PLUTARCH's READING of XENOPHON* Philip Stadter Among the Great Classical Authors, Xenophon Was Especial

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

PLUTARCH's READING of XENOPHON* Philip Stadter Among the Great Classical Authors, Xenophon Was Especial chapter one ‘STAYING UP LATE’: PLUTARCH’S READING OF XENOPHON* Philip Stadter Among the great classical authors, Xenophon was especially similar to Plutarch. Both men were philosophers, historians, and essayists, civically involved, but outside active government. Xenophon’s exile cut him of from Athenian political life, as Plutarch’s provincial Greek background did from a Roman career. Both made friends with those in power and both wrote at length about foreign cultures, Xenophon on Sparta and Persia, Plutarch on Rome. Both wrote history with an essentially didactic and ethical pur- pose, and found in historical exempla a pleasing device to reach a wider non-philosophical audience. The manner in which Plutarch appropriated Xenophon’s works as he was writing his own is a particularly signi cant example of how imperial Greek authors related to their classical past. Close study of his citations of or allusions to Xenophon reveals how the classical Athenian’s works were received and understood under the Flavians and Trajan. At the same time we can learn how Plutarch and his cultured readers, both Roman and Greek, rede ned their heritage in asserting their own identity and their new position in a Greco-Roman empire. Xenophon was much admired in the second-century Greek revival.1 Arrian took his works as the models for many of his own, and became known as the new Xenophon, using Xenophon as his own name in some of his works. In the Atticist revival Xenophon was an important stylistic canon, although never as highly regarded as Demosthenes or Plato. However, Dio Chrysostom presents his works as those most useful for the politician: ‘I think he alone of the ancients can satisfy all the requirements of a πολιτικὸς ἀνήρ’ (18.14). His works, Dio asserts, ofer models for every sort of speech, whether military or political, and his persuasive simplicity seems almost * I am grateful for the comments of Roberto Nicolai, Robin Water eld, and Guido Sche- pens on the oral version of this paper, and for the stimulating atmosphere of the Liverpool conference. 1 See Münscher 1920, Tuplin 1993: 22–29, 189–192, and Swain 1996, index s.v. Xenophon. 44 philip stadter enchantment (γοητεία). The treatise On plain speech (περὶ ἀφελοῦς λόγου) attributed to Aelius Aristides considers Xenophon the paragon of the plain style, and cites him over 130 times, referring to six works.2 There is no doubt that Plutarch also appreciated Xenophon’s style, for he includes him among those who write history with force and charm (δύναµις καὶ χάρις) along with Herodotus and Homer and celebrates the joy of read- ing their accounts. He likes to quote particularly striking phrases, such as that describing Ephesus as ‘war’s workshop’ (πολέµου ἐργαστήριον), and will occasionally refer to the stylistic efectiveness of Xenophon’s presentation.3 Plutarch’s stylistic debt to Xenophon is a topic better suited for another occasion. However, one can observe that while Plutarch did not believe in the somewhat mindless imitation urged in On plain speech,4 he sought and achieved charm and delight in narrative reminiscent of Xenophon. Although his sentences are generally longer and contain more subordinate clauses,5 his artistry and delight in anecdotes, character portrayal, vivid nar- rative, and unusual word choice recall Xenophon’s. Plutarch’s numerous quotations and allusions indicate his thorough familiarity with Xenophon’s works. He cites or refers to Xenophon by name on some fty occasions, thirty-one of which are in the Moral Essays, four- teen in the Parallel Lives (including nine in the Agesilaus and the accom- panying syncrisis), and ve in Artaxerxes. Within the Moral Essays, Table Talk employs Xenophon most extensively, with eight named references. The range of titles referred to includes all the major works (Hellenica, Anaba- sis, Cyropaedia, and Memorabilia) and many of the shorter ones (Agesilaus, Symposium, Oeconomicus, Cynegeticus, and Spartan Constitution). Memo- rable quotes from Xenophon, drawn from four diferent works, ornament the rst few sentences of no fewer than ve of Plutarch’s Moral Essays, 2 That is, Anabasis, Memorabilia, Cyropaedia, Agesilaus, Symposium, and Cynegeticus. The same passages may be cited repeatedly for diferent purposes. Most of the examples are drawn from the beginnings of works—Ages. 1, Symp. 1, 2, Cyr. 1.1, Mem. 1.1, 1.2, An. 1.1, 1.2— although occasionally other passages are referred to. The work never refers to the Hellenica or to other minor works, except, surprisingly, the Cynegeticus, which is cited four times, three from the rst chapter. Rutherford 1998: 124–153, ofers a translation of Schmid’s 1926 Teubner text. He discusses Xenophon as a canon for the plain style (64–79). 3 Herodotus and Homer: Non posse suaviter 1093B. War’s workshop: Marc. 21.3, from Hell. 3.4.17. Stylistic efectiveness: Artax. 8.1, referring to An. 1.8. 4 De prof. in virt. 79D criticizes those interested only in ‘Attic purity’ (τὸ καθαρόν τε καὶ ᾽Αττικὸν) in Plato and Xenophon. 5 Yaginuma 1992, 4728, notes that in samples of either author, Plutarch’s sentences average 22 words, Xenophon’s 15. Occasional sentences in Plutarch can be very long, 90 words or more..
