Robot Ethics: Mapping the Issues for a Mechanized World

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Robot Ethics: Mapping the Issues for a Mechanized World Artificial Intelligence 175 (2011) 942–949 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Artificial Intelligence www.elsevier.com/locate/artint CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by DigitalCommons@CalPolyRobot ethics: Mapping the issues for a mechanized world Patrick Lin KeithAbney George Bekey abstract As with other emerging technologies, advanced robotics brings with it new ethical and policy challenges. This paper will describe the flourishing role of robots in society—from security to sex—and survey the numerous ethical and social issues, which we locate in three broad categories: safety & errors, law & ethics, and social impact. We discuss many of these issues in greater detail in our forthcoming edited volume on robot ethics from Keywords: Robot MIT Press. Robotics Ethics Society Philosophy Psychology Law Policy Safety Error Bill Gates recently observed that “the emergence of the robotics industry ... is developing in much the same way that the computer business did 30 years ago” [18]. As a key architect of the computer industry, his prediction has special weight. In a few decades—or sooner, given exponential progress forecasted by Moore’s Law—robots in society will be as ubiquitous as computers are today, he believes; and we would be hard-pressed to find an expert who disagrees. But consider just a few of the challenges linked to computers in the last 30 years: They have displaced or severely threatened entire industries, for instance, typewriter manufacturing and sales by word-processing software, accountants by spreadsheets, artists by graphic-design programs, and many local businesses by Internet retailers. Customer-tracking websites, street-view maps, and the free and anonymous flow of information online still raise privacy concerns. The digital medium enables sharing that may infringe on copyright claims, and a largely unregulated process of registering domain names has led to charges of cybersquatting or trademark disputes. The effects of social networking and virtual reality on real-world relationships are still unclear, and cyberbullying is a new worry for parents. Internet addiction, especially to online gaming and pornography, continues to ruin real lives. Security efforts to protect corporate networks and personal computers require a massive educational campaign, not unlike safe-sex programs in the physical world. And so on. To be clear, these are not arguments that the computer industry should never have been developed, but only that its benefits need to be weighed against its negative effects. However, we are not interested in making such a cost-benefit evaluation here but would like to focus on an important lesson: If the evolution of the robotics industry is analogous to that of computers, then we can expect important social and ethical challenges to rise from robotics as well, and attending to them sooner rather than later will likely help mitigate those negative consequences. Society has long been concerned with the impact of robotics, even before the technology was viable. Beginning with the first time the word ‘robot’ was coined [13], most literary works about robots are cautionary tales about insufficient programming, emergent behavior, errors, and other issues that make robots unpredictable and potentially dangerous (e.g., [5,6,16,45]). In popular culture, films continue to dramatize and demonize robots, such as Metropolis, Star Wars, Blade Runner, Terminator, AI, and I, Robot, to name just a few. Headlines today also stoke fears about robots wreaking havoc on the battlefield as well as financial trading markets, perhaps justifiably so (e.g., [19]). A loose band of scholars worldwide has been researching issues in robot ethics for some time (e.g., [42]). And a few reports and books are trickling into the marketplace (e.g., [43,26,38]). But there has not yet been a single, accessible resource that draws together such thinking on a wide range of issues, e.g., programming design, military affairs, law, privacy, religion, healthcare, sex, psychology, robot rights, and more. To fill that need, the authors of this paper are in the process of editing a collection of robot-ethics papers [28] for MIT Press, a leading publisher in robotics as well as ethics. In this journal paper, we will briefly introduce the major issues in robot ethics. 