Equality and Liberty As Complements

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Equality and Liberty As Complements Hoover Press : Machan (Equality) DP5 HPEQUA0400 05-06-01 rev1 page 97 Equality and Liberty as Complements Mark LeBar and liberty are twin pillars of modern democratic attitudes. We believe they underwrite our commit- ments to our cherished political institutions and our relations among ourselves as citizens. Yet it is not so obvious that these pillars stand together. In a perfectly free world, some of us would no doubt fare well whereas others would not. Even if we begin with equal amounts of wealth, given the differences in our abilities and enterprise, the freedom to do what we wish with it will threaten that equality. And a world in which each of us was assured a roughly equal degree of material welfare would require massive constraints on our liberty. The broken promises of twentieth-cen- tury socialism suggest that if equality is used to justify political insti- tutions, liberty is quickly extinguished. Is it then right to see equality and liberty as in tension with each other? If we want to avoid that conclusion, we might begin by suspecting that we have got hold of the wrong conceptions of either liberty or equality, or both. Perhaps material equality is not the form of equality that is of greatest moral and political value. Perhaps, on the other hand, the freedom to do what you wish with Hoover Press : Machan (Equality) DP5 HPEQUA0400 05-06-01 rev1 page 98 98 / Mark LeBar what you have is not the most important notion of liberty. The right conceptions of both ideals might eliminate the tension be- tween them. So I will suggest in this chapter. But what conceptions are the right ones? In what follows I sur- vey some of the candidates that philosophers and theorists have offered in the brief history of modern democracy. That history is littered with problematic conceptions of equality and liberty. I will suggest that the most promising approach (though one in need of much development itself ) is one proposed by Immanuel Kant—a revered figure in moral philosophy, but unjustly overlooked as a source of political insight. Equality figures greatly in our understanding of what is politically sacrosanct. The Declaration of Independence takes as a “self-evi- dent” truth that “all men are created equal,” and in doing so it lays claim to an ideal that we have tried valiantly to realize. But in what way are we equal? What kind of equality should matter for political institutions? It patently cannot be equality of any sort of natural attribute. There is simply no denying that we differ from each other in more ways than we can count, but these differences do not affect our conviction that we are equal in some important sense. Equality must be a normative, not a descriptive, ideal; it must be a matter not of what we are like, but rather of how we ought to treat each other. The claim of the Declaration of Independence is that people should be treated as equals, not that people are equal in any biolog- ical sense. But what does it mean to treat people as equals? How are polit- ical institutions capable of reflecting or embodying such an ideal? These are the questions that advocates of the ideal of material equality of various sorts—egalitarians—themselves disagree about. Hoover Press : Machan (Equality) DP5 HPEQUA0400 05-06-01 rev1 page 99 Equality and Liberty as Complements /99 Equality of Welfare We might begin with the idea that treating people as equals means ensuring that, by and large, they live equally well, or have equally valuable or desirable lives. Some, indeed, have argued that political institutions ought to be arranged to ensure equality of welfare or equality of condition. We can appreciate the motivation for this idea by recognizing the role of brute luck in how desirable our lives are. My life is a much better one, given the time and circumstances of my birth and the parents to whom I was born, than it would have been had I been born a century before, or born into severe poverty. In one important sense it is just my luck that I was not. And there is something attractive about the idea that one job for human beings in community—in particular as part of their political organization—should be to minimize these unfair results of nature’s crapshoot. As John Rawls, a prominent proponent of one form of egalitarianism, puts the point, a just society is one in which “men agree to share one another’s fate”1 by attempting to counteract the arbitrary natural distribution of advantages and disadvantages in our institutions. And one way to do this is to distribute the goods we produce so as to equalize the conditions in which we live our lives. The aim is to ensure that all of us live roughly equally well. Plausible as this proposal sounds initially, it confronts two signif- icant problems. First, such a proposal must include an account of how such welfare or well-being is to be measured, if we are to equalize it. This is a sizable problem. Is there some objective list of things we can check off and sum up for each person to arrive at a measurement of how well each is living? What would go on such a list, and who decides that? Consider a good as fungible as financial wealth. If we were to equalize the wealth of Bill Gates and the 1. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971). Hoover Press : Machan (Equality) DP5 HPEQUA0400 05-06-01 rev1 page 100 100 / Mark LeBar Dalai Lama, would that make them equally well off? By whose standards? It seems doubtful that financial wealth matters to each of them in the same way. In general, it is hard to imagine any objec- tive list of things to measure the desirability of lives that would command consensus. Though there are certainly broad areas of convergence (most of us would rather have more money than less), there is also great difference among the standards we use to judge how well our lives are going. One way of avoiding that problem is this: instead of equalizing people’s holdings in some fixed list of good things (which people may or may not value, or value to differing degrees), focus instead on equalizing the degree to which they have what they do value— the degree to which their own preferences are satisfied. Given this interpretation of equality of welfare, it does not matter that Bill Gates and the Dalai Lama do not have the same amount of money. What matters is that each has what he wants to a roughly equal degree, though what that is for each is very different. But this approach too has its drawbacks. What if what I want is prohibitively costly? What if I can be happy only if I have uninter- rupted opportunity to gaze on original Renoirs and will be deeply unhappy otherwise? Does a commitment to equality require that I be ensured uninterrupted access to the paintings? What if my pref- erence is something less bizarre but more perverse, such as the reinstitution of slavery? Is there the slightest reason for our political system to be designed so that I get equal satisfaction of that prefer- ence? Presumably not. Clearly not just any preference I have should count for purposes of measuring my well-being, and thus for equal- izing my well-being with that of my fellow citizens. Moreover, my claims to the satisfaction of my preferences are even weaker if I have deliberately cultivated those preferences. If they are my doing (so to speak), the fact that I could have cultivated other, less costly or less perverse, preferences further undermines my claim on society for their satisfaction. This brings us to the Hoover Press : Machan (Equality) DP5 HPEQUA0400 05-06-01 rev1 page 101 Equality and Liberty as Complements / 101 second serious problem for equality of welfare of which I spoke earlier, and egalitarians differ deeply as to how to deal with it. Whether and how our responsibility for our preferences matters is a specific case of a more general worry: how are we to reconcile equality of welfare with the idea that each of us must be thought to bear (some) responsibility for how well our lives go? We are not just victims of fate with respect to our well-being. We are agents who act to make our lives better or worse, and we hold each other accountable for much of how well we live. These facts matter for our thinking about equality. For example, suppose we think that society ought to be ordered so that each person fares equally well (by some metric or other) in their lives, and we distribute goods accordingly. But someone, call him Burt, loves to gamble. Unfortunately (for Burt) he is not good at it, and consequently he loses money as fast as he can get his hands on it. If we attempt to give him more money for food, clothing, housing, and so on to bring his welfare up to a level of equality with others, he will just lose it gambling. Does a commitment to equality require that we keep funneling money to Burt in an effort to maintain his level of welfare at par with the welfare of others? Equality of Resources Proponents of egalitarianism deal in different ways with the idea that we bear some responsibility for our own well-being. One way is to insist that, instead of aiming for equality of welfare as an out- come, political institutions should provide for equality of resources, leaving individuals to bear the responsibility for how they deploy those resources and consequently for what level of well-being they achieve.2 2.
Recommended publications
  • The Relationship Between Capitalism and Democracy
    The Relationship Between Capitalism And Democracy Item Type text; Electronic Thesis Authors Petkovic, Aleksandra Evelyn Publisher The University of Arizona. Rights Copyright © is held by the author. Digital access to this material is made possible by the University Libraries, University of Arizona. Further transmission, reproduction or presentation (such as public display or performance) of protected items is prohibited except with permission of the author. Download date 01/10/2021 12:57:19 Item License http://rightsstatements.org/vocab/InC/1.0/ Link to Item http://hdl.handle.net/10150/625122 THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND DEMOCRACY By ALEKSANDRA EVELYN PETKOVIC ____________________ A Thesis Submitted to The Honors College In Partial Fulfillment of the Bachelors degree With Honors in Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and Law THE UNIVERSITY OF ARIZONA M A Y 2 0 1 7 Approved by: ____________________________ Dr. Thomas Christiano Department of Philosophy Abstract This paper examines the very complex relationship between capitalism and democracy. While it appears that capitalism provides some necessary element for a democracy, a problem of political inequality and a possible violation of liberty can be observed in many democratic countries. I argue that this political inequality and threat to liberty are fueled by capitalism. I will analyze the ways in which capitalism works against democratic aims. This is done through first illustrating what my accepted conception of democracy is. I then continue to depict how the various problems with capitalism that I describe violate this conception of democracy. This leads me to my conclusion that while capitalism is necessary for a democracy to reach a certain needed level of independence from the state, capitalism simultaneously limits a democracy from reaching its full potential.