Recommended publications
  • Keeping Tradition Alive: Just War and Historical Imagination Cian O’Driscoll
    Journal of Global Security Studies, 3(2), 2018, 234–247 doi: 10.1093/jogss/ogy003 Research Article Keeping Tradition Alive: Just War and Historical Imagination Cian O’Driscoll University of Glasgow Abstract The just war tradition is one of the key constituencies of international political theory, and its vocab- ulary plays a prominent role in how political and military leaders frame contemporary conflicts. Yet, it stands in danger of turning in on itself and becoming irrelevant. This article argues that scholars who wish to preserve the vitality of this tradition must think in a more open-textured fashion about its historiography. One way to achieve this is to problematize the boundaries of the tradition. This article pursues this objective by treating one figure that stands in a liminal relation to the just war tradition. Despite having a lot to say about the ethics of war, Xenophon is seldom acknowledged as a bona fide just war thinker. The analysis presented here suggests, however, that his writings have much to tell us, not only about how he and his contemporaries thought about the ethics of war, but about how just war thinking is understood (and delimited) today and how it might be revived as a pluralistic critical enterprise. Keywords: just war, ancient Greece, Xenophon, historiography, changing character of war “The past is a different country, they do things differ- its totality, as a rolling story, rather than as an index of ently there.” discrete individuated contributions (Johnson 2009, 252). L. P. Hartley Proponents of this
    [Show full text]
  • Anton Powell, Nicolas Richer (Eds.), Xenophon and Sparta, the Classical Press of Wales, Swansea 2020, 378 Pp.; ISBN 978-1-910589-74-8
    ELECTRUM * Vol. 27 (2020): 213–216 doi:10.4467/20800909EL.20.011.12801 www.ejournals.eu/electrum Anton Powell, Nicolas Richer (eds.), Xenophon and Sparta, The Classical Press of Wales, Swansea 2020, 378 pp.; ISBN 978-1-910589-74-8 The reviewed book is a collection of twelve papers, previously presented at the confe- rence organised by École Normale Supérieure in Lyon in 2006. According to the edi- tors, this is a first volume in the planned series dealing with sources of Spartan his- tory. The books that follow this will deal with the presence of this topic in works by Thucydides, Herodotus, Plutarch, and in archaeological material. The decision to start the cycle from Xenophon cannot be considered as surprising; this ancient author has not only written about Sparta, but also had opportunities to visit the country, person- ally met a number of its officials (including king Agesilaus), and even sent his own sons for a Spartan upbringing. Thus his writings are widely considered as our best source to the history of Sparta in the classical age. Despite this, Xenophon’s literary work remains the subject of numerous controver- sies in discussions among modern scholars. The question of his objectivity is especial- ly problematic and the views about the strong partisanship of Xenophon prevailed for a long time; allegedly, he was depicting Sparta and king Agesilaus in a possibly overly positive light, even omitting inconvenient information.1 In the second half of the 20th century such opinion has been met with a convincing polemic, clearly seen in the works of H.
