The Liar Paradox and the Letter to Titus

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Liar Paradox and the Letter to Titus The Liar Paradox and the Letter to Titus PATRICK GRAY Rhodes College Memphis, TN 38112 ODYSSEUS WAS, BY REPUTATION, an exceptionally good liar (Plato Hipp. min. 364C-E). His habit of telling tales is a necessary survival skill as he makes his way home from the Trojan War.1 The habit proves hard to kick when he finally reaches Ithaca. In his encounters in the second half of the Odyssey with Eumaeus the loyal swineherd and with Penelope, his long-suffering wife, he does not immediately reveal his true identity but rather claims to be a man of Crete. This disguise is fit­ ting in light of the widely held opinion that Cretans were persistent prevaricators.2 Homer's choice of disguise for Odysseus may in fact be the earliest evidence for this reputation. So pervasive is this view of Crete that it finds its way into the pages of the NT. The author of the Letter to Titus describes the local population as ''always liars, evil beasts, lazy gluttons" (1:12), a characterization he conveniently borrows from one of their own. Whereas the commentary tradition has paid close attention to the negative stereotype of Cretans, one other aspect of its deployment has frequently escaped notice. When the author quotes "one of their own prophets" indicting Cre­ tans as "always liars" and then proceeds to remark that "this testimony is true," he in essence reproduces one of the most (in)famous antinomies of the ancient world. 1 See Adele J. Haft, "Odysseus, Idomeneus and Menones: The Cretan Lies oí Odyssey 13-19," CJ19 (1984) 289-306. 2 In Greek, "to play the Cretan" (Κρητίζειν) means "'to lie" (Plutarch A em. 23.6: Lys. 20.2). Their claim to be the site of the tomb of Zeus leads Callimachus {Hymn. 1.8-9) and many writers thereafter to label the Cretans a race of liars (cf. Lucían Phìlops 3; Tun. 6): see also Reggie M. Kidd. 'Titus as Apologia Grace for Liars, Beasts, and Bellies," HBT 21 (1999) 185-209. esp. 191- 97. 302 THE LIAR PARADOX AND THE LETTER TO TITUS 303 If Cretans are always liars, and if the speaker—usually identified as Epimenides3— is a Cretan, then he must be a liar. And if he is a liar, then his "testimony" cannot be true. On the other hand, if it is true that Cretans are always liars, then his testi­ mony corresponds to the facts of the case and he is not lying. But this would mean that not all Cretans are lying all the time, which would mean that the beginning premise was false. So if he is lying, then he is telling the truth (when he says that Cretans are always liars); and if he is telling the truth, then he must be lying (since he himself disproves the stated rule that Cretans are always liars). Logicians refer to this state of affairs as a paradox. In various forms this particular paradox was known in antiquity as the Liar (ό ψευδόμενος).4 Is the author oblivious to the logical and rhetorical havoc he has wrought?5 3 Clement of Alexandria is the first Christian writer to identify the speaker in Titus 1:12 as Epi­ menides {Strom. 1.59.2; cf. Jerome Comm. Tit 7). The original source of the hexameter verse quoted by the author of Titus is likely the Theogony or the Chresmoi of Epimenides; see J. Rendei Harris, "The Cretans Are Always Liars," Expositor 7, no. 2 (1906) 305-17; idem, "St. Paul and Epimenides," Expositor 15, no. 1 (1915) 29-35; and Robert Renehan, "Classical Greek Quotations in the New Testament," in The Heritage of the Early Church (ed. David Neiman and Margaret A. Schatkin; Orientalia Christiana Analecta 195; Rome: Pontificium Institutum Studiorum Orientalium, 1973) 35. G. M. Lee ("Epimenides in the Epistle to Titus [1:12]," NovT22 [1980] 96; cf. G. L. Huxley, Greek Epic Poetry [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1969] 81-82), however, believes that the remark originated as a reply made to Epimenides by the Pythoness at Delphi, which later came to be included among the sayings of the Cretan seer. Jerome D. Quinn {The Letter to Titus: A new translation with notes and commentary and an introduction to Titus, I and II Timothy, the Pastoral Epistles [AB 35; New York: Doubleday, 1990] 108) believes that the author is quoting from an anthology that circulated in the Hellenistic period. For the legends surrounding the life of Epi­ menides, whom Plato calls a "divine man" {Leg. 1.642D-F), see Diog. Laert. 1.109-15. 