Associationism and Style in the Nineteenth-Century British Novel Deborah Aschkenes Submitted in Partial Fu

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Associationism and Style in the Nineteenth-Century British Novel Deborah Aschkenes Submitted in Partial Fu In the Mind’s Eye: Associationism and Style in the Nineteenth-Century British Novel Deborah Aschkenes Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2015 © 2015 Deborah Aschkenes All rights reserved. ABSTRACT In the Mind’s Eye: Associationism and Style in the Nineteenth-Century British Novel Deborah Aschkenes In the Mind’s Eye: Associationism and Style in the Nineteenth-Century British Novel argues that the British novel, in its syntactic, grammatical, and rhetorical strategies, incorporated associationist premises about reading comprehension. Associationism, as a term, encapsulates a series of theories during the period that attempted to explain the ways in which external stimuli were “represented” in the mind and linked with other ideas. Inquiries into the association of ideas spanned numerous fields but shared a core belief: everything an individual touched, saw, smelled, or read, was translated into a secondary representation in the mind. Since all objects— whether a phrase, a misty moor, or a character’s face—were thought to be experienced through mental “miniatures,” the association of ideas was the mechanism of the reading experience and of phenomenal experience. Associationist theories delineated how words evoked images, and the ways in which these images became linked to form holistic ideas in the course of a sentence, a paragraph, and throughout a work of fiction. In this project, I show how four canonical nineteenth-century authors—Jane Austen, Walter Scott, Charles Dickens, and George Eliot—created prose styles intended to evoke, enhance, or even resist the spontaneous associative mechanisms considered essential to the comprehension of language. In order to trace the contours of an associative stylistics during the period, I pair each author with associationist theories contemporary with their fiction. In Chapter One, I demonstrate how Jane Austen’s techniques in Persuasion, Northanger Abbey, and Sense and Sensibility incorporated the tenets of the dominant model of associationism in Austen’s day: those of David Hartley. Austen’s mode of representation is highly metonymic, capitalizing on of principles of language comprehension proposed in Hartley’s work. The great degree of stylistic control so often attributed to Austen’s prose is inextricably rooted with the Hartleyan paradigm: a strategy of representation to depict a social world and its objects according to an associationist epistemology. In Chapter Two, I read Sir Walter Scott’s Waverley with the theories of his teacher Dugald Stewart. Walter Scott studied with Dugald Stewart at the University of Edinburgh and in Stewart’s Elements of the Philosophy of the Human Mind, Stewart develops literary-aesthetic guidelines based on the mental models posited in his work. Stewart recommends that a writer delineate in the form of an “outline,” a “minimum” required for the reader to comprehend a represented object. Stewart’s theories about language cognition and literary technique, I argue, provide guidelines for Scott’s development of his own style of literary outline. In Chapter Three, I unfold how Charles Dickens’s style in David Copperfield draws on the associative principles in Lindley Murray’s English Grammar. In Murray’s Grammar, the sentence is a unit of cognition: a precise capsule in which our thoughts are both formed and transmitted. Grammar is an external representation of links between thoughts: the association of ideas in its most tangible form. In Chapter Four, I show that George Eliot integrates a number of discourses about the human mind into her style, with the goal of developing a technique to manage the spontaneous actions of mental associations. The work of James Mill, John Stuart Mill, and Alexander Bain influenced Eliot’s view of associationist psychology, and Eliot, in turn, develops her own associative theories of language in her essays and journals. Eliot’s associative model of reading incorporates principles of chemistry. Elaboration, a term important to both literary and scientific discourse, provided Eliot with a syntactic style closely aligned with the structure of associative links. More importantly, elaboration afforded Eliot a strategy of cognitive delay; a stylistics intended to subvert the spontaneous action of the mind. By providing “raw materials” for the reader in the form of concrete nouns, and elaborating with a series of extended prepositional phrases, Eliot demands that the reader slow down the automatic action of association and redraw the mental picture. TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgments ii Dedication iv Introduction 1 1. The Style of the Sensorium: Association and Representation in the Novels of Jane Austen 13 2. The Outlines of History: Sir Walter Scott and Dugald Stewart 59 3. Copperfield’s Cognitive Grammar: Charles Dickens and Lindley Murray 99 4. The Chemistry of Associationism: George Eliot Elaborates 136 Bibliography 169 i