1. What is a robot? Let us start with a basic issue: What is a robot? Given society’s long fascination with robotics, it seems hardly worth asking the question, as the answer surely must be obvious. On the contrary, there is still a lack of consensus among roboticists on how they define the object of their craft. For instance, an intuitive definition could be that a robot is merely a computer with sensors and actuators that allow it to interact with the external world; however, any computer that is connected to a printer or can eject a CD might qualify as a robot under that definition, yet few roboticists would defend that implication. Certainly, artificial intelligence (AI) by itself can raise interesting issues, such as whether we ought to have humans in the loop more in critical systems, e.g., those controlling energy grids and making financial trades, lest we risk widespread blackouts and stock-market crashes [14,29]. But robots or embodied AI that can directly exert influence on the world seem to pose additional or special risks and ethical quandaries we want to distinguish here. A plausible definition, therefore, needs to be more precise and distinguish robots from mere computers and other devices. We do not presume we can resolve this great debate here, but it is important that we offer a working definition prior to laying out the landscape of current and predicted applications of robotics. In its most basic sense, we define “robot” as an engineered machine that senses, thinks, and acts: “Thus a robot must have sensors, processing ability that emulates some aspects of cognition, and actuators. Sensors are needed to obtain information from the environment. Reactive behaviors (like the stretch reflex in humans) do not require any deep cognitive ability, but on-board intelligence is necessary if the robot is to perform significant tasks autonomously, and actuation is needed to enable the robot to exert forces upon the environment. Generally, these forces will result in motion of the entire robot or one of its elements (such as an arm, a leg, or a wheel)” [9]. This definition does not imply that a robot must be electromechanical; it leaves open the possibility of biological robots, as well as virtual or software ones. But it does rule out as robots any fully remote-controlled machines, since those devices do not “think”, e.g., many animatronics and children’s toys. That is, most of these toys do not make decisions for themselves; they depend on human input or an outside actor. Rather, the generally accepted idea of a robot depends critically on the notion that it exhibits some degree of autonomy or can “think” for itself, making its own decisions to act upon the environment. Thus, the US Air Force’s Predator unmanned aerial vehicle (UAV), though mostly tele-operated by humans, makes some navigational decisions on its own and therefore would count as a robot. By the same definition, the following things are not robots: conventional landmines, toasters, adding machines, coffee makers, and other ordinary devices. As should be clear by now, the definition of “robot” also trades on the notion of “think”, another source of contention which we cannot fully engage here. By “think”, what we mean is that the machine is able to process information from sensors and other sources, such as an internal set of rules either programmed or learned, and to make some decisions autonomously. Of course, this definition merely postpones our task and invites another question: What does it mean for machines to have autonomy? If we may simply stipulate it here, we define “autonomy” in robots as the capacity to operate in the real-world environment without any form of external control, once the machine is activated and at least in some areas of operation, for extended periods of time [9]. Thus again, fully remote- or tele-operated machines would not count as autonomous, since they depend on external control; they cannot “think” and therefore cannot act for themselves. But what about the everyday desktop or laptop com­ puters: Are they autonomous? Doesn’t their programming count as human inputs or external control in some important sense? If so, how can robots ever be said to be free from external control, if all robots are computers (electromechanical or otherwise) at their core? These are all good questions that demand answers, for a complete discussion of what it means to be a robot. Many will engage other difficult issues from technical to philosophical, such as complexity, unpredictability, determinism, responsibility, and free will. As such, we cannot offer a complete discussion given space limitations of this paper, and we will have to content ourselves with the working definitions stipulated above—which should be enough to understand why we include some machines and not others in the following section. 2. Robots today and tomorrow Robots are often tasked to perform the “three Ds”, that is, jobs that are dull, dirty, or dangerous. For instance, automo­ bile factory robots execute the same, repetitive assemblies over and over, with precision and without complaint; military surveillance UAVs patrol the skies for far more hours than a human pilot can endure at a time. Robots crawl around in dark sewers, inspecting pipes for leaks and cracks, as well as do the dirty work in our homes, such as vacuuming floors. Not afraid of danger, they also explore volcanoes and clean up contaminated sites, in addition to more popular service in defusing bombs and mediating hostage crises.