4 Modern logicians frequently use "Liar Paradox" and "Epimenides Paradox" interchange­ ably (incorrectly so, according to Christoph Zimmer, "Die Lügner-Antinomie in Titus 1,12," LB 59 [1987] 77-99, esp. 85-92). Brief introductions to the problem may be found in A. N. Prior, "Epi­ menides the Cretan," Journal of Symbolic Logic 23 (1958) 261-66; and Alan Ross Anderson, "St. Paul's Epistle to Titus," in The Paradox of the Liar (ed. Robert L. Martin; New Haven: Yale Uni­ versity Press, 1970) 1-11. Richard L. Kirkham provides an overview of the proposed solutions {The­ ories of Truth [Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992] 271-306). The most comprehensive treatment of the Liar in antiquity is that of Alexander Rüstow, Der Lügner. Theorie/Geschichte und Auflösung (Leipzig: Teubner, 1910) 17-102. For a survey of the discussion among medieval Islamic com­ mentators, see Larry B. Miller, "A Brief History of the Liar Paradox," in Of Scholars, Savants, and Their Texts (ed. Ruth Link-Salinger; New York: Peter Lang, 1989) 173-82. Paul Vincent Spade treats the problem as it appears in Christian Scholastic texts ("The Origins of the Mediaeval Insolubilia Literature," Franciscan Studies 33 [1973] 292-309). The secondary literature dealing with the Liar and with related paradoxes of self-reference such as the Burali-Forti Paradox and Russell's Paradox is enormous and still growing; see Martin, Paradox of the Liar, 135-49; and, most recently, the bib­ liography in Elke Brendel, Die Wahrheit über den Lügner: Eine philosophisch-logische Analyse der Antinomie des Lügners (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1992). 5 This would appear to be the case when the psalmist, in 116:11, declares, "I said in my haste 'All men are liars'" {KJV; cf. JPS). Whereas the psalmist belongs to the class of "all men," he has indeed spoken hastily. The rendering of the RSV removes the contradiction ("I said in my conster- 304 THE CATHOLIC BIBLICAL QUARTERLY | 69,2007 Or was it his intention all along to fall into this conundrum? My aim in this essay is to test the hypothesis that the author is indeed aware of the contradiction by (1) examining the function and status of logical paradoxes in antiquity and (2) set­ ting the passage within the context of the pervasive paraenetic concerns about talk­ ativeness, taciturnity, and propriety in speech here and elsewhere in the Pastoral Epistles. I. The Liar Paradox in Greco-Roman Antiquity If the author (be it Paul or someone writing in his name) is acquainted with the paradox, there are two possible explanations: Either he has encountered it directly, in some form or other, in the course of his schooling, or the paradox has already become part and parcel of Mediterranean cultural literacy in the first cen­ tury.6 Because it would be extremely difficult—in the absence of an explicit ref­ erence—to demonstrate beyond all doubt that the author had studied the Liar in some sort of formal manner, in practical terms these two possibilities stand at two points along a common continuum. Discussions of the Liar Paradox appear frequently in both technical and pop­ ular literature produced in the Hellenistic period as well as in the centuries fol­ lowing its purported appropriation in Titus. The Liar looms particularly large in the philosophical literature. Eubulides of Miletus, widely known as a critic of Aristotle and as the teacher of Demosthenes, is said to have formulated a number of classic logic problems such as the Liar, on account of which he became the butt of jokes by the comic poets (Diog. Laert. 2.108). Aristotle's successor as the head of the Lyceum, Theophrastus, wrote three books on the Liar (Diog. Laert. 5.49).7 It was common knowledge, however, that the Stoics were the specialists in this and other paradoxes (Cicero Div. 2 A Al; Fin. 4.4.8; Diog. Laert. 7.44).8 Chrysippus, who nation, 'Men are all a vain hope"'), but the XRSV restores it ("I said in my consternation, 'Every­ one is a liar'"). 6 Contemporary examples of paradoxes familiar to the general public might include: Which came first, the chicken or the egg? If God is omnipotent, can God create a rock so big that he is unable to lift it? What happens when an irresistible force meets at immovable object? If a tree falls in the forest and no one is present to hear it, does it make a sound? Can a man travel back in time and change history in such a way (e.g., by killing his own grandfather before his grandfather met his grandmother) that he would prevent himself from being born? Some of these puzzles are not, strictly speaking, paradoxes, but they are the type of logical conundrums that are well known and that nonspecialists regard as, at best, idle curiosities. "Aristotle himself anticipates its main lines in Soph el. 180a32, 180b2-7; see Joseph M. Bochenski, Ancient Formal Logic (Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1957) 101. 8 Cicero devotes an entire treatise to the Paradoxa Stoicorum.
