Sjahss-66-1276-1287

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sjahss-66-1276-1287 Scholars Journal of Arts, Humanities and Social Sciences ISSN 2347-5374(Online) Abbreviated Key Title: Sch. J. Arts Humanit. Soc. Sci. ISSN 2347-9493(Print) ©Scholars Academic and Scientific Publishers (SAS Publishers) A Unit of Scholars Academic and Scientific Society, India Commonsense Political Philosophy Panayot Butchvarov* The University of Iowa, Iowa, USA Abstract: Some concrete or specific political truths are obvious, evident, indeed self- *Corresponding author evident, even though the relevant, indeed any, abstract or general principles are not. Panayot Butchvarov We might say that they are matters of common sense, meaning by the latter the mature and thoughtful judgments we all share and any serious theorizing, scientific or Article History philosophical, must at least begin with and thus respect even if eventually reject. A Received: 12.06.2018 number of examples are discussed. Accepted: 27.06.2018 Keywords: philosophy, political, commonsense, concrete, abstract, abortion, Published: 30.06.2018 democracy, collectivism, individualism, poverty. DOI: POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 10.21276/sjahss.2018.6.6.15 Questioned, “What are you going to say when they ask you the political philosophy behind TVA?” Franklin Roosevelt replied, “I’ll tell them it’s neither fish nor fowl but whatever it is, it will taste awfully good to the people of the Tennessee Valley [1]”. The reply implied a distinction between concrete or specific political truths, in which Roosevelt often exhibited utmost confidence, and general political principles or theories, which he famously mistrusted, agreeing perhaps with Edmund Burke that they are condemned to “the nakedness and solitude of metaphysical abstraction [2]”. It also implied that some of these truths are obvious, evident, indeed self-evident, even if the relevant abstract or general principles (if any) are not. We might say that they are matters of common “formulating hypotheses...and subjecting them to sense, meaning by this the mature and thoughtful confirmation or disconfirmation by the intuitive moral judgments we all share and any serious theorizing, credibility of their various substantive scientific or philosophical, must at least begin with and consequences....The method depends on taking thus respect even if eventually reject. Indeed, Richard seriously the evidential value of strong moral intuitions Price defined common sense as the faculty of self- about concrete cases, including imaginary cases[4]”. evident truths [3]. Nagel informs us that “[T]hese convictions form the deep common element in...Rawls’ A Theory of Justice, There may be abstract or general principles in Dworkin’s Taking Rights Seriously, Walzer’s Just and politics that are true. But none so far seems to be known Unjust Wars, Thomson’s “A Defense of Abortion,” and to be true, even in the loose everyday sense of “know.” Nozick’s Anarchy, State, and Utopia.” But he does not At most, we only know concrete political facts. A explain how and why such “strong moral intuitions” superficially unkind yet appropriate way of expressing should enjoy “moral credibility” and “evidential value.” this would be that in politics principles really do not He does not hold that they are Platonic awarenesses of matter, only facts do, that in politics there is room only moral Forms or Kantian a priori cognitions. Rather, for data, none for ideology. If this is true of politics, they seem to be just personal convictions accompanied presumably it would be true also of political by strong moral feelings. But, as Mill remarked, “one of philosophy. We would need to be satisfied with a the most unequivocal cases of moral feeling” is “the politics and a political philosophy without principles, odium theologicum, in a sincere bigot[5]”. More theories, or ideologies. Saying this may sound recently, Richard Brandt warned, “Various facts about blasphemous, but to appeal to principles we know that the genesis of our moral beliefs militate against the we do not know to be true would surely be worse. mere appeal to intuitions in ethics[4]”. If this is clear in the case of moral feelings, it is even clearer in the case In his Foreword to the 2013 edition of Robert of political feelings. Neither Plato nor Aristotle, neither Nozick’s Anarchy, State, and Utopia, Thomas Nagel Locke nor Hume, neither Kant nor Hegel, neither Mill writes of the “belief in the reality of the moral domain, nor Marx, neither Russell nor Wittgenstein would have as an area in which there are real questions with right put much stock in their evidential value. But I am not and wrong answers.” He claims that “progress...toward proposing a return to any of their own views. There is a discovering the [se] right answers” could be made by Available online: http://saspjournals.com/sjahss 1276 Panayot Butchvarov., Sch. J. Arts. Humanit. Soc. Sci., Jun 2018; 6(6): 1276-1287 third option. I shall call it commonsense political Political philosophy is neither politics