Learn to Direct Your Dreams by Jessica Hamzelou Newscientist / June 15, 2010

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Learn to Direct Your Dreams by Jessica Hamzelou Newscientist / June 15, 2010 archived as http://www.stealthskater.com/Documents/Lucid_12.doc (.pdf) more of the Lucid Dreaming at http://www.stealthskater.com/Science.htm#Lucid note: because important websites are frequently "here today but gone tomorrow", the following was archived from http://www.newscientist.com/article/mg20627640.900-want-to-find-your-mind- learn-to-direct-your-dreams.html on December 29, 2009. This is NOT an attempt to divert readers from the aforementioned web-site. Indeed, the reader should only read this back-up copy if the updated original cannot be found at the original author's site. Want to find your Mind? Learn to direct your Dreams by Jessica Hamzelou NewScientist / June 15, 2010 Editorial http://www.newscientist.com/article/mg20627642.200-wake-up-dreaming-to-explore- consciousness.html The study of Lucid Dreaming has been seen as a fringe activity for too long. The little research that has been done suggests lucid dreamers' brains are in a penumbral state between waking and sleeping, offering all kinds of opportunities for study. Some now believe it could be possible to induce lucid dreams at will. Doing so would offer more than the chance to enjoy fantastical adventures. Harnessing lucid dreams could provide insights into consciousness (see "The secret of Consciousness: Re-interpreting Dreams"). As with any advance into a twilight zone, there will be concerns. A lucid dreamer might lose their ability to distinguish between the dream world and reality, for example. It is right to be cautious. But let's not lose sight of the opportunities. Some believe that confronting our demons in lucid dreams could help us overcome phobias. Others see the research leading to therapies for schizophrenia. There are even suggestions that practicing a motor task in a lucid dream (such as dancing or playing an instrument) can hone skills in the waking World. By harnessing our night-time dreams, we may be able to realize our waking ones more easily. "Am I awake or am I dreaming?" I ask myself for probably the hundredth time. I am fully awake, just like all the other times I asked. And to be honest, I am beginning to feel a bit silly. All week, I have been performing this "reality check" in the hope that it will become so ingrained in my mind that I will start asking it in my dreams too. If I succeed, I will have a lucid dream -- a thrilling state of consciousness somewhere between waking and sleeping in which unlike conventional dreams you are aware that you are dreaming and able to control your actions. Once you have figured this out, the dream world is theoretically your oyster and you can act out your fantasies to your heart's content. 1 Journalistic interest notwithstanding, I am pursuing lucid dreaming for entertainment. To some neuroscientists, however, the phenomenon is of profound interest and they are using lucid dreamers to explore some of the weirder aspects of the brain's behavior during the dream state (see "Dream Mysteries"). Their results are even shedding light on the way our brains produce our rich and complex conscious experience. It's a central issue in the study of Consciousness. In 1992, Gerald Edelman at the Scripps Research Institute in La Jolla, California proposed that there are 2 possible states of consciousness which he called primary and secondary consciousness. Primary consciousness is the simple subjective experience of sensory perception and emotions, which could be applied to most animals. It's a state of "just being, feeling, floating" according to Ursula Voss at the University of Frankfurt in Germany. The mental life of your common or "garden" human, however, is a lot more complicated. That's because we are "aware of being aware". This allows us to reflect upon ourselves and our feelings and, in an ideal world, make insightful decisions and judgments. This state -- dubbed "secondary consciousness" -- is thought to be unique to humans. "When you're awake, you have both primary and secondary consciousness. Secondary consciousness is that reflective awareness that determines a great part of waking consciousness," says Voss. Pinning down how our brain produces these two, subjective, states of consciousness is a tough challenge because it's difficult to isolate the different aspects of consciousness in fully awake subjects from other neural processes unrelated to awareness. Which is where dreams come in. When we dream, we experience events (albeit imagined) and emotions. But, crucially, we lack certain aspects of self-awareness that we normally feel when we are awake, particularly those involved in the rational reflection on what we are experiencing. You could easily see an outrageous event -- a fluorescent pink kitten flying past on golden wings, to name but one -- without batting a dream eyelid. "If we can accept really