Recommended publications
  • Artificial Intelligence and the Ethics of Self-Learning Robots Shannon Vallor Santa Clara University, [email protected]
    Santa Clara University Scholar Commons Philosophy College of Arts & Sciences 10-3-2017 Artificial Intelligence and the Ethics of Self-learning Robots Shannon Vallor Santa Clara University, [email protected] George A. Bekey Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.scu.edu/phi Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Vallor, S., & Bekey, G. A. (2017). Artificial Intelligence and the Ethics of Self-learning Robots. In P. Lin, K. Abney, & R. Jenkins (Eds.), Robot Ethics 2.0 (pp. 338–353). Oxford University Press. This material was originally published in Robot Ethics 2.0 edited by Patrick Lin, Keith Abney, and Ryan Jenkins, and has been reproduced by permission of Oxford University Press. For permission to reuse this material, please visit http://www.oup.co.uk/academic/rights/permissions. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Arts & Sciences at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE AND 22 THE ETHICS OF SELF - LEARNING ROBOTS Shannon Va ll or and George A. Bekey The convergence of robotics technology with the science of artificial intelligence (or AI) is rapidly enabling the development of robots that emulate a wide range of intelligent human behaviors.1 Recent advances in machine learning techniques have produced significant gains in the ability of artificial agents to perform or even excel in activities for­ merly thought to be the exclusive province of human intelligence, including abstract problem-solving, perceptual recognition, social interaction, and natural language use.
    [Show full text]
  • An Ethical Framework for Smart Robots Mika Westerlund
    An Ethical Framework for Smart Robots Mika Westerlund Never underestimate a droid. Leia Organa Star Wars: The Rise of Skywalker This article focuses on “roboethics” in the age of growing adoption of smart robots, which can now be seen as a new robotic “species”. As autonomous AI systems, they can collaborate with humans and are capable of learning from their operating environment, experiences, and human behaviour feedback in human-machine interaction. This enables smart robots to improve their performance and capabilities. This conceptual article reviews key perspectives to roboethics, as well as establishes a framework to illustrate its main ideas and features. Building on previous literature, roboethics has four major types of implications for smart robots: 1) smart robots as amoral and passive tools, 2) smart robots as recipients of ethical behaviour in society, 3) smart robots as moral and active agents, and 4) smart robots as ethical impact-makers in society. The study contributes to current literature by suggesting that there are two underlying ethical and moral dimensions behind these perspectives, namely the “ethical agency of smart robots” and “object of moral judgment”, as well as what this could look like as smart robots become more widespread in society. The article concludes by suggesting how scientists and smart robot designers can benefit from a framework, discussing the limitations of the present study, and proposing avenues for future research. Introduction capabilities (Lichocki et al., 2011; Petersen, 2007). Hence, Lin et al. (2011) define a “robot” as an Robots are becoming increasingly prevalent in our engineered machine that senses, thinks, and acts, thus daily, social, and professional lives, performing various being able to process information from sensors and work and household tasks, as well as operating other sources, such as an internal set of rules, either driverless vehicles and public transportation systems programmed or learned, that enables the machine to (Leenes et al., 2017).
    [Show full text]
  • Nudging for Good: Robots and the Ethical Appropriateness of Nurturing Empathy and Charitable Behavior
    Nudging for Good: Robots and the Ethical Appropriateness of Nurturing Empathy and Charitable Behavior Jason Borenstein* and Ron Arkin** Predictions are being commonly voiced about how robots are going to become an increasingly prominent feature of our day-to-day lives. Beyond the military and industrial sectors, they are in the process of being created to function as butlers, nannies, housekeepers, and even as companions (Wallach and Allen 2009). The design of these robotic technologies and their use in these roles raises numerous ethical issues. Indeed, entire conferences and books are now devoted to the subject (Lin et al. 2014).1 One particular under-examined aspect of human-robot interaction that requires systematic analysis is whether to allow robots to influence a user’s behavior for that person’s own good. However, an even more controversial practice is on the horizon and warrants attention, which is the ethical acceptability of allowing a robot to “nudge” a user’s behavior for the good of society. For the purposes of this paper, we will examine the feasibility of creating robots that would seek to nurture a user’s empathy towards other human beings. We specifically draw attention to whether it would be ethically appropriate for roboticists to pursue this type of design pathway. In our prior work, we examined the ethical aspects of encoding Rawls’ Theory of Social Justice into robots in order to encourage users to act more socially just towards other humans (Borenstein and Arkin 2016). Here, we primarily limit the focus to the performance of charitable acts, which could shed light on a range of socially just actions that a robot could potentially elicit from a user and what the associated ethical concerns may be.