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy and the Foreigner in Plato's Dialogues
    Philosophy and the Foreigner in Plato’s Dialogues By Rebecca LeMoine A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Political Science) at the UNIVERSITY OF WISCONSIN-MADISON 2014 Date of final oral examination: 06/20/2014 The dissertation is approved by the following members of the Final Oral Committee: Richard Avramenko, Associate Professor, Political Science Alex Dressler, Assistant Professor, Classics Daniel Kapust, Associate Professor, Political Science Helen Kinsella, Associate Professor, Political Science John Zumbrunnen, Professor, Political Science i ABSTRACT The place of foreigners in Plato’s thought remains understudied despite the prevalence of foreign characters, myths, and practices throughout his dialogues. Attending to this gap in the scholarly literature, this dissertation challenges conventional depictions of Plato as hostile to diversity by showing that Plato makes a compelling case for why we should engage with foreigners: the epistemological benefits of cross-cultural engagement. Through exegetical readings of the Republic, Laws, Phaedrus, and Menexenus, I argue that Plato finds cross-cultural dialogue epistemologically beneficial owing to its ability to provoke us to philosophize together, an activity at once conducive to the quest for wisdom and generative of friendship. Put simply, conversations with foreigners perform the same role as the Socratic gadfly of stinging us into consciousness. This finding has major implications for the field of political theory and, specifically, for the role of the new subfield commonly referred to as comparative political theory. By demonstrating the centrality of cross-cultural dialogue to Plato’s conception of political theory, this dissertation suggests that comparative political theory is not a deviation from the tradition of Western political theory, but a restoration of it.
    [Show full text]
  • The Liar Paradox As a Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument
    University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3 May 15th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM The Liar Paradox as a reductio ad absurdum argument Menashe Schwed Ashkelon Academic College Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Schwed, Menashe, "The Liar Paradox as a reductio ad absurdum argument" (1999). OSSA Conference Archive. 48. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA3/papersandcommentaries/48 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Title: The Liar Paradox as a Reductio ad Absurdum Author: Menashe Schwed Response to this paper by: Lawrence Powers (c)2000 Menashe Schwed 1. Introduction The paper discusses two seemingly separated topics: the origin and function of the Liar Paradox in ancient Greek philosophy and the Reduction ad absurdum mode of argumentation. Its goal is to show how the two topics fit together and why they are closely connected. The accepted tradition is that Eubulides of Miletos was the first to formulate the Liar Paradox correctly and that the paradox was part of the philosophical discussion of the Megarian School. Which version of the paradox was formulated by Eubulides is unknown, but according to some hints given by Aristotle and an incorrect version given by Cicero1, the version was probably as follows: The paradox is created from the Liar sentence ‘I am lying’.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Referential Problems in Mathematics
    Michigan Law Review Volume 90 Issue 5 1992 Some Lesson About the Law From Self-Referential Problems in Mathematics John M. Rogers University of Kentucky Robert E. Molzon University of Kentucky Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr Part of the Mathematics Commons, and the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation John M. Rogers & Robert E. Molzon, Some Lesson About the Law From Self-Referential Problems in Mathematics, 90 MICH. L. REV. 992 (1992). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol90/iss5/3 This Essay is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Law Review at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ESSAY SOME LESSONS ABOUT THE LAW FROM SELF-REFERENTIAL PROBLEMS IN MATHEMATICS John M. Rogers* and Robert E. Molzon ** If systems of law can be analogized to axiomatic systems of mathe­ matical logic in a tight enough fashion, then some conclusions of twen­ tieth-century mathematicians regarding number theory systems may usefully be applied to legal systems as well. In particular, legal theo­ rists must become comfortable with the incompleteness of legal sys­ tems, no matter how carefully constructed, in the same way that mathematicians and philosophers have become comfortable with the incompleteness of axiomatic systems of number theory. The analogy sheds light on some currently perceived problems with our constitu­ tional system.
