBETWEEN BANACH SPACES BY ROY PLASTOCK(l) ABSTRACT. We consider the problem of finding precise conditions for a map F between two Banach spaces X, Y to be a global homeomorphism. Using methods from covering space theory we reduce the global homeomor- phism problem to one of finding conditions for a local homeomorphism to satisfy the "line lifting property." This property is then shown to be equivalent to a lim- iting condition which we designate by (L). Thus we finally show that a local homeomorphism is a global homeomorphism if and only if (L) is satisfied. In par- ticular we show that if a local homeomorphism is (i) proper (Banach-Mazur) or (ii) ¡Q infi^ii^ l/||[F'(x)]_ lids = ~ (Hadamard-Levy), then (L) is satisfied. Other analytic conditions are also given. Introduction. Suppose we have a continuous (or continuously differentiable) map F between two Banach spaces X and Y. We ask what additional assump- tions must be imposed upon F to insure that it is a homeomorphism (diffeomor- phism) of X onto TI We observe that if F is a homeomorphism then in par- ticular it is a local homeomorphism. Also if F is a diffeomorphism, then by the chain rule F'(x) is an invertible linear map for every x. Since these conditions are necessary for our problem, we shall always assume that our map F is either a local homeomorphism or, if F eC1(Ar), that F'(x) is invertible. Thus we ask when such a map is a homeomorphism (diffeomorphism) of X onto Y.
    [Show full text]