weird and bizarre events as perfectly normal happenings, that means there's something wrong with our reflective, rational consciousness," says Patrick McNamara of Boston University. For this reason, some researchers like Allan Hobson at Harvard Medical School believe that dreams are akin to Edelman's definition of primary consciousness. Comparing the dream state with the waking state could let us explore the way the brain generates the self-awareness of secondary consciousness. Some headway had already been made in this direction by the late 1990s. In 1997, Eric Nofzinger and his colleagues at the University of Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania compared the brain activity of awake individuals with dreamers using PET scans which reveal how much energy parts of the brain are using. The team identified 3 main regions that showed more activity during dream sleep which is characterized by rapid eye movement (REM). The areas were along the midline of the brain, the insula and the left amygdala. Together, these regions are thought to be involved in motivation and reward mechanisms and processing emotions, which Nofzinger reckons might explain why dreams are often so emotional. 2 Surprisingly, given the irrationality of the dream experience, many of the frontal areas of the brain involved in advanced cognition such as reasoning and forward planning were also active in the dreamers. But there was one notable exception: the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (DLPFC) was remarkably subdued in REM sleep, compared with during wakefulness. To Hobson, that strongly suggests that this particular area -- above other frontal regions -- is crucial for the critical reflective awareness present in waking, and therefore secondary, consciousness (Trends in Cognitive Sciences, vol 6, p 475). Could this one brain region alone explain our secondary consciousness? It's here that lucid dreams enter the picture. With their increased self-awareness, lucid dreams share certain aspects of secondary consciousness. So researchers are now vying to observe what happens in the brain when someone "wakes up" within their dream and whether they exhibit any further signatures of consciousness. "It's a very interesting leap because it can show you exactly what occurs if you jump from limited consciousness to very high consciousness," says Victor Spoormaker of the Max Planck Institute of Psychiatry, Munich, Germany. "This should be one of the main themes of lucid dream research." Lucidity on demand Voss and her colleagues made tentative steps towards using lucid dreams to study consciousness in 2009. She trained a group of students to become lucid dreamers using a number of tips and tricks (see "Lessons in Lucidity"). Once they had "woken up" within their dream, the subjects were then asked to signal to Voss that they were lucid by moving their eyes in a previously agreed pattern, which was measured with an electro-oculograph. "We have no other way of knowing they're really in a lucid dream," says Voss. "It's a great effort to make these eye movements because normally you're in that dream and you're busy with other things; you don't want to communicate with the outside world." At the same time, Voss used EEG (i.e., a cap of electrodes placed on the scalp) to record their brain activity. Unfortunately, the team only managed to capture 3 lucid dreams -- an indication of just how tricky they are to study. But it was enough to reveal a couple of intriguing differences between the lucid and non-lucid dreaming brain that may contribute to the secondary state of consciousness. Firstly, the team observed an increase in a specific brainwave -- oscillating at 40 hertz -- in the frontal regions during the lucid dreams compared to the non-lucid dreams which tended to have slower brainwaves. They also found greater synchronized activity between the frontal and parietal regions of the brain than in normal REM sleep, though less than would be expected in a fully awake subject (Sleep, vol 32, p 1191). Importantly, the overall brain activity was still significantly different to the waking state. Meaning that the subjects couldn't have been awake and simply pretending to lucid dream (see diagram). 3 What was the DLPFC up to? If it really were key to the self-awareness of secondary consciousness, you would expect it to "light up" during the lucid dreaming state. Unfortunately, EEG is not sensitive enough to measure the neural activity in such a small, specific area. However, preliminary work by Michael Czisch at the Max Planck Institute of Psychiatry in Munich, Germany hints at the answer. He used high-resolution fMRI scans to investigate the brain state of lucid dreamers. Although the results are currently being peer-reviewed (so many of the details are still "under wraps"), Czisch has hinted that the scans again reveal highly coordinated activity in the frontal regions of the brain, and also in the parietal and temporal zones, once the dreamers became lucid.