    [Show full text]
  • Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (In a Constitutional Democracy)
    Georgetown University Law Center Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW 2013 Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (in a Constitutional Democracy) Imer Flores Georgetown Law Center, [email protected] Georgetown Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper No. 12-161 This paper can be downloaded free of charge from: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub/1115 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2156455 Imer Flores, Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (in a Constitutional Democracy), in LAW, LIBERTY, AND THE RULE OF LAW 77-101 (Imer B. Flores & Kenneth E. Himma eds., Springer Netherlands 2013) This open-access article is brought to you by the Georgetown Law Library. Posted with permission of the author. Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.georgetown.edu/facpub Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, Legislation Commons, and the Rule of Law Commons Chapter6 Law, Liberty and the Rule of Law (in a Constitutional Democracy) lmer B. Flores Tse-Kung asked, saying "Is there one word which may serve as a rule of practice for all one's life?" K'ung1u-tzu said: "Is not reciprocity (i.e. 'shu') such a word? What you do not want done to yourself, do not ckJ to others." Confucius (2002, XV, 23, 225-226). 6.1 Introduction Taking the "rule of law" seriously implies readdressing and reassessing the claims that relate it to law and liberty, in general, and to a constitutional democracy, in particular. My argument is five-fold and has an addendum which intends to bridge the gap between Eastern and Western civilizations,
    [Show full text]
  • National Honor Society Liberty High School Chapter LHS Chapter of The
    National Honor Society Liberty High School Chapter 1115 Linden Street Bethlehem, PA 18018 LHS Chapter of the National Honor Society A pplication Criteria and Requirements Criteria to Receive an Application: Students must have a 3.75 cumulative GPA at the end of their Sophomore or Junior year to receive an application at the beginning of their Junior or Senior year, respectively. How to Apply: Students will receive an application packet at the beginning of the school year in which they are eligible (Junior or Senior year). The application must be completely filled out and returned on the due date in September. The sections are as follows: Section I - Community Service Juniors applying must have at least 30 hours of community service completed (ie: 15 hours/year). Seniors applying must have at least 45 hours completed It is recommended that students complete all 60 hours of community service prior to applying at a minimum Section II - Essay Statement Demonstrate how you plan to incorporate the four pillars of the National Honor Society into your future experiences and endeavors: F our Pillars: I. Scholarship II: Leadership III: Service IV: Character Section III - Leadership Positions List any/all leadership positions you feel may be appropriate. The more positions listed, the better Section IV - Structured Extracurricular Activities/Work List any/all activities you feel are relevant. The more activities listed, the better. Section V - Teacher Recommendations Requirements Once Accepted: Attendance ALL meetings are mandatory unless otherwise noted. If you fail to come to a meeting without an excuse, you will have a meeting with Mr.