ACKNOWLEDGMENTS First, I must extend my heartfelt gratitude to my committee: Nicholas Dames, James Eli Adams, and Joanna Stalnaker, whose equal measures of intelligence and kindness helped this project come to fruition. Thank you for understanding what I was trying to do even before it was done. My adviser, Nicholas Dames, taught me that unflinching kindness was a viable pedagogical strategy, even during long hours and difficult days. Jim Adams was a model in his unremitting generosity and seemingly unending energy for close, attentive reading. Joanna Stalnaker’s immeasurably helpful suggestions rejuvenated my thinking on numerous chapters. I am indebted to the generosity of my readers Maureen McLane and Eileen Gillooly. Eileen, I must also thank you for sharing along the way your love for the field and the people in it. I can’t express how much more pleasant this process was made by the presence of my warm and wonderful cohort: especially AM, AS, EH, GB, JH, JT, TD, SM, and your partners. You were (and still are) ready to trade ideas as enthusiastically at the end of this process as you were at all of our humble beginnings. Most importantly, I must thank my family: Anna, Elayne, Jeff, Joe, and Stephen. You were a tireless source of support, my ever-joyous cheerleaders, and fonts of perseverance. I couldn't have done it without you. And lastly, I thank my students, who remind me every day why I do this work. ii DEDICATION To my parents iii INTRODUCTION In 1859, George Henry Lewes published a review of Jane Austen’s work that challenged his predecessors’ readings of the author based on his knowledge of Victorian psychology. Rather than acknowledging the “truth of description” produced by “a precision that delights the reader,” as Sir Walter Scott famously noted, Lewes claimed that when speaking of Austen’s work, “the very word ‘describing’ is altogether misplaced and misleading. She seldom describes anything.”1 “Although every reader must necessarily conjure up to himself a vivid image of people whose characters are so vividly presented,” Lewes contends, “each reader has to do this for himself.”2 Lewes’s criticism derives from his understanding of the reading process. Austen’s language, which relied on abstract terms such as “wonderfully handsome,”3 allowed the reader’s mind to “conjure” a mental picture primarily of his or her own design. This strategy, Lewes believed, was “a defect and a mistake.” In Lewes’s view, the great imaginative leeway afforded by terms like “handsome” or “elegant” led to vagueness and imprecision.4 Yet, Lewes admits that the conceptual freedom that Austen’s technique offered also resulted in the highest achievement in art: “the truest representation effected by the least 1 Sir Walter Scott, from an unsigned review of Emma. Quarterly Review, October 1815, No. 14, (issued March 1816) and George Henry Lewes, “The Novels of Jane Austen” Blackwood’s Edinburgh Magazine, July 1859 lxxxvi, both in Jane Austen: The Critical Heritage, Ed. B.C. Southam (London: Routledge & K. Paul, 1995) 67 and 158, respectively. 2 Lewes “The Novels.” 158 3 Jane Austen, Pride and Prejudice, The Complete Novels of Jane Austen (New York: Modern Library, 1940) 234. These words comprise the first description of Mr. Bingley. 4 Lewes 158 1 expenditure of means.”5 Austen’s “economy of art,” as he called it, produced vivid details in the reader’s mind with very little detail on the page.6 Lewes, in fact, defines Austen’s merits and her flaws by the same measure: the amount of imaginative agency given to the reader to produce the grounds at Pemberley, the seaside at Lyme, and Elizabeth Bennet’s famously fine eyes. Lewes’s review points toward one of the essential questions in British fiction of the period: what is the relationship between detail on the page and realistic representation in the mind? The principles of associationism, which dominated theories of cognition in nineteenth- century Britain, stated that textual detail and mental detail did not exist in a one-to-one ratio. An individual word could spark denotative and connotative content based on previous ideas with which it had been associated. Like many writers of nineteenth-century Britain, Lewes considered the associative models of mental life to be a measure for aesthetic judgments. In this project, I show how four canonical nineteenth-century authors, Jane Austen, Walter Scott, Charles Dickens, and George Eliot created prose styles that capitalized upon—and sometimes subverted—the associative mechanisms thought to be essential in the comprehension of language. The effects that literary style were thought to have on the reading experience were rooted in materialist paradigms of cognition and memory at the core of nineteenth-century British psychology. Inquiries into the nature of associationism spanned numerous fields but shared a 5 Lewes argues: “if the art of the novelist be the representation of human life by means of a story; and if the truest representation, effected by the least expenditure of means, constitutes the highest claim of art, then we say that Miss Austen has carried the art to a point of excellence surpassing that reached by any of her rivals.” “The Novels” 166.