nor philosophy. political science, but also it is not ethics, partly because ethics is concerned with far more than political matters, Political philosophy is not politics. Neither is it but also because claims to true principles from which political science or even ethics. If politics is “public life interesting conclusions may be drawn are much less and affairs involving matters of authority and plausible in political philosophy than in ethics. Political government” (Oxford English Dictionary), clearly philosophy asks what a political social organism, political philosophy is not politics: philosophers are not especially the state, ought to be and do, ethics asks what politicians, except per accidens. As to political science, an individual person ought to be and do. Both aim at insofar as it is science rather than philosophy, it belongs telling us what is good and right. Thus, both face the among the empirical disciplines, even if only some that challenges of moral skepticism (which says that even if are still developing – economics, sociology, there is such a matter of fact as being good or being anthropology – parts of which indeed it already right it is unknown and perhaps unknowable) and moral includes. None of these disciplines has achieved the antirealism (which says that there is no such matter of cognitive status enjoyed by physics or biology, but their fact). I have discussed skepticism and antirealism in method of investigation is the same as that of physics ethics elsewhere in detail [10]. Suffice it here to say that and biology; it is clear, plausible, and noncontroversial though their opposites, moral cognitivism and moral – that of empirical research. realism, have always been suspect in ethics, in political philosophy they have seldom been even defended, In contrast, philosophers, whether in political except with unconvincing inferences from metaphysics philosophy or metaphysics, in epistemology or logic, in (as in Plato), ethics (Bentham), economics (Marx), or ethics or aesthetics, etc., do not engage in empirical thought experiments (Rawls). In ethics, for example, research at all – most probably lack the needed that happiness is good and pain bad, or Aquinas’s first inclination and perhaps talent for it. They also, it must principle of natural law, that “good is to be done and be noted, lack special expertise regarding "concepts" or promoted, and evil is to be avoided,” are unlikely to be “ideas,” as well as regarding "meanings" or "uses" of questioned. In political philosophy, even the thesis that words, the “workings of language.” As the exponents of justice is fairness remains controversial, unless intended the 17th century “new way of ideas” eventually learned, as a trivial tautology by gerrymandering the senses of and some of the linguistic philosophers of the 20th the Latinate "justice" and the Germanic “fair,” and century are still learning, these too are empirical ignoring the Latinate “equity.” matters, investigated by psychologists and brain scientists in the case of ideas or concepts and by COMMON SENSE linguists and lexicographers in the case of meanings or In Principia Ethica, G. E. Moore wrote that a uses of words. Philosophers, of course, have a good ear self-evident proposition is one that is evident though not for the nuances of some segments of speech, as J. L. by virtue of inference from other propositions, meaning Austin famously did, but Austin himself insisted that by “evident,” we may suppose, “seen” to be true, videre such an ear was not a substitute for actual empirical being the Latin for “to see”[11]. In “A Defence of research[7]. Philosophers are also good at Common Sense,” he called such propositions “truisms” argumentation, much as lawyers are, but this does not of common sense[12]. I shall just call them “obvious” imply mastery of the subject matters under (one of the senses of “obvious” is “plain or evident,” argumentation nor does it involve research in them– for according to the OED), in order to avoid the technical those lawyers routinely call on experts, witnesses, and here irrelevant controversies in epistemology detectives. regarding the notion of evidence and especially of self- evidence. Sometimes, for stylistic reasons, I shall use Human wellbeing, happiness, and prosperity the adverb “obviously.” I shall also point out have been the central concerns of both political occasionally that certain judgments are not parts of philosophy and ethics. But they are empirical matters, commonsense by prefacing them with “it is not obvious and so are the means of achieving them. They lie, that.” therefore, beyond the particular competence of political philosophy and ethics[8]. Indian utilitarians who hope In “A Defence of Common Sense” Moore to learn in American universities how to reduce merely listed the propositions he found evident – he did suffering in India presumably go to colleges of not argue for them, presumably because he was agriculture, public health, and business administration, convinced that none of the standard deductive and not philosophy departments.