    [Show full text]
  • 5. What Matters Is the Motive / Immanuel Kant
    This excerpt is from Michael J. Sandel, Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do?, pp. 103-116, by permission of the publisher. 5. WHAT MATTERS IS THE MOTIVE / IMMANUEL KANT If you believe in universal human rights, you are probably not a utili- tarian. If all human beings are worthy of respect, regardless of who they are or where they live, then it’s wrong to treat them as mere in- struments of the collective happiness. (Recall the story of the mal- nourished child languishing in the cellar for the sake of the “city of happiness.”) You might defend human rights on the grounds that respecting them will maximize utility in the long run. In that case, however, your reason for respecting rights is not to respect the person who holds them but to make things better for everyone. It is one thing to con- demn the scenario of the su! ering child because it reduces overall util- ity, and something else to condemn it as an intrinsic moral wrong, an injustice to the child. If rights don’t rest on utility, what is their moral basis? Libertarians o! er a possible answer: Persons should not be used merely as means to the welfare of others, because doing so violates the fundamental right of self-ownership. My life, labor, and person belong to me and me alone. They are not at the disposal of the society as a whole. As we have seen, however, the idea of self-ownership, consistently applied, has implications that only an ardent libertarian can love—an unfettered market without a safety net for those who fall behind; a 104 JUSTICE minimal state that rules out most mea sures to ease inequality and pro- mote the common good; and a celebration of consent so complete that it permits self-in" icted a! ronts to human dignity such as consensual cannibalism or selling oneself into slav ery.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Worries About the Coherence of Left-Libertarianism Mathias Risse
    John F. Kennedy School of Government Harvard University Faculty Research Working Papers Series Can There be “Libertarianism without Inequality”? Some Worries About the Coherence of Left-Libertarianism Mathias Risse Nov 2003 RWP03-044 The views expressed in the KSG Faculty Research Working Paper Series are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect those of the John F. Kennedy School of Government or Harvard University. All works posted here are owned and copyrighted by the author(s). Papers may be downloaded for personal use only. Can There be “Libertarianism without Inequality”? Some Worries About the Coherence of Left-Libertarianism1 Mathias Risse John F. Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University October 25, 2003 1. Left-libertarianism is not a new star on the sky of political philosophy, but it was through the recent publication of Peter Vallentyne and Hillel Steiner’s anthologies that it became clearly visible as a contemporary movement with distinct historical roots. “Left- libertarian theories of justice,” says Vallentyne, “hold that agents are full self-owners and that natural resources are owned in some egalitarian manner. Unlike most versions of egalitarianism, left-libertarianism endorses full self-ownership, and thus places specific limits on what others may do to one’s person without one’s permission. Unlike right- libertarianism, it holds that natural resources may be privately appropriated only with the permission of, or with a significant payment to, the members of society. Like right- libertarianism, left-libertarianism holds that the basic rights of individuals are ownership rights. Left-libertarianism is promising because it coherently underwrites both some demands of material equality and some limits on the permissible means of promoting this equality” (Vallentyne and Steiner (2000a), p 1; emphasis added).
    [Show full text]
  • Rule of Law Freedom Prosperity
    George Mason University SCHOOL of LAW The Rule of Law, Freedom, and Prosperity Todd J. Zywick 02-20 LAW AND ECONOMICS WORKING PAPER SERIES This paper can be downloaded without charge from the Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection: http://ssrn.com/abstract_id= The Rule of Law, Freedom, and Prosperity Todd J. Zywicki* After decades of neglect, interest in the nature and consequences of the rule of law has revived in recent years. In the United States, the Supreme Court’s decision in Bush v. Gore has triggered renewed interest in the nature of the rule of law in the Anglo-American tradition. Meanwhile, economists have increasingly come to realize the importance of political and legal institutions, especially the presence of the rule of law, in providing the foundation of freedom and prosperity in developing countries. The emerging economies of Eastern Europe and the developing world in Latin America and Africa have thus sought guidance on how to grow the rule of law in these parts of the world that traditionally have lacked its blessings. This essay summarizes the philosophical and historical foundations of the rule of law, why Bush v. Gore can be understood as a validation of the rule of law, and explores the consequences of the presence or absence of the rule of law in developing countries. I. INTRODUCTION After decades of neglect, the rule of law is much on the minds of legal scholars today. In the United States, the Supreme Court’s decision in Bush v. Gore has triggered a renewed interest in the Anglo-American tradition of the rule of law.1 In the emerging democratic capitalist countries of Eastern Europe, societies have struggled to rediscover the rule of law after decades of Communist tyranny.2 In the developing countries of Latin America, the publication of Hernando de Soto’s brilliant book The Mystery of Capital3 has initiated a fervor of scholarly and political interest in the importance and the challenge of nurturing the rule of law.