Recommended publications
  • Theoretical Models of Consciousness: a Scoping Review
    brain sciences Review Theoretical Models of Consciousness: A Scoping Review Davide Sattin 1,2,*, Francesca Giulia Magnani 1, Laura Bartesaghi 1, Milena Caputo 1, Andrea Veronica Fittipaldo 3, Martina Cacciatore 1, Mario Picozzi 4 and Matilde Leonardi 1 1 Neurology, Public Health, Disability Unit—Scientific Department, Fondazione IRCCS Istituto Neurologico Carlo Besta, 20133 Milan, Italy; [email protected] (F.G.M.); [email protected] (L.B.); [email protected] (M.C.); [email protected] (M.C.); [email protected] (M.L.) 2 Experimental Medicine and Medical Humanities-PhD Program, Biotechnology and Life Sciences Department and Center for Clinical Ethics, Insubria University, 21100 Varese, Italy 3 Oncology Department, Mario Negri Institute for Pharmacological Research IRCCS, 20156 Milan, Italy; veronicaandrea.fi[email protected] 4 Center for Clinical Ethics, Biotechnology and Life Sciences Department, Insubria University, 21100 Varese, Italy; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +39-02-2394-2709 Abstract: The amount of knowledge on human consciousness has created a multitude of viewpoints and it is difficult to compare and synthesize all the recent scientific perspectives. Indeed, there are many definitions of consciousness and multiple approaches to study the neural correlates of consciousness (NCC). Therefore, the main aim of this article is to collect data on the various theories of consciousness published between 2007–2017 and to synthesize them to provide a general overview of this topic. To describe each theory, we developed a thematic grid called the dimensional model, which qualitatively and quantitatively analyzes how each article, related to one specific theory, debates/analyzes a specific issue.
    [Show full text]
  • Measuring Consciousness in Dreams: the Lucidity and Consciousness In
    Consciousness and Cognition 22 (2013) 8–21 Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect Consciousness and Cognition journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/concog Measuring consciousness in dreams: The lucidity and consciousness in dreams scale ⇑ Ursula Voss a,b, , Karin Schermelleh-Engel a, Jennifer Windt c, Clemens Frenzel d, Allan Hobson e a J.W. Goethe University, Deptartment of Psychology, Frankfurt, Germany b Vitos Hochtaunus GmbH, Waldkrankenhaus Koeppern, Germany c Johannes Gutenberg University Mainz, Germany d Rheinische Friedrich-Wilhelms University, Deptartment of Psychology, Bonn, Germany e Harvard Medical School, Boston, MA, United States article info abstract Article history: In this article, we present results from an interdisciplinary research project aimed at Received 28 April 2012 assessing consciousness in dreams. For this purpose, we compared lucid dreams with nor- mal non-lucid dreams from REM sleep. Both lucid and non-lucid dreams are an important contrast condition for theories of waking consciousness, giving valuable insights into the Keywords: structure of conscious experience and its neural correlates during sleep. However, the pre- Consciousness cise differences between lucid and non-lucid dreams remain poorly understood. The con- Dreams struction of the Lucidity and Consciousness in Dreams scale (LuCiD) was based on Lucid dreaming theoretical considerations and empirical observations. Exploratory factor analysis of the Emotion Insight data from the first survey identified eight factors that were validated in a second survey Control using confirmatory factor analysis: INSIGHT, CONTROL, THOUGHT, REALISM, MEMORY, Thought DISSOCIATION, NEGATIVE EMOTION, and POSITIVE EMOTION. While all factors are involved in dream consciousness, realism and negative emotion do not differentiate between lucid and non-lucid dreams, suggesting that lucid insight is separable from both bizarreness in dreams and a change in the subjectively experienced realism of the dream.