Recommended publications
  • Generic Statements and Antirealism
    GENERIC STATEMENTS AND ANTIREALISM Panayot BUTCHVAROV ABSTRACT: The standard arguments for antirealism are densely abstract, often enigmatic, and thus unpersuasive. The ubiquity and irreducibility of what linguists call generic statements provides a clear argument from a specific and readily understandable case. We think and talk about the world as necessarily subject to generalization. But the chief vehicles of generalization are generic statements, typically of the form “Fs are G,” not universal statements, typically of the form “All Fs are G.” Universal statements themselves are usually intended and understood as though they were only generic. Even if there are universal facts, as Russell held, there are no generic facts. There is no genericity in the world as it is “in-itself.” There is genericity in it only as it is “for-us.” KEYWORDS: Generic, General, Antirealism I shall take general statements to include those that logicians call universal, typically of the form “All Fs are G,” and particular, of the form “Some Fs are G,” but also those that linguists call generic, typically of the form “Fs are G.” The term ‘realism’ will be used for the metaphysical view that reality, the ‘world,’ is mind- independent, in particular, independent of our knowledge of it. ‘Antirealism’ will stand for the opposite view, including Kant’s transcendental idealism as well as recent positions such as Michael Dummett’s ‘antirealism,’ Nelson Goodman’s ‘irrealism,’ and Hilary Putnam’s ‘internal realism.’ According to antirealism, reality depends, insofar as it is known or knowable, on our ways of knowing it, our cognitive capacities – sense perception, introspection, intellectual intuition, imagination, memory, recognition, conceptualization, inductive and deductive reasoning, use of language and other symbolism.
    [Show full text]
  • Counterfactuals and Antirealism
    ISSN 2664-4002 (Print) & ISSN 2664-6714 (Online) South Asian Research Journal of Humanities and Social Sciences Abbreviated Key Title: South Asian Res J Human Soc Sci | Volume-1 | Issue-1| Jun-Jul -2019 | Short Communication Counterfactuals and Antirealism Panayot Butchvarov* The University of Iowa USA *Corresponding Author Panayot Butchvarov Article History Received: 12.07.2019 Accepted: 24.07.2019 Published: 30.07.2019 Abstract: There could be no causal connections in the world because if there were there would be counterfactual facts, and there are no such facts. Cognition of the world must employ counterfactual statements, roughly of the form “If p were true, then q would be true,” but obviously there are no counterfactual facts. Keywords: cognition, antirealism, causality, counterfactual The ways to antirealism Metaphysical antirealism is seemingly incredible but, paradoxically, also self-evident. It seems self-evident insofar as it says that if there is a world that we do not and cannot cognize (Kant‟s “things-in-themselves”) then we can ignore it, and if there is a world that we do or at least can cognize (Kant‟s “things-for-us”) then it can only be the world as we do or can cognize it. So the world we do cognize seems, in a sense, dependent on our cognition of it. (We may think of cognition as the capacity for knowledge, and of knowledge as the successful exercise of that capacity.) Metaphysical antirealism is not solipsistic – it‟s about what we, not what I, do or can cognize. For cognition of a world, unlike cognition of a toothache but like cognition of physics, mathematics, geography, or history, is inseparable from others‟ cognition – from the common language we speak to most of the views we espouse.
    [Show full text]
  • The Practical Turn' David G
    8 The Practical Turn' David G. Stern What is Practice Theory? What is a Practice? What is "practice theory"? The best short answer is that it is any theory that treats practice as a fundamental category, or takes practices as its point of departure . Naturally, this answer leads to further questions . What is meant by "practices" here? What is involved in taking practices as a point of departure or a fundamental category, and what does that commitment amount to? And what is the point of the contrast between a practice-based theory and one that starts elsewhere? Perhaps the most significant point of agreement among those who have taken the practical turn is that it offers a way out of Procustean yet seemingly inescap- able categories, such as subject and object, representation and represented, con- ceptual scheme and content, belief and desire, structure and action, rules and their application, micro and macro, individual and totality . Instead, practice the- orists propose that we start with practices and rethink our theories from the ground up. Bourdieu, for instance, insists that only a theory of practice can open up a way forward : Objective analysis of practical apprehension of the familiar world . teaches us that we shall escape from the ritual either/or choice between objectivism and subjectiv- ism in which the social sciences have so far allowed themselves to be trapped only if we are prepared to inquire into the mode of production and functioning of the practical mastery which makes possible both an objectively intelligible practice and also an objectively enchanted experience of that practice .