    [Show full text]
  • Quong-Left-Libertarianism.Pdf
    The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 19, Number 1, 2011, pp. 64–89 Symposium: Ownership and Self-ownership Left-Libertarianism: Rawlsian Not Luck Egalitarian Jonathan Quong Politics, University of Manchester HAT should a theory of justice look like? Any successful answer to this Wquestion must find a way of incorporating and reconciling two moral ideas. The first is a particular conception of individual freedom: because we are agents with plans and projects, we should be accorded a sphere of liberty to protect us from being used as mere means for others’ ends. The second moral idea is that of equality: we are moral equals and as such justice requires either that we receive equal shares of something—of whatever it is that should be used as the metric of distributive justice—or else requires that unequal distributions can be justified in a manner that is consistent with the moral equality of persons. These twin ideas—liberty and equality—are things which no sound conception of justice can properly ignore. Thus, like most political philosophers, I take it as given that the correct conception of justice will be some form of liberal egalitarianism. A deep and difficult challenge for all liberal egalitarians is to determine how the twin values of freedom and equality can be reconciled within a single theory of distributive justice. Of the many attempts to achieve this reconciliation, left-libertarianism is one of the most attractive and compelling. By combining the libertarian commitment to full (or nearly full) self-ownership with an egalitarian principle for the ownership of natural resources, left- libertarians offer an account of justice that appears firmly committed both to individual liberty, and to an egalitarian view of how opportunities or advantages must be distributed.
    [Show full text]
  • Freedom, Legality, and the Rule of Law John A
    Washington University Jurisprudence Review Volume 9 | Issue 1 2016 Freedom, Legality, and the Rule of Law John A. Bruegger Follow this and additional works at: http://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_jurisprudence Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, Legal History Commons, Legal Theory Commons, and the Rule of Law Commons Recommended Citation John A. Bruegger, Freedom, Legality, and the Rule of Law, 9 Wash. U. Jur. Rev. 081 (2016). Available at: http://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_jurisprudence/vol9/iss1/7 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School at Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Washington University Jurisprudence Review by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. FREEDOM, LEGALITY, AND THE RULE OF LAW JOHN A. BRUEGGER ABSTRACT There are numerous interactions between the rule of law and the concept of freedom. We can see this by looking at Fuller’s eight principles of legality, the positive and negative theories of liberty, coercive and empowering laws, and the formal and substantive rules of law. Adherence to the rules of formal legality promotes freedom by creating stability and predictability in the law, on which the people can then rely to plan their behaviors around the law—this is freedom under the law. Coercive laws can actually promote negative liberty by pulling people out of a Hobbesian state of nature, and then thereafter can be seen to decrease negative liberty by restricting the behaviors that a person can perform without receiving a sanction. Empowering laws promote negative freedom by creating new legal abilities, which the people can perform.
    [Show full text]
  • Montesquieu on the History and Geography of Political Liberty
    Montesquieu on the History and Geography of Political Liberty Author: Rebecca Clark Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/bc-ir:103616 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2012 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College Graduate School of Arts & Sciences Department of Political Science MONTESQUIEU ON THE HISTORY AND GEOGRAPHY OF POLITICAL LIBERTY A dissertation by REBECCA RUDMAN CLARK submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2012 © Copyright by REBECCA RUDMAN CLARK 2012 Abstract Montesquieu on the History and Geography of Political Liberty Rebecca R. Clark Dissertation Advisor: Christopher Kelly Montesquieu famously presents climate and terrain as enabling servitude in hot, fertile climes and on the exposed steppes of central Asia. He also traces England’s exemplary constitution, with its balanced constitution, independent judiciary, and gentle criminal practices, to the unique conditions of early medieval northern Europe. The English “found” their government “in the forests” of Germany. There, the marginal, variegated terrain favored the dispersion of political power, and a pastoral way of life until well into the Middle Ages. In pursuing a primitive honor unrelated to political liberty as such, the barbaric Franks accidentally established the rudiments of the most “well-tempered” government. His turn to these causes accidental to human purposes in Parts 3-6 begins with his analysis of the problem of unintended consequences in the history of political reform in Parts 1-2. While the idea of balancing political powers in order to prevent any one individual or group from dominating the rest has ancient roots, he shows that it has taken many centuries to understand just what needs to be balanced, and to learn to balance against one threat without inviting another.