    [Show full text]
  • An Architecture for Ethical Robots
    1 An architecture for ethical robots Dieter Vanderelst & Alan Winfield Bristol Robotics Laboratory, University of the West of England T Block, Frenchay Campus, Coldharbour Lane, Bristol, BS16 1QY, United Kingdom Abstract—Robots are becoming ever more autonomous. This Anderson [2] and our previous work [27] are the only instances expanding ability to take unsupervised decisions renders it im- of robots having been equipped with a set of moral principles. perative that mechanisms are in place to guarantee the safety of So far, most work has been either theoretical [e.g., 25] or behaviours executed by the robot. Moreover, smart autonomous robots should be more than safe; they should also be explicitly simulation based [e.g., 3]. ethical – able to both choose and justify actions that prevent The approach taken by Anderson and Anderson [1, 2] and harm. Indeed, as the cognitive, perceptual and motor capabilities others [25, 3] is complementary with our research goals. These of robots expand, they will be expected to have an improved authors focus on developing methods to extract ethical rules capacity for making moral judgements. We present a control for robots. Conversely, our work concerns the development architecture that supplements existing robot controllers. This so-called Ethical Layer ensures robots behave according to a of a control architecture that supplements the existing robot predetermined set of ethical rules by predicting the outcomes of controller, ensuring robots behave according to a predeter- possible actions and evaluating the predicted outcomes against mined set of ethical rules [27, 26]. In other words, we are those rules. To validate the proposed architecture, we implement concerned with methods to enforce the rules once these have it on a humanoid robot so that it behaves according to Asimov’s been established [10].
    [Show full text]
  • Acknowledgements Acknowl
    2161 Acknowledgements Acknowl. B.21 Actuators for Soft Robotics F.58 Robotics in Hazardous Applications by Alin Albu-Schäffer, Antonio Bicchi by James Trevelyan, William Hamel, The authors of this chapter have used liberally of Sung-Chul Kang work done by a group of collaborators involved James Trevelyan acknowledges Surya Singh for de- in the EU projects PHRIENDS, VIACTORS, and tailed suggestions on the original draft, and would also SAPHARI. We want to particularly thank Etienne Bur- like to thank the many unnamed mine clearance experts det, Federico Carpi, Manuel Catalano, Manolo Gara- who have provided guidance and comments over many bini, Giorgio Grioli, Sami Haddadin, Dominic Lacatos, years, as well as Prof. S. Hirose, Scanjack, Way In- Can zparpucu, Florian Petit, Joshua Schultz, Nikos dustry, Japan Atomic Energy Agency, and Total Marine Tsagarakis, Bram Vanderborght, and Sebastian Wolf for Systems for providing photographs. their substantial contributions to this chapter and the William R. Hamel would like to acknowledge work behind it. the US Department of Energy’s Robotics Crosscut- ting Program and all of his colleagues at the na- C.29 Inertial Sensing, GPS and Odometry tional laboratories and universities for many years by Gregory Dudek, Michael Jenkin of dealing with remote hazardous operations, and all We would like to thank Sarah Jenkin for her help with of his collaborators at the Field Robotics Center at the figures. Carnegie Mellon University, particularly James Os- born, who were pivotal in developing ideas for future D.36 Motion for Manipulation Tasks telerobots. by James Kuffner, Jing Xiao Sungchul Kang acknowledges Changhyun Cho, We acknowledge the contribution that the authors of the Woosub Lee, Dongsuk Ryu at KIST (Korean Institute first edition made to this chapter revision, particularly for Science and Technology), Korea for their provid- Sect.