    [Show full text]
  • Xenophon's Theory of Moral Education Ix
    Xenophon’s Theory of Moral Education Xenophon’s Theory of Moral Education By Houliang Lu Xenophon’s Theory of Moral Education By Houliang Lu This book first published 2015 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2015 by Houliang Lu All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-4438-6880-9 ISBN (13): 978-1-4438-6880-8 TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements ................................................................................... vii Editions ..................................................................................................... viii Introduction ................................................................................................. 1 Part I: Background of Xenophon’s Thought on Moral Education Chapter One ............................................................................................... 13 Xenophon’s View of His Time Chapter Two .............................................................................................. 41 Influence of Socrates on Xenophon’s Thought on Moral Education Part II: A Systematic Theory of Moral Education from a Social Perspective Chapter One ..............................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • BRUCE LAFORSE, Praising Agesilaus: the Limits of Panhellenic
    Praising Agesilaus: the Limits of Panhellenic Rhetoric Bruce Laforse Shortly after the death of the Spartan king Agesilaus c. 360, Xenophon wrote an encomium of his old friend and patron. As one of the two kings in the unique Spartan dual kingship, Agesilaus had played a crucial role from 400 to 360 BC, a period which saw Sparta both rise to the pinnacle of power and then collapse. The Agesilaus is one of the earliest surviving examples of a prose work written in praise of an historical figure.1 In such an encomium the object was not to present a strictly accurate portrait of the subject; rather it was to praise his character, glorify his achievements and, on the other hand, to anticipate or defend against any potential detractors.2 Omission, exaggeration and bending of the truth were not only allowed but, indeed, expected. Its purpose, therefore, was far different from that of a modern biography; nor, despite the idealization of the subject’s character, did it attempt primarily to uplift and instruct, as did Plutarch’s later moralizing biographies, by presenting positive and negative models to emulate or avoid.3 It was designed to praise, to put the best possible face on the subject’s life, career, background and character.4 It is not, then, strictly speaking, a work of history, and thus scholars must exercise caution when using it as an historical source.5 Supplying conclusive proof that Xenophon himself regarded the purpose of the Agesilaus as fundamentally different from history is the fact that he wrote a much fuller and (comparatively) more balanced account of Agesilaus’ career in the Hellenica, his history of the years 411 to 362.6 The two works date to the same period, and share, with very minor alterations, a number of passages.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Xenophon Poroi 5
    ORE Open Research Exeter TITLE Xenophon Poroi 5: Securing a ‘More Just’ Athenian Hegemony AUTHORS Farrell, CA JOURNAL Polis: The Journal for Ancient Greek Political Thought DEPOSITED IN ORE 03 March 2016 This version available at http://hdl.handle.net/10871/20403 COPYRIGHT AND REUSE Open Research Exeter makes this work available in accordance with publisher policies. A NOTE ON VERSIONS The version presented here may differ from the published version. If citing, you are advised to consult the published version for pagination, volume/issue and date of publication Xenophon Poroi 5: Securing a ‘More Just’ Athenian Hegemony Abstract: The present study examines section five of Poroi and Xenophon’s proposal to restore the reputation of Athens. After outlining his plan for ‘justly’ supplying the dēmos with sufficient sustenance in Poroi 1-4, section 5 addresses the desire to regain hegemony after Athens had lost the Social War. Xenophon does not adopt an anti-imperialist stance; instead he seeks to re-align imperial aspirations with Athenian ideals and earlier paradigms for securing hegemony. Xenophon’s ideas in Poroi are contextualized with consideration for his ‘Socratic’ distinction between tyranny and kingship, as well as his wider advice for ruling well. It is shown that his proposals for securing the consent of the allies reiterates ideas that Xenophon outlines across his corpus, especially Hiero and Cyropaedia. In Poroi Xenophon therefore applies his political thought in an attempt to re-direct Athenian ambitions away from policies that prompted charges of being a ‘tyrant polis’ and towards ‘legitimate rule’. Keywords: Xenophon; Poroi; imperialism/hegemony; Social War In 2009 Dustin Gish and Wayne Ambler co-edited a volume of Polis devoted to Xenophon.