    [Show full text]
  • Capitalism in the Classical and High Liberal Traditions*
    CAPITALISM IN THE CLASSICAL AND HIGH LIBERAL TRADITIONS* By Samuel Freeman I. Essential Features of Liberalism Liberalism holds that there are certain individual liberties that are of fundamental political significance. These liberties are fundamental or basic in that they are preconditions on the pursuit of other social values, such as achieving economic efficiency, promoting the general welfare, and mod- erating the degree of inequality in the distribution of income and wealth. None of these liberties are absolute, but the reasons for limiting their exercise are to protect other basic liberties and maintain essential back- ground conditions for their effective exercise. For example, freedom of speech and expression can be limited when it imminently endangers others’ safety or the freedom of their person, but not because the ideas expressed are found to be offensive by vast majorities of people. Liberal basic liberties are also inalienable: they cannot be given up voluntarily or permanently transferred to anyone else, though some liberties are forfeit- able upon criminal conviction for serious crimes. No liberal government would enforce a contract in which a person sold himself into permanent servitude, or alienated his freedom to change religions, or legally bound himself to vote only as his employer insisted. An integral feature of a liberal constitution is the protection of the basic rights and liberties nec- essary to establish and maintain the equal civic status of citizens. What liberties do liberals generally find to have this extraordinary status? Liberals now would all agree that among the basic liberties are freedom of thought, expression, and inquiry, freedom of conscience and of association, freedom and security of the person, and free choice of occupation.
    [Show full text]
  • John Stuart Mill--Individuality Or Utility? William Hoffman Loyola University Chicago
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Loyola eCommons Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1979 John Stuart Mill--Individuality or Utility? William Hoffman Loyola University Chicago Recommended Citation Hoffman, William, "John Stuart Mill--Individuality or Utility?" (1979). Master's Theses. Paper 3039. http://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/3039 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1979 William Hoffman JOHN STUART MILL--INDIVIDUALITY OR UTILITY7 by William Hoffman A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Loyola University of Chicago in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts April 1979 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to thank Dr. Thomas Engeman and Dr. James Wiser for their invaluable assistance in the development of this thesis. ii VITA The author, William Hoffman, is the son of the late Howard Hoffman and Genevieve (Janis) Hoffman. He was born January 12, 1951, in Chicago, Illinois. His secondary education was achieved at Weber High School in Chicago, Illinois, where he graduated in 1969. In September of 1969 he entered Wright Junior College, which he attended for one year. In September of 1970 he entered DePaul University and in June of 1973 he received the degree of Bachelor of Arts with honor.
    [Show full text]
  • Liberal Internationalism: Historical Trajectory and Current Prospects
    Liberal internationalism: historical trajectory and current prospects Article (Accepted Version) Jahn, Beate (2018) Liberal internationalism: historical trajectory and current prospects. International Affairs, 94 (1). pp. 43-61. ISSN 0020-5850 This version is available from Sussex Research Online: http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/id/eprint/70461/ This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies and may differ from the published version or from the version of record. If you wish to cite this item you are advised to consult the publisher’s version. Please see the URL above for details on accessing the published version. Copyright and reuse: Sussex Research Online is a digital repository of the research output of the University. Copyright and all moral rights to the version of the paper presented here belong to the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. To the extent reasonable and practicable, the material made available in SRO has been checked for eligibility before being made available. Copies of full text items generally can be reproduced, displayed or performed and given to third parties in any format or medium for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes without prior permission or charge, provided that the authors, title and full bibliographic details are credited, a hyperlink and/or URL is given for the original metadata page and the content is not changed in any way. http://sro.sussex.ac.uk Liberal Internationalism - Historical Trajectory and Current Prospects Beate Jahn Abstract Liberal internationalism has been in crisis for a while now. Yet, until recently its supporters have argued that its prospects are better than ever since the successful spread of liberal principles, practices and institutions in the international sphere provides the necessary basis for reform.
    [Show full text]