    [Show full text]
  • Gerald Edelman - Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    Gerald Edelman - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Create account Log in Article Talk Read Edit View history Gerald Edelman From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Main page Gerald Maurice Edelman (born July 1, 1929) is an Contents American biologist who shared the 1972 Nobel Prize in Gerald Maurice Edelman Featured content Physiology or Medicine for work with Rodney Robert Born July 1, 1929 (age 83) Current events Porter on the immune system.[1] Edelman's Nobel Prize- Ozone Park, Queens, New York Nationality Random article winning research concerned discovery of the structure of American [2] Fields Donate to Wikipedia antibody molecules. In interviews, he has said that the immunology; neuroscience way the components of the immune system evolve over Alma Ursinus College, University of Interaction the life of the individual is analogous to the way the mater Pennsylvania School of Medicine Help components of the brain evolve in a lifetime. There is a Known for immune system About Wikipedia continuity in this way between his work on the immune system, for which he won the Nobel Prize, and his later Notable Nobel Prize in Physiology or Community portal work in neuroscience and in philosophy of mind. awards Medicine in 1972 Recent changes Contact Wikipedia Contents [hide] Toolbox 1 Education and career 2 Nobel Prize Print/export 2.1 Disulphide bonds 2.2 Molecular models of antibody structure Languages 2.3 Antibody sequencing 2.4 Topobiology 3 Theory of consciousness Беларуская 3.1 Neural Darwinism Български 4 Evolution Theory Català 5 Personal Deutsch 6 See also Español 7 References Euskara 8 Bibliography Français 9 Further reading 10 External links Hrvatski Ido Education and career [edit] Bahasa Indonesia Italiano Gerald Edelman was born in 1929 in Ozone Park, Queens, New York to Jewish parents, physician Edward Edelman, and Anna Freedman Edelman, who worked in the insurance industry.[3] After עברית Kiswahili being raised in New York, he attended college in Pennsylvania where he graduated magna cum Nederlands laude with a B.S.
    [Show full text]
  • Towards a Possible Entropy-Driven Process of Consciousness
    Journal of Behavioral and Brain Science, 2018, 8, 674-696 http://www.scirp.org/journal/jbbs ISSN Online: 2160-5874 ISSN Print: 2160-5866 Towards a Possible Entropy-Driven Process of Consciousness Pierre R. Blanquet1,2 1Club d’Histoire des Neurosciences, Université Pierre et Marie Curie, Paris, France 2Lab. SHERE, Université Paris-Diderot, Paris, France How to cite this paper: Blanquet, P.R. Abstract (2018) Towards a Possible Entropy-Driven Process of Consciousness. Journal of Beha- In the present article, we argue that consciousness and body are not to be vioral and Brain Science, 8, 674-696. separate to explain the intentional consciousness of the human being facing https://doi.org/10.4236/jbbs.2018.812041 to environment. 1) The most neurobiologist and neurocognitivist studies Received: November 21, 2018 suggest that the emerging consciousness appears to be a generic recurring Accepted: December 24, 2018 process which subsumes under it the various results of scientist approaches. Published: December 27, 2018 When analyzed with the cybernetic transductive method of Simondon, this process can be viewed as a noetico-neuronal unit which the sui generis activ- Copyright © 2018 by author and Scientific Research Publishing Inc. ity can be boiled down to concept of intentional consciousness. 2) Homeosta- This work is licensed under the Creative sis can be also metaphorically described as a generic recurring process which Commons Attribution International subsumes under it the myriad molecular feedback loops of organism. This License (CC BY 4.0). self-regulating dynamic process could be governed by the cosmologic (Earth http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ Open Access + Universe) production of entropy, which would keep high activity and dis- sipating energy and low internal entropy to maintain an ordering in the or- ganic structure.