    [Show full text]
  • Paradoxes Situations That Seems to Defy Intuition
    Paradoxes Situations that seems to defy intuition PDF generated using the open source mwlib toolkit. See http://code.pediapress.com/ for more information. PDF generated at: Tue, 08 Jul 2014 07:26:17 UTC Contents Articles Introduction 1 Paradox 1 List of paradoxes 4 Paradoxical laughter 16 Decision theory 17 Abilene paradox 17 Chainstore paradox 19 Exchange paradox 22 Kavka's toxin puzzle 34 Necktie paradox 36 Economy 38 Allais paradox 38 Arrow's impossibility theorem 41 Bertrand paradox 52 Demographic-economic paradox 53 Dollar auction 56 Downs–Thomson paradox 57 Easterlin paradox 58 Ellsberg paradox 59 Green paradox 62 Icarus paradox 65 Jevons paradox 65 Leontief paradox 70 Lucas paradox 71 Metzler paradox 72 Paradox of thrift 73 Paradox of value 77 Productivity paradox 80 St. Petersburg paradox 85 Logic 92 All horses are the same color 92 Barbershop paradox 93 Carroll's paradox 96 Crocodile Dilemma 97 Drinker paradox 98 Infinite regress 101 Lottery paradox 102 Paradoxes of material implication 104 Raven paradox 107 Unexpected hanging paradox 119 What the Tortoise Said to Achilles 123 Mathematics 127 Accuracy paradox 127 Apportionment paradox 129 Banach–Tarski paradox 131 Berkson's paradox 139 Bertrand's box paradox 141 Bertrand paradox 146 Birthday problem 149 Borel–Kolmogorov paradox 163 Boy or Girl paradox 166 Burali-Forti paradox 172 Cantor's paradox 173 Coastline paradox 174 Cramer's paradox 178 Elevator paradox 179 False positive paradox 181 Gabriel's Horn 184 Galileo's paradox 187 Gambler's fallacy 188 Gödel's incompleteness theorems
    [Show full text]
  • List of Paradoxes 1 List of Paradoxes
    List of paradoxes 1 List of paradoxes This is a list of paradoxes, grouped thematically. The grouping is approximate: Paradoxes may fit into more than one category. Because of varying definitions of the term paradox, some of the following are not considered to be paradoxes by everyone. This list collects only those instances that have been termed paradox by at least one source and which have their own article. Although considered paradoxes, some of these are based on fallacious reasoning, or incomplete/faulty analysis. Logic • Barbershop paradox: The supposition that if one of two simultaneous assumptions leads to a contradiction, the other assumption is also disproved leads to paradoxical consequences. • What the Tortoise Said to Achilles "Whatever Logic is good enough to tell me is worth writing down...," also known as Carroll's paradox, not to be confused with the physical paradox of the same name. • Crocodile Dilemma: If a crocodile steals a child and promises its return if the father can correctly guess what the crocodile will do, how should the crocodile respond in the case that the father guesses that the child will not be returned? • Catch-22 (logic): In need of something which can only be had by not being in need of it. • Drinker paradox: In any pub there is a customer such that, if he or she drinks, everybody in the pub drinks. • Paradox of entailment: Inconsistent premises always make an argument valid. • Horse paradox: All horses are the same color. • Lottery paradox: There is one winning ticket in a large lottery. It is reasonable to believe of a particular lottery ticket that it is not the winning ticket, since the probability that it is the winner is so very small, but it is not reasonable to believe that no lottery ticket will win.
    [Show full text]
  • A HEURISTIC SEARCH for COMMERCIAL and MANAGEMENT SCIENCE APPLICATIONS By
    A TIFICIAL INTELLIGEN CE- A HEURISTIC SEARCH FOR COMMERCIAL AND MANAGEMENT SCIENCE APPLICATIONS by Philip A. Cooper B.S., Syracuse University (1973) SUBMITTED TO THE ALFRED P. SLOAN SCHOOL OF MANAGEMENT IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF SCIENCE IN MANAGEMENT at the MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY JUNE 1984 1 Philip A. Cooper 1984 The author hereby grants to M.I.T. permission to reDroduce and to distribute copies of this thesis document in whole or in part. Signature of Author:.... ''*--^ P. Sloan School of Management 7 May 4, 1984 Certified by: John Henderson Thesis Supervisor Accepted by Alan F. White Director of Executive Education - 1 - ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE- A HEURISTIC SEARCH FOR COMMERCIAL AND MANAGEMENT SCIENCE APPLICATIONS By PHILIP A. COOPER Submitted to the Alfred P. Sloan School of Management on May 4, 1983 in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Science in Management ABSTRACT This thesis seeks to examine the rapidly growing and influential area of computer science called Artificial Intelligence; with a view towards providing a perspective on the field's: - Historical context - Anthropology and morphology - What may we reasonably expect it to do A businessman's perspective is taken throughout the thesis. The underlying question are: Is the techonology ready to be commercialized and what will the criteria be for successful products. Key issues in Artificial Intelligence are defined and discussed. Prospective product areas are identified, and desireable system attributes are put forth. Finally, moral and ethical question are examined. Thesis Supervisor: John Henderson Title: Associate Professor of Management Science - 2 - Acknowledgements The author would like to express his appreciation to the following people for their special contributions which made this epistle possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Critique of Previous Comprehensive Studies of Self-Referential Paradoxes