    [Show full text]
  • XX Век II. METAETHICS of the 20Th CENTUR
    Максимов Л.В. Сектор этики ИФ РАН (апрель 2016) Метаэтика. Избранная библиография. Часть II. – XX век II. METAETHICS OF THE 20th CENTURY (SELECTIVE BIBLIOGRAPHY) 1. Bruce A. Ackerman Social Justice in the Liberal State (New Haven: YAle University Press, 1980) 2. Robert Ackermann "Consistency and Ethics" in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 69, 1969. 3. E. M. Adams "A Critique of the Emotive Theory of Ethical Terms" in Journal of Philosophy 46, 1949. EMA complains that Ayer and Stevenson do not adequately analyse approbation, failing properly to distinguish it from mere liking. If we do analyse it we find it involves a cognitive element in the form of a judgement of rightness. So it is incoherent to analyse judgements of rightness in terms of approval. "Word-Magic and Logical Analysis in the Field of Ethics" in Journal of Philosophy 47, 1950. "The Nature of Ethical Inquiry" in Journal of Philosophy 48, 1951. "Cartesianism in Ethics" in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 16, 1956. "Mr Hare on the Role of Principles in Deciding" in Mind 65, 1956. "The Nature of 'Ought'" in Philosophical Studies 7, 1956. "'Ought' Again" in Philosophical Studies 8, 1957. "Hall's Analysis of "Ought"" in Journal of Philosophy 55, 1958. "The Theoretical and the Practical" in Review of Metaphysics 13, 1960. Ethical Naturalism and the Modern World-View (London: Oxford University Press, 1961). "Classical Moral Philosophy and Metaethics" in Ethics 74, 1964. "A Defense of Value Realism" in Southern Journal of Philosophy 4, 1966. "Gewirth on Reason and Morality" in Review of Metaphysics 33, 1980. "The Subjective Normative Structure of Agency" in Regis, Gewirth's Ethical Rationalism "Rationality and Morality" in Review of Metaphysics 46, 1993.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE Richard Anthony Fumerton
    CURRICULUM VITAE Richard Anthony Fumerton PERSONAL Born, October 7, 1949, Toronto, Ontario Married, two children Home Address: 608 Whiting Ave, Iowa City, Iowa 52245 Office Phone: (319) 335-0022 Home Phone: (319) 338-5602 Cell Phone: (319) 621-8148 E-mail: [email protected] Fax: (319) 353-2322 EDUCATION Ph.D. Brown University, 1974, Philosophy M.A. Brown University, 1973, Philosophy B.A. University of Toronto (Victoria College), 1971, Philosophy TEACHING Professor, University of Iowa, 1985-present Associate Professor, University of Iowa, 1979-1985 Visiting Assistant Professor, University of Minnesota, Fall Quarter, 1978 Assistant Professor, University of Iowa, 1974-1979 HONORS AND AWARDS F. Wendell Miller Professorship, 2003-present Regents Award for Faculty Excellence, 1997 Collegiate Teaching Award, University of Iowa, 1996 M. L. Huitt Award for Excellence in Teaching, 1994, University of Iowa Canada Council Fellow, 1973-74 Woodrow Wilson Fellow, 1971-72 DISSERTATIONS DIRECTED Brian Collins. A Utilitarian Account of Political Obligation. In Progress. Samuel Taylor. The Problem of Easy Justification: An Investigation of Evidence, Justification and Reliability. In progress. Kalyn Kappelman. A Critical Evaluation of Virtue Consequentialism. In progress. Ian MacMillan. Internalism, Externalism, and Epistemic Source Circularity. November, 2012. Brett Coppenger. Achieving Epistemic Descent.. Summer, 2012. Travis Dickinson. Direct Awareness of Fit as the Solution to all Sellarsian Dilemmas. Spring, 2011. Pat Monaghan (co-directed with Evan Fales). Property Possession as Identity. August, 2010. John DePoe. The Knowledge Argument for Dualism. August, 2010 Tom Javoroski. Space Time Gaps and the Persistence of Objects Through Time. Fall, 2009. Anthony Bryson. Epistemology and the Role of Intuition. Fall, 2009.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato and Hobbes: on the Foundations of Political Philosophy
    Plato and Hobbes: On the Foundations of Political Philosophy Jan Dejnoñka May 1, 1992; edited for the Web, November 11, 2005 (new final paragraph of main text added July 22, 2006) There is a certain philosophia prima on which all other philosophy ought to depend... --Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan Jan Dejnoñka, Plato and Hobbes: On the Foundations of Political Philosophy (1992). A theory of the state based on theory of human nature and theory of value, with Hume’s is-ought inference problem solved. Philosophers and others discussed include Aristotle, Epicurus, G. W. F. Hegel, Immanuel Kant, Frances Hutcheson, Abraham Maslow, John Paul Scott, Richard E. Leakey, Raymond Dart, Robert Ardrey, Leo Strauss, Panayot Butchvarov, H. P. Grice, P. F. Strawson, C. D. Broad, W. T. Stace, Ernest Barker, Robert Lodge, Henry Teloh, Samuel Taylor Coleridge, C. B. MacPherson, Herbert W. Schneider, Richard, S. Peters, Mortimer Adler, Irving R. Copi, Alan Gewirth, Charles Hampden-Turner, Wilhelm Windelband, Stewart Umphrey, Miriam M. Reik, Martin A. Bertman, Ernest Nagel, Richard Taylor, A. E. Taylor, John Searle, John H. Hick, Joseph Raz, C. S. Lewis, Robert Nisbet, Russell Kirk, and James Bond Stockdale. Table of Contents Preface Introduction 1. The State A. A Pros Hen Theory of Politics B. Defining the State 2 C. Plato’s Definition of the State D. Hobbes’ Definition of the State E. Is the State a Fiction? 2. Values A. Values as Properties B. Against Radical Ethical Relativism C. Plato and Hobbes on Moral Relativism 3. Human Nature A. An Evolutionary Theory of Human Nature B. An Evolutionary Theory of Politics C.