    [Show full text]
  • The Manuscripts of Xenophon's "Symposium" , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 34:2 (1993:Summer) P.187
    CIRIGNANO, JOHN, The Manuscripts of Xenophon's "Symposium" , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 34:2 (1993:Summer) p.187 The Manuscripts of Xenophon's Symposium John Cirignano CENT SCHOLARSHIP has produced a clearer picture of the Krelationships among manuscripts of certain opuscula of Xenophon. 1 These shorter works have been shown to belong to two distinct families: one headed by Vaticanus gr. 1335 (A), the other by a lost hyparchetype, Cl>. In this paper I examine and interrelate manuscripts containing Xenophon's Symposium, a work found only in the manuscripts of the second family. The twenty-three manuscripts described here contain a total of twenty-five Symp. texts, seven of which are incomplete.2 Three of the four groups of the <l> family of Symp. 1 Agesilaus: R. WIECZOREK, Xenophon 's Agesilaus: A Collation, Stemma, and Critical Text (diss. University of Iowa 1975 [Ann Arbor 1975: hereafter 'Wieczorek']); Hiero: J. K. DEULING and]. CiRIGNANO, "A Reappraisal of the Later ABS Family Tradition of Xenophon's [fiero," Scriptorium 44 (1990: 'Deuling and Cirignano') 54-68; D. O. Haltinner and E. A. Schmoll, "The Older Manuscripts of Xenophon's Hiero, " RHText 10 (1980) 231-36; L. LEVERENZ, "The Descendants of Laurentianus 80.13 in Xenophon's Hiero," StIt 7 (1989: 'Leverenz') 12-23; Memorabilia: M. BANDINI, "Osservazioni sulla storia del testo dei Memorabili di Senofonte in eta umanistica," StCIOr (1988: 'Bandini, "Osservazioni''') 271-92, and "I Memorabili di Senofante fra il Bessarione, Isidoro di Kiev, e Pier Vettori," BollClass 12 (1991: 'Bandini, "Mem. "') 83-92; lIipparchicus: D. F. JACKSON, "A New Look at the Manuscripts of Xenophon's Hipparchicus," CQ N.S.
    [Show full text]
  • Xenophon's Virtue Personified
    Kentron Revue pluridisciplinaire du monde antique 32 | 2016 Approches historiennes des images (I) Xenophon’s Virtue Personified Nili Alon Amit Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/kentron/855 DOI: 10.4000/kentron.855 ISSN: 2264-1459 Publisher Presses universitaires de Caen Printed version Date of publication: 31 December 2016 Number of pages: 137-150 ISBN: 978-2-84133-840-5 ISSN: 0765-0590 Electronic reference Nili Alon Amit, « Xenophon’s Virtue Personified », Kentron [Online], 32 | 2016, Online since 10 May 2017, connection on 16 November 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/kentron/855 ; DOI : https:// doi.org/10.4000/kentron.855 Kentron is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 International License. XENOPHON’S VIRTUE PERSONIFIED Some elements in man’s nature make for friendship. […] For thanks to their virtue (διὰ γὰρ τὴν ἀρετήν) these prize the untroubled security of moderate possessions above sovereignty won by war; despite hunger and thirst, they can share their food and drink without a pang; and although they delight in the charms of beauty they can resist the lure and avoid offending those whom they should respect (Xenophon, Mem. 2.6.21-22, Socrates on friendship) 1. In the above quotation Socrates explains to Critobulus that friendship is created and sustained through the virtues of friends. Virtue (arete) is said to enable friendship; but it is described in terms that, as we shall see, are not case-specific but common to all instances of arete in Xenophon’s writings: in other places it is security or self-preservation which is gained through virtue, which is described as moderation, endurance, and self restraint.