Recommended publications
  • Imagination Bound: a Theoretical Imperative
    University of Kentucky UKnowledge Theses and Dissertations--Philosophy Philosophy 2016 Imagination Bound: A Theoretical Imperative Robert Michael Guerin University of Kentucky, [email protected] Digital Object Identifier: http://dx.doi.org/10.13023/ETD.2016.017 Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Guerin, Robert Michael, "Imagination Bound: A Theoretical Imperative" (2016). Theses and Dissertations-- Philosophy. 8. https://uknowledge.uky.edu/philosophy_etds/8 This Doctoral Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations--Philosophy by an authorized administrator of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STUDENT AGREEMENT: I represent that my thesis or dissertation and abstract are my original work. Proper attribution has been given to all outside sources. I understand that I am solely responsible for obtaining any needed copyright permissions. I have obtained needed written permission statement(s) from the owner(s) of each third-party copyrighted matter to be included in my work, allowing electronic distribution (if such use is not permitted by the fair use doctrine) which will be submitted to UKnowledge as Additional File. I hereby grant to The University of Kentucky and its agents the irrevocable, non-exclusive, and royalty-free license to archive and make accessible my work in whole or in part in all forms of media, now or hereafter known. I agree that the document mentioned above may be made available immediately for worldwide access unless an embargo applies.
    [Show full text]
  • Coversheet for Thesis in Sussex Research Online
    A University of Sussex DPhil thesis Available online via Sussex Research Online: http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/ This thesis is protected by copyright which belongs to the author. This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the Author The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the Author When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given Please visit Sussex Research Online for more information and further details Elkington & Co. and the Art of Electro-Metallurgy, circa 1840-1900. Alistair Grant. A Thesis Submitted to the University of Sussex for Examination for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy. September 2014. 2 I hereby declare that this thesis is solely my own work, and has not been, and will not be submitted in whole, or in part, to another University for the award of any other degree. Signature:……………………………………… 3 This PhD thesis is dedicated to my wife Lucy and my daughter Agnes. I would like to thank my wife, Dr. Lucy Grant, without whose love, encouragement, and financial support my doctoral studies could not have happened. Her fortitude, especially during the difficult early months of 2013 when our daughter Agnes was ill, anchored our family and home, and enabled me to continue my research and complete this PhD thesis. 4 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS First and foremost, I would like to thank my supervisor Professor Maurice Howard. Having nurtured my enthusiasm for Art History as an undergraduate at the University of Sussex from 1983-1986, when I approached him, 23 years later, about pursuing PhD research into Elkington & Co.