    [Show full text]
  • Comparative Philosophy and the Tertium: Comparing What with What, and in What Respect?
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by RERO DOC Digital Library Dao (2014) 13:151–171 DOI 10.1007/s11712-014-9368-z Comparative Philosophy and the Tertium: Comparing What with What, and in What Respect? Ralph Weber Published online: 15 April 2014 # Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014 Abstract Comparison is fundamental to the practice and subject-matter of philosophy, but has received scant attention by philosophers. This is even so in “comparative philosophy,” which literally distinguishes itself from other philosophy by being “com- parative.” In this article, the need for a philosophy of comparison is suggested. What we compare with what, and in what respect it is done, poses a series of intriguing and intricate questions. In Part One, I offer a problematization of the tertium comparationis (the third of comparison) by examining conceptualizations of similarity, family resem- blance, and analogy, which it is sometimes argued can do without a tertium comparationis. In Part Two, I argue that a third of comparison is already required to determine what is to be compared, and insofar as that determination precedes the comparison that tertium may be called “pre-comparative.” This leads me to argue against incomparability and to show how anything can indeed be compared to any- thing. In Part Three, I relate my arguments to what is today commonly labelled “comparative philosophy.” Finally, I raise some questions of ontology and politics in order to demonstrate the relevance of a philosophy of comparison. Keywords Comparative philosophy. Intercultural philosophy. Tertium comparationis . Analogy. Family resemblance 1 Introduction It is very ordinary for us to engage in comparisons of all sorts.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE Richard Anthony Fumerton
    1 CURRICULUM VITAE Richard Anthony Fumerton PERSONAL Born, October 7, 1949, Toronto, Ontario Married, two children Home Address: 608 Whiting Ave, Iowa City, Iowa 52245 Office Phone: (319) 335-0022 Home Phone: (319) 338-5602 Cell Phone: (319) 621-8148 E-mail: [email protected] Fax: (319) 353-2322 EDUCATION Ph.D. Brown University, 1974, Philosophy M.A. Brown University, 1973, Philosophy B.A. University of Toronto (Victoria College), 1971, Philosophy TEACHING Professor, University of Iowa, 1985-present Associate Professor, University of Iowa, 1979-1985 Visiting Assistant Professor, University of Minnesota, Fall Quarter, 1978 Assistant Professor, University of Iowa, 1974-1979 HONORS AND AWARDS Michael J. Brody Award (for Faculty Service), 2016 University of Iowa Presidential Lecturer, Spring, 2016 F. Wendell Miller Professorship, 2003-present Regents Award for Faculty Excellence, 1997 Collegiate Teaching Award, University of Iowa, 1996 M. L. Huit Award for Excellence in Teaching, 1994, University of Iowa Canada Council Fellow, 1973-74 Woodrow Wilson Fellow, 1971-72 DISSERTATIONS DIRECTED Justin Christopher, Testimony in Narrative Research (co-director). Summer, 2017 Bryan Appley, Skepticism and Reasoning to the Best Explanation. Spring, 2016 Greg Stoutenburg, Knowledge, Infallibility, and Skepticism. Spring, 2015 Brian Collins, A Utilitarian Account of Political Obligation. (Co-director). Summer, 2014. Samuel Taylor. The Problem of Easy Justification: An Investigation of Evidence, Justification and Reliability. Summer. 2013. Kalyn Kappelman. A Critical Evaluation of Virtue Consequentialism. In progress. Ian MacMillan. Internalism, Externalism, and Epistemic Source Circularity. November, 2012. 2 Brett Coppenger. Achieving Epistemic Descent. Summer, 2012. Travis Dickinson. Direct Awareness of Fit as the Solution to all Sellarsian Dilemmas.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Newsletter on Philosophy in Two-Year Colleges, Vol. 16, No. 1