    Critique of Previous Comprehensive Studies of Self-referential Paradoxes YAMAMORI Maiko Kyoto University Abstract: The fact that it produces a paradox implies the possibility that a theory or a thought is not entirely rational. At the same time, the possible resolution of paradoxes suggests candidates for the conditions that may make theories or thoughts consistent. Many scholars have investigated paradoxes to find their solutions. The primary approach to a paradox is to consider each solution in turn (the one-by-one approach); studies using this approach have resulted in many diverse solutions, but it is limited by serious problems. Hence, I will adopt another approach, termed here as the comprehensive approach, to consider a general solution or solutions to all paradoxes. Here the focus will be on self-referential paradoxes. A self-referential paradox indicates a paradox that occurs when the subject of a proposition is in part the proposition itself. Further, some paradoxes are not self-referential but seem to be. To preserve the appearances of our intuition of a self-reference, I introduce a categorization of self-references into two types (with two corresponding types of accompanying paradoxes): the first is a narrow self-reference, that is, precisely a reference to itself (this matches the existing characterization). The other type is a broad self-reference or a reference to a group or groups containing itself. In this paper, first, I will examine the works of three figures, Bertrand Russell; Graham Priest; and Martin Pleitz, who take a comprehensive approach: considering the general conditions for self-referential paradoxes, analyzing them, and suggesting general solutions for them.
    [Show full text]
  • Vicious Queues and Vicious Circles
    Asia Pacific Mathematics Newsletter 1 ViciousVicious Queues Queues and and ViciousVicious Circles Circles N Raja N Raja 1. Introduction 2. Paradox and Circularity How wonderful that we have met with a We have to be willing to wrestle with para- paradox. Now we have some hope of making dox in pursuing understanding. progress. — Harold Evans — Niels Bohr This article presents an introduction to some of Paradoxes may be classified into two basic types the fascinating paradoxes that arise in logic and — logical paradoxes and semantic paradoxes. the foundations of mathematics. The study of Logical paradoxes involve notions only from the paradoxes spans a recorded history of nearly two theory of sets. The most well known among the thousand six hundred years of intellectual stud- logical paradoxes is Russell’s paradox [3] from Set ies in philosophy, mathematics, logic, and other theory: disciplines. It is not surprising that the number of The set of all sets that are not members of them- known paradoxes is quite large, and we can only selves is both a member of itself, and also not a member touch upon a tiny fraction of them in this article. of itself. However, we try to discern a pattern even among Other examples of logical paradoxes are Can- the few paradoxes that we do present, and also tor’s paradox and Burali-Forti’s paradox. Unlike point out several connections between paradoxes logical paradoxes, the semantic paradoxes make and the proofs of a number of important theorems use of notions which do not occur in the standard in mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Paradoxes of Intensionality Version Of: March 1, 2007 Dustin Tucker and Richmond H
    Paradoxes of Intensionality Version of: March 1, 2007 Dustin Tucker and Richmond H. Thomason Philosophy Department, University of Michigan Abstract We identify a class of paradoxes that are neither set-theoretical or semantical, but that seem to depend on intensionality. In particular, these paradoxes arise out of plausible properties of propositional attitudes and their objects. We try to explain why logicians have neglected these paradoxes, and to show that, like the Russell Paradox and the direct discourse Liar Paradox, these intensional paradoxes are recalcitrant and challenge logical analysis. Indeed, when we take these paradoxes seriously, we may need to rethink the commonly accepted methods for dealing with the logical paradoxes. 1. Introduction Contemporary work on the paradoxes of logic and set theory is framed by ideas that go back to the 1920s and 1930s. In 1925, Frank Ramsey divided the paradoxes into those (like the Russell Paradox) that arise within mathematics, and those (like the Liar Paradox) that do not. Having made his division of the paradoxes, Ramsey took the Liar and related paradoxes to be extralogical, involving an “empirical” linguistic element. But later, in work published in 1936, Alfred Tarski showed that the Liar Paradox does arise even in rigorously presented semantic theories of formalized languages, making a compelling case that the enterprise of producing these theories belongs to logic. At the same time, he demonstrated how the para- dox could be avoided by relativizing truth to a language and invoking a linguistic hierarchy in which no language could serve as its own semantic metalanguage. These ideas were congenial to the spirit of the times.