    [Show full text]
  • The Grand Challenges of Science Robotics Exclusive Licensee Guang-Zhong Yang,1* Jim Bellingham,2 Pierre E
    SCIENCE ROBOTICS | PERSPECTIVE ROBOTICS Copyright © 2018 The Authors, some rights reserved; The grand challenges of Science Robotics exclusive licensee Guang-Zhong Yang,1* Jim Bellingham,2 Pierre E. Dupont,3 Peer Fischer,4,5 Luciano Floridi,6,7,8,9,10 American Association 11 12,13 14 15 1 for the Advancement Robert Full, Neil Jacobstein, Vijay Kumar, Marcia McNutt, Robert Merrifield, of Science. No claim 16 17,18 7,8,9 19 Bradley J. Nelson, Brian Scassellati, Mariarosaria Taddeo, Russell Taylor, to original U.S. 20 21 22,23 Manuela Veloso, Zhong Lin Wang, Robert Wood Government Works One of the ambitions of Science Robotics is to deeply root robotics research in science while developing novel robotic platforms that will enable new scientific discoveries. Of our 10 grand challenges, the first 7 represent underpin- ning technologies that have a wider impact on all application areas of robotics. For the next two challenges, we have included social robotics and medical robotics as application-specific areas of development to highlight the substantial societal and health impacts that they will bring. Finally, the last challenge is related to responsible in- novation and how ethics and security should be carefully considered as we develop the technology further. Downloaded from INTRODUCTION great strides in realizing its mission of power- ing components into synthetic structures to Just over a year ago, we published the first issue ing the world’s robots, from space robot chal- create robots that perform like natural systems. of Science Robotics. Even within this relatively lenges to autonomous driving, industrial (iii) New power sources, battery technol- short period of time, remarkable progress has assembly, and surgery.
    [Show full text]
  • Report of Comest on Robotics Ethics
    SHS/YES/COMEST-10/17/2 REV. Paris, 14 September 2017 Original: English REPORT OF COMEST ON ROBOTICS ETHICS Within the framework of its work programme for 2016-2017, COMEST decided to address the topic of robotics ethics building on its previous reflection on ethical issues related to modern robotics, as well as the ethics of nanotechnologies and converging technologies. At the 9th (Ordinary) Session of COMEST in September 2015, the Commission established a Working Group to develop an initial reflection on this topic. The COMEST Working Group met in Paris in May 2016 to define the structure and content of a preliminary draft report, which was discussed during the 9th Extraordinary Session of COMEST in September 2016. At that session, the content of the preliminary draft report was further refined and expanded, and the Working Group continued its work through email exchanges. The COMEST Working Group then met in Quebec in March 2017 to further develop its text. A revised text in the form of a draft report was submitted to COMEST and the IBC in June 2017 for comments. The draft report was then revised based on the comments received. The final draft of the report was further discussed and revised during the 10th (Ordinary) Session of COMEST, and was adopted by the Commission on 14 September 2017. This document does not pretend to be exhaustive and does not necessarily represent the views of the Member States of UNESCO. – 2 – REPORT OF COMEST ON ROBOTICS ETHICS EXECUTIVE SUMMARY I. INTRODUCTION II. WHAT IS A ROBOT? II.1. The complexity of defining a robot II.2.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics and Robotics. a First Approach1
    ETHICS AND ROBOTICS. A FIRST APPROACH1. RAFAEL DE ASÍS ROIG2 Abstract: Clearly, technical and scientific progress and moral progress do not necessarily go hand in hand. Therefore, this article encourages reflection on the new ethical challenges posed by such developments and, in particular, by robotics, a field that has developed greatly in recent decades and that has led to possibilities unimaginable until recently. Thus, the author examines here the so-called roboethics, its content, the specific fields it addresses –such as social relations and moral agency of robots–, as well as the different approaches and views on these issues. Keywords: Ethics, robotics, moral agent, human rights Contents: I. INTRODUCTION; II. ROBOTICS; III. ROBOETHICS. I. INTRODUCTION In the 20th and 21st centuries there have been major advances in both the scientific and technical field. The first one has been named the science century. In this regard, it has been claimed that the first half of the 20th century focused on Physics whilst the second half on Biology, Genetics and Computer Science (Rifkin 1998: p. 20). As for the 21st century until now is characterised by the rise of Neuroscience and Nanotechnology as well as by advances in the field of Robotics (in connection with the other areas but especially to I.T). However, despite all these advances, poverty, hunger and dissatisfaction regarding rights still persist. It is not surprising that Th. Pogge commences his book World Poverty and Human Rights examining how it is possible that extreme poverty affects half of humanity despite the enormous economic and technological progress, and how it is possible that the distribution of scientific and technological benefits is so uneven (Pogge 2002).