    [Show full text]
  • Affective Consciousness: Core Emotional Feelings in Animals And
    ARTICLE IN PRESS Consciousness and Cognition Consciousness and Cognition xxx (2005) xxx–xxx www.elsevier.com/locate/concog Affective consciousness: Core emotional feelings in animals and humans Jaak Panksepp Department of Psychology, Bowling Green State University, Bowling Green, OH 43403, USA Falk Center for Molecular Therapeutics, Department of Biomedical Engineering, McCormick School of Engineerings, Northwestern University, Evanston, IL, USA Received 7 February 2004 Abstract The position advanced in this paper is that the bedrock of emotional feelings is contained within the evolved emotional action apparatus of mammalian brains. This dual-aspect monism approach to brain– mind functions, which asserts that emotional feelings may reflect the neurodynamics of brain systems that generate instinctual emotional behaviors, saves us from various conceptual conundrums. In coarse form, primary process affective consciousness seems to be fundamentally an unconditional ‘‘gift of nature’’ rather than an acquired skill, even though those systems facilitate skill acquisition via various felt reinforcements. Affective consciousness, being a comparatively intrinsic function of the brain, shared homologously by all mammalian species, should be the easiest variant of consciousness to study in animals. This is not to deny that some secondary processes (e.g., awareness of feelings in the generation of behavioral choices) cannot be evaluated in animals with sufficiently clever behavioral learning procedures, as with place-preference procedures and the analysis of changes in learned behaviors after one has induced re-valuation of incen- tives. Rather, the claim is that a direct neuroscientific study of primary process emotional/affective states is best achieved through the study of the intrinsic (‘‘instinctual’’), albeit experientially refined, emotional action tendencies of other animals.
    [Show full text]
  • Consciousness, Dreams, and Inference
    J. Allan Hobson 1 and Karl J. Friston 2 Consciousness, Dreams, and Inference ¡ ¥ ¨ The Cartesian Theatre Revisited ¤ ¡ ¢ ¥ ¤ ¤ Abstract: This paper considers the Cartesian theatre as a metaphor ¡ ¨ for the virtual reality models that the brain uses to make inferences ¡ about the world. This treatment derives from our attempts to under- ¨ ¥ ¤ £ stand dreaming and waking consciousness in terms of free energy ¢ minimization. The idea here is that the Cartesian theatre is not ¡ observed by an internal (homuncular) audience but furnishes a thea- © tre in which fictive narratives and fantasies can be rehearsed and ¨ § tested against sensory evidence. We suppose the brain is driven by the ¥ ¦ ¤ £ ¡ imperative to infer the causes of its sensory samples; in much the same ¢ ¤ ¡ way as scientists are compelled to test hypotheses about experimental ¢ ¤ data. This recapitulates Helmholtz’s notion of unconscious inference ¡ and Gregory’streatment of perception as hypothesis testing. However, we take this further and consider the active sampling of the world as the gathering of confirmatory evidence for hypotheses based on our virtual reality. The ensuing picture of consciousness (or active infer - ence) resolves a number of seemingly hard problems in consciousness research and is internally consistent with current thinking in systems neuroscience and theoretical neurobiology. In this formalism, there is a dualism that distinguishes between the (conscious) process of Correspondence: Karl Friston, Wellcome Trust Centre for Neuroimaging, Institute of Neurology, Queen Square, London, WC1N 3BG. Email: [email protected] [1] Division of Sleep Medicine, Harvard Medical School, Boston, MA 02215, USA. [2] The Wellcome Trust Centre for Neuroimaging, University College London, Queen Square, London, WC1N 3BG.
    [Show full text]
  • A Brief Tour of the Introductions to Consciousness Studies
    Epilogue: A Brief Tour of the Introductions to Consciousness Studies That a man should simply and profoundly say that he cannot understand how consciousness has come into existence – is perfectly natural. But that a man should glue his eye to a microscope and stare and stare – and still not be able to see how it happens – is ridiculous, and it is particularly ridiculous when it is supposed to be serious. […] If the natural scientists had been developed in Socrates’ day as they are now, all the sophists would have been scientists. One would have hung a microscope outside his shop in order to attract custom, and then would have had a sign painted saying: “Learn and see through a giant microscope how a man thinks” (Soren Kierkegaard, diary entry of 1846 ) Like a fortress under siege, consciousness has so far resisted any attempts to provide convincing solutions to the many questions it poses. The great neurophysiologist Sir Charles Sherrington (Fig. 1 ) neatly captured the problem of understanding the very nature of consciousness as a phenomenon which appears to elude scientifi c explana- tion within the domain of physical science: “The energy-concept […] embraces and unifi es much. […] Immense as it is, and self-satisfying as it is, and self-contained as it is, it yet seems but an introduction to something else. For instance a star which we perceive. The energy-scheme deals with it, describes the passing of radiation thence into the eye, the little light-image of it formed at the bottom of the eye, the ensuing photo-chemical action in the retina, the trains of action- potentials travelling along the nerve to the brain, the further electrical disturbance in the brain, the action- potentials streaming thence to the muscles of eye-balls and of the pupil, the contrac- tion of them sharpening the light-image and placing the best seeing part of the retina under it.