    [Show full text]
  • Andrew G. Scott, Leadership, Valor, and Spartan Death in Battle in Xenophon's Hellenica
    The Ancient History Bulletin VOLUME TWENTY-NINE: 2015 NUMBERS 3-4 Edited by: Edward Anson ò Michael Fronda òDavid Hollander Timothy Howe òJoseph Roisman ò John Vanderspoel Pat Wheatley ò Sabine Müller ISSN 0835-3638 ANCIENT HISTORY BULLETIN Volume 29 (2015) Numbers 3-4 Edited by: Edward Anson, Michael Fronda, David Hollander, Sabine Müller, Joseph Roisman, John Vanderspoel, Pat Wheatley Senior Editor: Timothy Howe Editorial correspondents Elizabeth Baynham, Hugh Bowden, Franca Landucci Gattinoni, Alexander Meeus, Kurt Raaflaub, P.J. Rhodes, Robert Rollinger, Victor Alonso Troncoso Contents of volume twenty-nine Numbers 3-4 91 Benjamin Scolnic, The Villages of the Carians in Diodorus Siculus and Seleucus I’s Route to Babylon in the Winter of 312/311 B.C.E. 115 Andrew G. Scott, Leadership, Valor, and Spartan Death in Battle in Xenophon's Hellenica 134 Guglielmo Bagella, Il Metodo Compositivo di Plutarco per la Vita di Crasso 157 Alexander Yakobson, Cicero, the Constitution and the Roman People NOTES TO CONTRIBUTORS AND SUBSCRIBERS The Ancient History Bulletin was founded in 1987 by Waldemar Heckel, Brian Lavelle, and John Vanderspoel. The board of editorial correspondents consists of Elizabeth Baynham (University of Newcastle), Hugh Bowden (Kings College, London), Franca Landucci Gattinoni (Università Cattolica, Milan), Alexander Meeus (University of Leuven), Kurt Raaflaub (Brown University), P.J. Rhodes (Durham University), Robert Rollinger (Universität Innsbruck), Victor Alonso Troncoso (Universidade da Coruña) AHB is currently edited by: Timothy Howe (Senior Editor: [email protected]), Edward Anson, Michael Fronda, David Hollander, Sabine Müller, Joseph Roisman, John Vanderspoel and Pat Wheatley. AHB promotes scholarly discussion in Ancient History and ancillary fields (such as epigraphy, papyrology, and numismatics) by publishing articles and notes on any aspect of the ancient world from the Near East to Late Antiquity.
    [Show full text]
  • Xenophon's Hellenica
    chapter three Xenophon’s Hellenica enophon’s Hellenica is notorious for omissions of fact and inequali- Xties of treatment.1 These flaws could be explained by the theory that Xenophon wrote different sections at different times, without fully unify- ing it as a whole. Nevertheless, the Hellenica is coherent as it stands, and Xenophon is certainly consistent in his views on moral virtue through- out; I therefore treat it as a unified whole.2 In the past, the facile explana- 1. Unless otherwise specified, all references to Xenophon in this chapter are from the Hellenica. 2. It is a longstanding debate whether or not Xenophon wrote his Hellenica as a continu- ous whole, in view of the distinctive differences between 1–2.3.10 in particular and the rest of the work. The definitive expression of the “analysts’” viewpoint, that Xenophon composed the different sections of the Hellenica at different times, is that of Malcolm MacLaren (“On the Composition of Xenophon’s Hellenica,” AJP 55 [1934]: 121–39, 249–62). The strong- est arguments for the opposite camp, the “unitarians,” who believe that Xenophon composed the Hellenica as a unified whole, are made by W. P. Henry (Greek Historical Writing: A Historiographical Essay Based on Xenophon’s Hellenica [Chicago: Argonaut, 1967]). Because Xenophon must have written much of the Hellenica long before the time of the Battle of Mantinea (the last event contained in this work), there are necessarily slight variations in language and expression. These need not, however, obscure the essential unity of the work in purpose and methods; see also W.