    [Show full text]
  • KANYOK, NATHAN J., MS, December 2019 COMPUTER SCIENCE
    KANYOK, NATHAN J., M.S., December 2019 COMPUTER SCIENCE SITUATIONAL AWARENESS MONITORING FOR HUMANS-IN-THE-LOOP OF TELEPRES- ENCE ROBOTIC SYSTEMS (80 pages) Thesis Advisor: Dr. Jong-Hoon Kim Autonomous automobiles are expected to be introduced in increasingly complex increments until the system is able to navigate without human interaction. However, humanity is uncomfortable with relying on algorithms to make security critical decisions, which often have moral dimensions. Many robotic systems keep humans in the decision making loop due to their unsurpassed ability to perceive contextual information in ways we find relevant. It is likely that we will see transportation systems with no direct human supervision necessary, but these systems do not address our worry about moral decisions. Until we are able to embed moral agency in digital systems, human actors will be the only agents capable of making decisions with security-critical and moral components. Additionally, in order for a human to be in the position that we can have confidence in their decision, they must be situationally aware of the environment in which the decision will be made. Virtual reality as a medium can achieve this by allowing a person to be telepresent elsewhere. A telepresence dispatch system for autonomous transportation vehicles is proposed that places emphasis on situational awareness so that humans can properly be in the decision making loop. Pre-trial, in-trial, and post-trial metrics are gathered that emphasize human health and monitor situational awareness through traditional and novel approaches. SITUATIONAL AWARENESS MONITORING FOR HUMANS-IN-THE-LOOP OF TELEPRESENCE ROBOTIC SYSTEMS A thesis submitted to Kent State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Science by Nathan J.
    [Show full text]
  • Promoting Inclusiveness in Exoskeleton Robotics: Addressing Challenges for Pediatric Access
    Paladyn, Journal of Behavioral Robotics 2020; 11: 327–339 Research Article Eduard Fosch-Villaronga, Anto Čartolovni*, and Robin L. Pierce Promoting inclusiveness in exoskeleton robotics: Addressing challenges for pediatric access https://doi.org/10.1515/pjbr-2020-0021 received December 10, 2019; accepted May 24, 2020 1 Introduction Robotics have increased productivity and resource efficiency Abstract: Pediatric access to exoskeletons lags far behind in the industrial and retail sectors, and now there is an that of adults. In this article, we promote inclusiveness in emerging interest in realizing a comparable transformation exoskeleton robotics by identifying and addressing chal- in other areas, including health care [1]. However, the lenges and barriers to pediatric access to this potentially life- introduction of robots for health-care and therapeutic changing technology. We first present available exoskeleton purposes that interact directly with patients, older adults, solutions for upper and lower limbs and note the variability and children is not straightforward. It is widely recognized intheabsenceofthese.Next,wequerythepossiblereasons that these robots can entail risks for users and could infringe for this variability in access, explicitly focusing on children, on rights and further may have a significant impact on care- who constitute a categorically vulnerable population, and recipient values, including those of workers’ and end-users’ also stand to benefitsignificantly from the use of this values [2–9]. technology at this critical point in their physical and A relatively new technology that is changing the lives of emotional growth. We propose the use of a life-based design impaired users is physical assistant robots. Physical assistant approach as a way to address some of the design challenges robots, also named exoskeletons, help users perform a task and offer insights toward a resolution regarding market by augmenting or supplementing their capabilities (ISO viability and implementation challenges.