    [Show full text]
  • Defence of Idealism: Some Questions and Conclusions , London: Macmillan, 1917
    1 May Sinclair, A Defence of Idealism: Some Questions and Conclusions , London: Macmillan, 1917, Extract 1: introduction There is a certain embarrassment in coming forward with an Apology for Idealistic Monism at the present moment. You cannot be quite sure whether you are putting in an appearance too late or much too early. It does look like personal misfortune or perversity that, when there are lots of other philosophies to choose from, you should happen to hit on the one that has just had a tremendous innings and is now in process of being bowled out. As long ago as the early 'nineties Idealism was supposed to be dead and haunting Oxford. I know that the New Realists have said that it is now a fashionable philosophy. But either they do not really mean it, or they mean that only philosophies in their last decrepitude become fashionable at all. [...] I think it may be said that certain vulnerable forms of Idealism are things of the past; and that the new atomistic Realism is a thing of the future; at any rate of the immediate future. But we know of Old Realisms that died and decayed, and were buried, and of New Idealisms that died and rose again. […] And so I think that some day (which may be as distant as you please) the New Realism will grow old and die, and the New Idealism will be born again. It will be born, not out of its own ashes, nor out of its own life only, but out of what is living in the system that for the time being has superseded it.
    [Show full text]
  • Dreams: a Unified Theory Approach Chance Mcdermott James Madison University
    James Madison University JMU Scholarly Commons Dissertations The Graduate School Fall 2017 Dreams: A unified theory approach Chance McDermott James Madison University Follow this and additional works at: https://commons.lib.jmu.edu/diss201019 Part of the Clinical Psychology Commons Recommended Citation McDermott, Chance, "Dreams: A unified theory approach" (2017). Dissertations. 163. https://commons.lib.jmu.edu/diss201019/163 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the The Graduate School at JMU Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of JMU Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Dreams: A Unified Theory Approach Chance McDermott A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty of JAMES MADISON UNIVERSITY In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the degree of Doctor of Psychology Department of Graduate Psychology December 2017 FACULTY COMMITTEE: Committee Chair: Dr. Gregg Henriques Committee Members/ Readers: Dr. Kenneth Critchfield Dr. Anne Stewart Acknowledgements I would like to thank all of the members of my dissertation committee for their support and guidance in the completion of this work. Dr. Gregg Henriques, Dr. Anne Stewart, Dr. Elena Savina, and Dr. Ken Critchfield, each inspired me to produce my best work clinically, theoretically, and creatively. I benefitted not only through their dedication to teaching and training, but also through the opportunity to observe countless examples their richness of character and warmth of spirit. I would like to express special gratitude to my advisor, Dr. Gregg Henriques, who went above and beyond in his efforts to help me grow as a scholar, clinician, and human being.