    [Show full text]
  • The Nature of Learning and Memory
    Arlo Clark-Foos, Ph.D. 2 October 2017 1 • Life Without Memory (Clive Wearing) – Video Clive’s Diary “10:08 a.m.: Now I am superlatively awake. First time aware for years.” “10:13 a.m.: Now I am overwhelmingly awake.” “10:28 a.m.: Actually I am now the first time awake for years.” 10/2/2017 12:41 PM 2 • Genes determine the possible range. • Reflex actions, simple behaviors – Knee-jerk, swallow, suck, grip John B. Watson and Rosalie Rayner 2 October 2017 3 • Experience (and memory of it) determines our individual differences and allows us to improve upon initial behaviors and reflexes. 2 October 2017 4 • How well can you read these sentences? The quick brown fox jumps over the lazy dog. Pack my box with five dozen liquor jugs. 2 October 2017 5 • Context and Expectations Group 1 Group 2 2 October 2017 6 Bugelski & Alampay (1961) 2 October 2017 7 Jastrow (1899) 2 October 2017 8 Kremen (2010) 2 October 2017 9 2 October 2017 10 2 October 2017 11 • Introspection, Logic, & Philosophy • Plato’s Aviary metaphor 2 October 2017 12 “other animals (as well as man) have memory, but … none … except man, shares in the faculty of recollection” • Observation and Data Theories • Contiguity, Frequency, Similarity • All knowledge is innate, • Memory The Republic – Replication of sensory perception – Passive re-perception • Familiarity? • Intuition and Logic • Reminiscence – Replaying an entire experience – Temporal contiguity • Recollection? 2 October 2017 13 Mind Body Cogito ergo sum Stimulus, Response (reflex arc) (Descartes, 1637) Like a machine/clock Animal “Spirits” flow Knowledge is mostly innate 2 October 2017 14 • Absolute Power of the Monarchy – Isaac Newton’s Light and Robert Boyle’s chemicals • Associationism (Green, Bitter/Sour vs.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Late British Associationism and Its Context This Is a Story About Philosophy. Or About Science
    Chapter 1: An Introduction to Late British Associationism and Its Context This is a story about philosophy. Or about science. Or about philosophy transforming into science. Or about science and philosophy, and how they are related. Or were, in a particular time and place. At least, that is the general area that the following narrative will explore, I hope with sufficient subtlety. The matter is rendered non-transparent by the fact that that the conclusions one draws with regard to such questions are, in part, matters of discretionary perspective – as I will try to demonstrate. My specific historical focus will be on the propagation of a complex intellectual tradition concerned with human sensation, perception, and mental function in early nineteenth century Britain. Not only philosophical opinion, but all aspects of British intellectual – and practical – life, were in the process of significant transformation during this time. This cultural flux further confuses recovery of the situated significance of the intellectual tradition I am investigating. The study of the mind not only was influenced by a set of broad social shifts, but it also participated in them fully as both stimulus to and recipient of changing conditions. One indication of this is simply the variety of terms used to identify the ‘philosophy of mind’ as an intellectual enterprise in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.1 But the issue goes far deeper into the fluid constitutive features of the enterprise - including associated conceptual systems, methods, intentions of practitioners, and institutional affiliations. In order to understand philosophy of mind in its time, we must put all these factors into play.
    [Show full text]
  • 272 Bibliography Abbreviations for Frequently Cited Works Analysis = Mill [1829] E&W = Bain [1859] EAP = Reid[1788/1969]
    Bibliography Abbreviations for Frequently Cited Works Analysis = Mill [1829] E&W = Bain [1859] EAP = Reid[1788/1969] EIP = Reid [1785/1969] First Enquiry = “An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding” in Hume [1777/1975] Inquiry = Reid [1764/1997] Lectures = Brown [1828/1860] or Hamilton [1844/1877] (sense obvious in context) Observations, OM = Hartley [1749/1966] S&I = Bain [1855] Sketch = Brown [1820/1977] SSR = Kuhn [1962/1970] Treatise = Hume [1739-1740/1978] Section I: Primary Sources Allen, Grant, Physiological Aesthetics [Garland Publishing, 1877]. Bain, Alexander, The Senses and the Intellect [University Publications of America, 1855/1977]. Bain, Alexander, The Emotions and the Will [University Publications of America, 1859/1977]. Bain, Alexander, “The Early Life of James Mill” in Mind, 1(1), pp.97-116 [1876a]. Bain, Alexander, “The Life of James Mill” in Mind, 1(4), pp.509-531 [1876b]. Bain, Alexander, James Mill: A Biography [Augustus M. Kelley, 1882a/1967]. Bain, Alexander, John Stuart Mill: A Criticism with Personal Reflections [Longmans, Green and Co., 1882b]. Bain, Alexander, Autobiography [1904]. Barzellotti, Giacomo, “Philosophy in Italy” in Mind, 3(12), pp.505-538 [1878]. Berkeley, George, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Jonathan Dancy, ed. [Oxford University Press, 1710/1998] Brown, Thomas, Lectures on the Philosophy of the Human Mind [Hallowell Glazer and Co., 1828]. 272 Brown, Thomas, Lectures on the Philosophy of the Human Mind [William Tegg, 1828/1860 (20th Edition)]. Brown, Thomas, Sketch of a System of the Philosophy of the Human Mind [1820], reprinted in Significant Contributions to the History of Psychology, Series A: Orientations, Volume I, Daniel N.