    [Show full text]
  • Conditional Antinomies
    CONDITIONAL ANTINOMIES Claudio Pizzi * Abstract: After a short premise about some paradoxical features of counterfactual reasoning, the paper tries to identify the analogues of the so-called Card Paradox and of the Liar antinomy by using a language containing the conditional operator symbolized by >. A first proposal is taken into account but dismissed since the resulting Liar is equivalent to the statement “the present statement is necessarily false”, which makes the corner operator indistinguishable from strict implication. A second proposed solution consists in paraphrasing every statement A into the conditional “I would lie if I said not-A”, where the conditional has the properties of the classical conditional operator. The “Epimenides” and “Truth-Teller” variants of the paradox are also examined in the last section. Keywords: Antinomy. Paradox. Liar. Epimenides. Counterfactuals. Conditionals. *Emeritus Siena University. Born in Milan (Italy) in 1944. Main research interests: Tense Logic, Conditional Logic, Philosophy of Causality, Abductive Reasoning. 19 CONDITIONAL ANTINOMIES . §1. Conditionals have been a source of paradoxes since the beginning of contemporary logic, as it is shown by the so-called paradoxes of material and strict implication. However, their more paradoxical features came out especially after the II World War, along with the first attempts to determine the logical properties of counterfactual conditionals1. It is in itself paradoxical, to begin with, that a contrary-to-fact antecedent has normally two legitimate consequents which are incompatible. For instance, under standard presuppositions about Apollo and human kind, both the following counterfactuals appear to be justified: (i) If Apollo were a man he would be mortal (ii) If Apollo were a man he would be the instance of an immortal man The paradox is here solved by the fact that one of the two conditionals, i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Russell, His Paradoxes, and Cantor's Theorem: Part I
    Philosophy Compass 5/1 (2010): 16–28. Russell, His Paradoxes, and Cantor’s Theorem: Part I Kevin C. Klement∗ University of Massachusetts Abstract In these articles, I describe Cantor’s power-class theorem, as well as a number of logical and philosophical paradoxes that stem from it, many of which were discovered or considered (implic- itly or explicitly) in Bertrand Russell’s work. These include Russell’s paradox of the class of all classes not members of themselves, as well as others involving properties, propositions, descriptive senses, class-intensions, and equivalence classes of coextensional properties. Part I focuses on Can- tor’s theorem, its proof, how it can be used to manufacture paradoxes, Frege’s diagnosis of the core difficulty, and several broad categories of strategies for offering solutions to these paradoxes. 1. Introduction In 1961, W. V. Quine described a philosophical method he dubbed ‘The Ways of Para- dox’. It begins with a seemingly well-reasoned argument leading to an apparently ab- surd conclusion. It continues with careful scrutiny of the reasoning involved. If we are ultimately unwilling to accept the conclusion as justified, the process may end with the conclusion that, ‘some tacit and trusted pattern of reasoning must be made explicit and be henceforward avoided or revised’ (‘Ways’ 11). This method perfectly describes Bertrand Russell’s philosophical work, especially from 1901 to 1910, while composing Principia Mathematica. Russell is most closely associated with the class-theoretic antinomy bearing his name: the class of all those classes that are not members of themselves would appear to be a member of itself if and only if it is not.
    [Show full text]
  • Table of Contents
    Table of Contents Introduction: The tension between the rational and the non-rational in Plato’s reasoning............................................... 11 Plato’s endeavor of truth-finding.................................................... 15 Plato’s rational/non-rational continuum of reasoning....................16 Mythos andlogos in Plato: How useful are competing modes of enquiry?......................................................................................... 19 How useful are Plato’s ideas for problem-solving in our.....24 time? 1. How does Plato communicate his ideas?.................................... 29 Foundations of communication and culture-construction............. 29 Performative acts and symbol-making.......................................30 Identity and complex culture.......................................................31 Intentionally....................................................... 33 Complex language....................................................................... 34 Salient agents in cultural identification as a precondition for self-reflection and reasoning................................................ 35 Language use and the crafting of philosophical terminology....... 37 Existing terms in new contexts................................................... 40 Plato’s creation of new terms......................................................52 New phraseology introduced by Plato.......................................59 The narrative fabric of Platonic discourse: Myth as a tool of philosophical
    [Show full text]