    [Show full text]
  • July 17, 2020 a Note on Three Equations for Consciousness
    1 July 17, 2020 A note on three equations for consciousness Alberto Montare Department of Psychology William Paterson University keyworDs: total human consciousness; primary consciousness; secondary consciousness; cosmological psychology. ________ Author may be contacteD at: [email protected] Paper may be cited as: http://hDl.hanDle.net./20.500.12164/3025. 2 Abstract Three new metatheoretical equations for total human consciousness, primary consciousness anD seconDary consciousness are presented. These equations are based on five fundamental entities underlying cosmic evolution: energy, matter, life, minD anD culture. It is hopeD that these equations may have some heuristic value for those workers who wish to appreciate the psychological process of consciousness as an integral part of the whole big picture of cosmic evolution. 3 A note on three equations for consciousness This note presents three metatheoretical equations for human consciousness that Describe: (1) total human consciousness (THC); (2) primary consciousness (PC); anD, (3) seconDary consciousness (SC). These equations are presented in terms of five funDamental, metatheoretical, third-person, psychological intervening variables that interact within human psyches to generate consciousness. The five funDamental variables chosen were: energy, matter, life, minD anD culture. The fundamental principle adopted in this work is that these five entities emerged as the basic interactive realities of cosmic evolution anD that each entity became a part of a new interaction term as the evolutionary antecedent for the neXt higher level of organization. This work is metatheoretical in the sense that it is presenteD here unDer the following Definition that is my combination of the Definitions for ‘metapsychology’ anD for ‘metatheory’ contained in the APA Dictionary of Psychology (2015, p.646): metatheoretical a higher-order theory about theories that involves a concern for the fundamental underlying principles and entities of any psychology.
    [Show full text]
  • Primary and Secondary Consciousness II
    Primary and secondary consciousness – Part 2 1 Feb. 28, 2021 (Documents) On the psychology of primary and secondary consciousness: Part 2 Alberto Montare Department of Psychology William Paterson University ________ Author may be contacted at: [email protected]. Primary and secondary consciousness – Part 2 2 Abstract In this second paper on the psychology of endogenous primary and exogenous secondary consciousness, the differential natures and functions of each of these two levels of consciousness previously examined by Montare (1996, 2000, 2019) were further elaborated. Primary consciousness and secondary consciousness were further examined in this paper as naturally- emergent, psychological-level systems that arise within the hierarchical, metatheoretical cosmological evolutionary framework of five fundamental entities and their interactions: energy (Stage 1); energy-by-matter (Stage 2); energy-by-matter-by-life (Stage 3); energy-by-matter-by-life-by-mind (Stage 4); and, energy-by-matter-by-life-by-mind-by-culture (Stage 5). In this scenario, primary consciousness evolved at Stage 4 and secondary consciousness subsequently emerged at Stage 5. It was suggested that primary consciousness initially arises internally within the individual mind from neuron-to-neuron communications, whereas secondary consciousness initially arises from external, cultural brain-to-brain communications. In conclusion, Summary Table 5 shows an accumulation of 41 distinctions between primary and secondary consciousness drawn from Part 1 (Montare (2019) combined
    [Show full text]
  • “Inner Perception Can Never Become Inner Observation”: Brentano On
    Philosophers’ volume 15, no. 10 1. Introduction Imprint march 2015 Franz Brentano’s Psychologie vom Empirischen Standpunkt has inspired the development of first-order or self-representational theories of consciousness.1 Such theories hold that a mental event or process is conscious if, and only if, it represents itself among other things. For example, Caston (2004, 524) writes: “A perception is directed at itself as “Inner Perception Can Never well as at a perceptible quality in the world.”2 In contrast, higher-order theories of consciousness argue that a mental event or state is conscious if, and only if, there is a distinct mental representation of it — a thought Become Inner Observation”: or a perception — that is non-inferentially arrived at. According to both views, consciousness of a mental phenomenon consists in, broadly speaking, a representation of it. But only the self-representational view Brentano on Awareness and has it that it is intrinsic to a mental phenomenon that it is represented. The higher-order view denies this: a mental phenomenon may be represented by a distinct mental state/event or not. In this paper I will not argue for the self-representational view, but Observation rather explore whether it can be defended against an important objection by developing Brentano’s notion of consciousness “on the side”. Let us start by outlining the objection that calls for a response from the proponent of the self-representational view. The self- representational view is often motivated by saying that it captures how things are for us when we consciously perceive and think.
    [Show full text]