    [Show full text]
  • The History of Associationism and British Medical Psychology
    THE HISTORY OF ASSOCIATIONISM AND BRITISH MEDICAL PSYCHOLOGY by ROBERT HOELDTKE AT the beginning ofthe eighteenth century the time-honoured identification of mental disease with derangements of the humoral factors still prevailed. Another closely related, but less well known tradition localized diseases of the mind to specific mental faculties. Diseases ofthe imagination were thus distinct from diseases ofthejudgment, memory, or will. These ideas were based upon an implicit vitalism; i.e. the faculties were envisioned as free and active aspects of the mind in some way independent of the laws governing the material and biological world. Faculty psychology and its assumed vitalism are of particular importance to the present study since it was this school ofthought that the eighteenth century psychology of associations attempted to discredit. The complex history of this new approach is described in Warren's History ofAssociationism. Several distinct themes are present, the first and most fundamental element being John Locke's assertion that knowledge was based upon sensation. David Hume further developed this simple statement in his observation that the sensation of related objects became associated in the mind so that the subsequent sensation of only one of the related objects would bring about the recollection of the whole series. Finally Hartley explained associating sensation in terms of the Newtonian concepts of vibration and gravitation. In so doing he emphasized the materialistic flavour of the psychology, making it acceptable to the new science of physics, although still finding it possible to evade the charge of materialism. Despite this pious and ambivalent concession to the past, Hartley's thought represented a radical departure from the psychology of active faculties, which gradually became discredited by eighteenth-century physicians.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 2 – Philosophical & Scientific Antecedents of Psychology
    CHAPTER 2 – PHILOSOPHICAL & SCIENTIFIC ANTECEDENTS OF PSYCHOLOGY Dr. Nancy Alvarado The Dark and Middle Ages Images of the Dark Ages Why Were the Dark Ages Dark? The Roman Empire had preserved knowledge, but it collapsed and was overrun by Barbarians. Access to the accumulated knowledge was preserved in Muslim libraries but these were inaccessible because the West was mostly Christian. The Medieval Church discouraged literacy, free thought, and scientific inquiry beyond the revealed wisdom of clerics & church scholars (St. Augustine). With the Crusades, knowledge was rediscovered. Muslim Libraries were Rediscovered Black sea Launched by Pope Urban II at the Council of Clermont in 1095, the First Crusade was the most successful. Urban gave a dramatic speech urging Christians to swarm toward Jerusalem and make it safe for Christian pilgrims by taking it away from the Muslims. One View of the Dark Ages Science in the Dark Ages Hothersall – the historian Kemp asserts there was innovation and science during the Dark Ages: Stirrups used for the first time in war (600’s AD/CE). A biography of Charlemagne was published (800’s). Domesday Book (1086 survey done for King William I of England) recorded 6000 watermills in Britain. Windmill invented in 1180 (taxed by the Vatican). It would be odd if there were no progress at all, but this is not comparable to what was seen in Greece & Rome nor was learning cumulative. Medieval Period Population increased putting pressure on peasants. Landowners had the advantage, there was famine. th th 14 universities were established in 12 & 13 centuries, including Oxford & Cambridge.