    [Show full text]
  • An Experimental Ethics Approach to Robot Ethics Education
    The Tenth AAAI Symposium on Educational Advances in Artificial Intelligence (EAAI-20) An Experimental Ethics Approach to Robot Ethics Education Tom Williams Qin Zhu Daniel Grollman Colorado School of Mines Colorado School of Mines Plus One Robotics Golden, CO 80402 Golden, CO 80402 Boulder, CO 80301 Abstract those concepts to analyze applications of AI and Robotics. But moreover, such courses may also cover computational We propose an experimental ethics-based curricular module approaches to moral decision making; psychological theo- for an undergraduate course on Robot Ethics. The proposed module aims to teach students how human subjects research ries of moral decision making and blame; and methods for methods can be used to investigate potential ethical concerns experimentally investigating ethical issues. This requires in- arising in human-robot interaction, by engaging those stu- structors with broad interdisciplinary backgrounds, and ped- dents in real experimental ethics research. In this paper we agogical methods that draw on these disparate disciplines. describe the proposed curricular module, describe our imple- In this work, we explore pedagogical techniques aimed at mentation of that module within a Robot Ethics course of- improving students achievement of learning objectives that fered at a medium-sized engineering university, and statis- sit at this confluence of disciplines. Specifically, we present tically evaluate the effectiveness of the proposed curricular and analyze the efficacy of a Robot Ethics course module in module
    [Show full text]
  • Robotics in Germany and Japan DRESDEN PHILOSOPHY of TECHNOLOGY STUDIES DRESDNER STUDIEN ZUR PHILOSOPHIE DER TECHNOLOGIE
    Robotics in Germany and Japan DRESDEN PHILOSOPHY OF TECHNOLOGY STUDIES DRESDNER STUDIEN ZUR PHILOSOPHIE DER TECHNOLOGIE Edited by /Herausgegeben von Bernhard Irrgang Vol./Bd. 5 Michael Funk / Bernhard Irrgang (eds.) Robotics in Germany and Japan Philosophical and Technical Perspectives Bibliographic Information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data is available in the internet at http://dnb.d-nb.de. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Robotics in Germany and Japan : philosophical and technical perspectives / Michael Funk, Bernhard Irrgang (eds.). pages cm ----- (Dresden philosophy of technology perspectives, ISSN 1861- -- 423X ; v. 5) ISBN 978-3-631-62071-7 ----- ISBN 978-3-653-03976-4 (ebook) 1. Robotics-----Germany----- Popular works. 2. Robotics----- Japan--Popular works. 3. Robotics-----Philosophy. I. Funk, Michael, 1985- -- editor of compilation. II. Irrgang, Bernhard, editor of compilation. TJ211.15.R626 2014 629.8'920943----- dc23 2013045885 Cover illustration: Humanoid Robot “ARMAR” (KIT, Germany), Photograph: Michael Funk An electronic version of this book is freely available, thanks to the support of libraries working with Knowledge Unlatched. KU is a collaborative initiative designed to make high quality books Open Access for the public good. More information about the initiative and links to the Open Access version can be found at www.knowledgeunlatched.org ISSN 1861-423X • ISBN 978-3-631-62071-7 (Print) E-ISBN 978-3-653-03976-4 (E-PDF) • E-ISBN 978-3-653-99964-8 (EPUB) E-ISBN 978-3-653-99963-1 (MOBI) • DOI 10.3726/978-3-653-03976-4 Open Access: This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution NonCommercial NoDerivatives 4.0 unported license.
    [Show full text]