    [Show full text]
  • Xenophon's Psychology of Philotimia
    Xenophon’s Psychology of Philotimia Rodrigo Illarraga N XENOPHON’S HIERO, the poet Simonides and the tyrant Hiero discuss the difference between the lives of laymen and I rulers.1 For much of the dialogue (Hier. 1–7), they seek to identify how rulers and those who are ruled experience differ- ently joy and sorrow. While Simonides holds the common opinion that rulers have pleasant lives, Hiero points out that this idea is the product of a false impression, and in reality rulers have the worst possible lives. From the beginning of the dialogue, both characters agree on a simple characterization of the sensations experienced by any individual (1.4). Pleasure and pain are the basic sensations that organize life and can be experienced by the body, the psykhe, or both at the same time (1.5). An interesting debate develops from this agreement. For Simonides, what distinguishes the ruler is his easy access to pleasure (1.8). However, Hiero points out that these things that are understood by Simonides as pleasure are 1 V. Gray, “Xenophon’s Hiero and the Meeting of the Wise Man and Tyrant in Greek Literature,” CQ 36 (1986) 117, has pointed out that “the ideals of the Hiero are Xenophon’s own and he is using the dialogue as a vehicle for their expression.” She holds (123) that Hiero’s innovative literary form answers Xenophon’s intention to present what he understands as a more broad and complete image about tyranny. R. Illarraga, “Note sulla forme della monarchia in Senofonte,” Magazzino di Filosofia 32 (2018) 50–60, holds that Xenophon does not understand tyranny and monarchy as fixed categories, but as one complex continuum that comprehends a more broad notion of rulers.
    [Show full text]
  • This Thesis Has Been Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for a Postgraduate Degree (E.G. Phd, Mphil, Dclinpsychol) at the University of Edinburgh
    This thesis has been submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for a postgraduate degree (e.g. PhD, MPhil, DClinPsychol) at the University of Edinburgh. Please note the following terms and conditions of use: • This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights, which are retained by the thesis author, unless otherwise stated. • A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. • This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author. • The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author. • When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given. Xenophon’s Theory of Moral Education Houliang Lu PhD in Classics University of Edinburgh 2014 Acknowledgement This thesis cannot be completed without the help of many people. First of all, I express my profound gratitude to my supervisors, Prof. Douglas Cairns and Prof. Andrew Erskine, for their careful correction and valuable advice for my thesis. I should also thank my former supervisor, Prof. Xiaoling Guo in Beijing Normal University as well as Prof. Shaoxiang Yan in Capital Normal University of Beijing, whose support and recommendation enable me to do my PhD program in University of Edinburgh. Besides, I am very grateful to the Chinese Scholarships Council and the University of Edinburgh, whose funding covers my tuition fee as well as my living expenses, so that I can finish my PhD programme in Edinburgh much more easily.
    [Show full text]
  • Aspects of Leadership in Xenophon
    ASPECTS OF LEADERSHIP IN XENOPHON HISTOS The Online Journal of Ancient Historiography Edited by Christopher Krebs and †John Moles Histos Supplements Supervisory Editor: John Marincola '. Antony Erich Raubitschek, Autobiography of Antony Erich Raubitschek . Edited with Introduction and Notes by Donald Lateiner (-.'/). -. A. J. Woodman, Lost Histories: Selected Fragments of Roman Historical Writers (-.'3). 4. Felix Jacoby, On the Development of Greek Historiography and the Plan for a New Collection of the Fragments of the Greek Historians . Translated by Mortimer Chambers and Stefan Schorn (-.'3). /. Anthony Ellis, ed., God in History: Reading and Re- writing Herodotean Theology from Plutarch to the Renaissance (-.'3). 3. Richard Fernando Buxton, ed., Aspects of Leadership in Xenophon (-.'8) ASPECTS OF LEADERSHIP IN XENOPHON EDITED BY RICHARD FERNANDO BUXTON HISTOS SUPPLEMENT 3 NEWCASTLE UPON TYNE - . ' 8 Published by H I S T O S School of History, Classics and Archaeology, Newcastle University, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE' <RU, United Kingdom ISSN (Online): -./8-3>84 (Print): -./8-3>33 © -.'8 THE INDIVIDUAL CONTRIBUTORS TABLE OF CONTENTS Preface ............................................................................... i About the Contributors ................................................... iii '. Athenian Leaders in Xenophon’s Memorabilia Melina Tamiolaki ............................................................ ' -. Tyrants as Impious Leaders in Xenophon’s Hellenica Frances Pownall ............................................................
    [Show full text]