    [Show full text]
  • 128 Dale E. Miller the Great Virtue of This Book Is That It Takes Seriously Mill's Utilitarianism. Too Many Accounts of Mill B
    128 book reviews Dale E. Miller J.S. Mill: Moral, Social and Political Thought, (Cambridge and Malden, MA: Polity), 252 pp. ISBN: 978-0-07456-2583-6 (hbk); 978-0-7456-2584-3 (pbk). Hardback/ Paperback: £ 55.00/15.99. The great virtue of this book is that it takes seriously Mill’s utilitarianism. Too many accounts of Mill’s thought have attempted to reinterpret Mill as anything but a utilitarian. This fashion was perhaps established by Isaiah Berlin’s account of Mill in ‘John Stuart Mill and the Ends of Life’, where Mill’s commit- ment to individual liberty is seen in terms of a retreat from the utilitarianism of Bentham and his father James Mill. Many studies of Mill take the view that, while his liberalism is to be applauded, his utilitarianism is to be regretted, and is, therefore, best written out of the account as something of an embarrass- ment. All this, presumably, is a result of the current obsession with intuition- ism and so-called deontological ethics (I say so-called since it was Bentham who invented the term ‘deontology’). Miller emphasizes the fact that Mill was never anything but a utilitarian throughout his career. He might have added that liberalism itself is a product of utilitarianism, and that this is something that contemporary liberals would do well to remember. Miller presents a philosophical reconstruction of Mill’s thought. He occa- sionally gives some historical context, for instance where Mill’s views might otherwise appear puzzling to the contemporary reader, but his main focus is on providing the best systematic account of Mill’s corpus, and on showing how it remains relevant to today’s debates and concerns, both theoretical and prac- tical.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume's Central Principles
    Hume’s Central Principles 2. Overview, Hume’s Theory of Ideas, and his Faculty Psychology Peter Millican Hertford College, Oxford An Integrated Vision ! We have seen how Hume’s investigation of the notion of causation brought together his interest in the Cosmological Argument for God’s existence, free will and the Problem of Evil, his opposition to aprioristic metaphysics (e.g. concerning mind and matter), and his view of human beings as part of the natural world, amenable to empirical investigation. ! Although there is historical evidence of his early interest in these things, they come together most clearly not in the Treatise itself (January 1739), but in the Abstract (autumn 1739) and the Enquiry concerning Human Understanding (1748) … 2 The Topics of the Abstract Introduction Associationism Probability Liberty and Necessity Copy Principle Sceptical Résumé Induction Idea of Necessity Belief Probability Personal Identity Passions 3 Geometry Overview (1) ! Starts from a theory of mental contents: impressions (sensations or feelings) and ideas (thoughts). ! Empiricist: all ideas are derived from impressions (and hence from experience) – Hume’s Copy Principle. ! Assumes a theory of faculties (reason, the senses, imagination etc.), in terms of which he expresses many of his main results. 4 Overview (2) ! Aims to deny that we have rational insight into things (and also – in his moral theory - that we are governed by reason). ! Relations of ideas / matters of fact –"roughly analytic / synthetic (but in the Treatise based on a theory of different kinds of relation) ! Demonstrative / probable reasoning –"roughly deductive / inductive 5 Overview (3) ! Induction presupposes an assumption of uniformity over time, which cannot be founded on any form of rational evidence.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Ontology in the Just War Tradition
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Texas A&M University “THAT TRUTH THAT LIVES UNCHANGEABLY”: THE ROLE OF ONTOLOGY IN THE JUST WAR TRADITION A Dissertation by PHILLIP WESLEY GRAY Submitted to the Office of Graduate Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY December 2006 Major Subject: Political Science © 2006 PHILLIP WESLEY GRAY ALL RIGHTS RESERVED “THAT TRUTH THAT LIVES UNCHANGEABLY”: THE ROLE OF ONTOLOGY IN THE JUST WAR TRADITION A Dissertation by PHILLIP WESLEY GRAY Submitted to the Office of Graduate Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Approved by: Chair of Committee, Cary J. Nederman Committee Members, Elisabeth Ellis Nehemia Geva J. R. G. Wollock Head of Department, Patricia Hurley December 2006 Major Subject: Political Science iii ABSTRACT “That Truth that Lives Unchangeably”: The Role of Ontology in the Just War Tradition. (December 2006) Phillip Wesley Gray, B.A., University of Dayton Chair of Advisory Committee: Dr. Cary J. Nederman The just war tradition as we know it has its origins with Christian theology. In this dissertation, I examine the theological, in particular ontological, presuppositions of St. Augustine of Hippo in his elucidation of just war. By doing so, I show how certain metaphysical ideas of St. Augustine (especially those on existence, love, and the sovereignty of God) shaped the just war tradition. Following this, I examine the slow evacuation of his metaphysics from the just war tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • A Crucible in Which to Put the Soul”: Keeping Body and Soul Together in the Moderate Enlightenment, 1740-1830
    “A CRUCIBLE IN WHICH TO PUT THE SOUL”: KEEPING BODY AND SOUL TOGETHER IN THE MODERATE ENLIGHTENMENT, 1740-1830 DISSERTATION Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the doctor of philosophy degree in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University KARA ELIZABETH BARR, M.A. DEPARTMENT OF HISTORY THE OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY 2014 DISSERTATION COMMITTEE: Dale K. Van Kley, director Matthew D. Goldish, advisor Geoffrey Parker COPYRIGHT BY KARA ELIZABETH BARR 2014 ABSTRACT This dissertation examines the relationship between Christianity and the Enlightenment in eighteenth-century Europe. Specifically, it explores how the Enlightenment produced the modern Western perception of the nature of the mind and its relationship to the body. While most traditional Enlightenment historiography argues that the movement was defined by radical, atheistic thinkers, like Diderot and Spinoza, who denied the existence of the traditional Christian immaterial and immortal soul, this project demonstrates that these extreme thinkers were actually a minority, confined largely to the intellectual fringes. By contrast, not only were many Enlightenment thinkers sincere Christians, but they were actually the most effective communicators of new ideas by showing how the Enlightenment supported, rather than attacked, traditional Christian beliefs. This moderate Enlightenment is responsible for developing Western ideas about how the mind and body are related, especially within the emerging fields of psychology and psychiatry in the mid-nineteenth century. This dissertation gains its focus through an examination of the work of two historiographically neglected enlightened thinkers—David Hartley in Britain, and the Abbé de Condillac in France. Both of them argued for the traditional Christian belief in an immortal soul, but used enlightened ideas to do so.
    [Show full text]
  • © 2015 Thomas Steven Highstead Immanuel Kant's Response to David Hume Regarding Cause and Effect by Thomas Steven Highstead A
    Immanuel Kant’s Response to David Hume regarding Cause and Effect By Thomas Steven Highstead A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Affairs in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of: Master of Arts In Philosophy Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario © 2015 Thomas Steven Highstead ii Abstract When David Hume could not experience the impression of a necessary connection in the constant conjunction of two events, he reasoned that the necessity inherent in such a relation was the result of a feeling or desire; a determination of the mind to connect one event to another. Immanuel Kant, on the other hand, argued that the idea of cause was an innate structure of thought that provided the objective validity to a causal relationship. I argue that Kant’s combination of sensible intuition and the faculty of thought provides a more comprehensive and objective explanation of how we understand the necessary connection between a cause and its effect. iii Acknowledgement There are two special people in my life for whom I owe a deep debt of gratitude for making this thesis possible. The first is my wife, Sheryll, whose encouragement and patience throughout this long process was steadfast. Besides being my life partner, she deigned to scrutinize my grammar, in an attempt to make my abstruse prose more accessible. The second person I wish to thank is my Supervisor, Dr. Melissa Frankel, whose patience, guidance, mentoring, and deep knowledge pushed me to produce a paper that is considerably better than if I was left to my own devices.
    [Show full text]