    NEWSLETTER | The American Philosophical Association Philosophy in Two-Year Colleges FALL 2016 VOLUME 16 | NUMBER 1 FROM THE EDITOR ARTICLES Eric Morton and George Rainbolt Thoughts on Consolidation of a Two-Year College and a Research University Michael B. Brezinsky The Ethics of Freedom: A Unified Framework for Teaching Ethics in the Community College Heather Wilburn Making Connections: Philosophy as Self-transformation and Critical Thinking David Sackris Preferred Qualifications: Community College Teaching Experience Andy Wible Community College Teachers and American Philosophical Association Meetings Robert Boyd Pursuing Reality: A Strawsonian Model CALL FOR PAPERS VOLUME 16 | NUMBER 1 FALL 2016 © 2016 BY THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION ISSN 2155-9708 APA NEWSLETTER ON Philosophy in Two-Year Colleges THOMAS URBAN, EDITOR VOLUME 16 | NUMBER 1 | FALL 2016 FROM THE EDITOR ARTICLES Thomas Urban Thoughts on the Consolidation of a Two- RETIRED PROFESSOR, HOUSTON COMMUNITY COLLEGE Year College and a Research University During the question-and-answer portion of the 2010 APA Central Division John Dewey Lecture, titled “On Not Eric Morton Knowing Where You Are Going,” speaker Alasdair MacIntyre GEORGIA PERIMETER COLLEGE remarked that in the future “Philosophy in the United States will be found in community colleges and other strange George Rainbolt places.” While this comment caught many by surprise, it GEORGIA STATE UNIVERSITY points to an evolving presence for philosophy in two-year and community colleges. The aim of this newsletter is to While mergers of colleges and universities have occurred foster a rich discussion concerning the nature and issues as long as there have been colleges and universities, it that characterize that evolution, as well as to highlight the seems likely that current political and economic factors great differences one finds from institution to institution, will lead to an increase in such mergers in the years to and the great diversity of faculty and students who populate come.
    [Show full text]
  • Meta-Ethics and Meta-Epistemology 277
    W!LLlAM P. ALSTON MET A-ETHIC S AND MET A-EPISTEMO LOG Y Recent epistemology has been heavily concerned with the conceptual and methodological foundations of the subject - in particular with the concepts of knowledge, certainty, basic knowledge, justification, and so on. In other words to a considerable extent it has been taken up with meta-epistemology, in contrast with substantive epistemology, in contrast with questions about what we know, how we know it, and how various parts of our knowledge are interrelated. Just as with ethics, meta-inquiries have been pursued through- out the history of the subject (see, e.g., the discussions of the concept of knowledge in Plato's Theaetetus and in Book N of Locke's Essay), but also as in ethics, meta concerns have been more prominent in twentieth century Anglo-American philosophy than ever before. However meta-epistemology has not yet attained the pitch of self- consciousness displayed by recent meta-ethics. Writers on epistemology, unlike their ethical brethren, rarely signal the shifting of gears between meta and substantive. Nor do most of them seem to be aware of the range of alternatives in meta-epistemology and their interrelations or of the ways in which decisions in do and do not narrow one's options in substantive epistemology. The time is ripe for an advance to a new level of self-consciousness in this regard. We need to take a hard look at the problems of meta-epistemology, their possible solutions, and their relations to the problems of substantive epistemology. This paper is designed to make a contribution to that enterprise.
    [Show full text]
  • Species of Goodness
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1999 Species of goodness. William Benjamin Bradley University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Bradley, William Benjamin, "Species of goodness." (1999). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2318. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2318 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. SPECIES OF GOODNESS A Dissertation Presented by WILLIAM BENJAMIN BRADLEY Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY February 1999 Department of Philosophy © Copyright by William Benjamin Bradley 1999 All Rights Reserved SPECIES OF GOODNESS A Dissertation Presented by WILLIAM BENJAMIN BRADLEY Approved as to style and content by: 7 /U^l Fred Feldman, Chair Phillip Bricker, Member ACKNOWLEDGMENTS There are many people I must thank for their help in my completion of this dissertation. First and foremost, I thank my thesis director, Fred Feldman. The idea for this dissertation came out of Fred's Ethics seminar in Spring 1996; it was Fred who encouraged me to pursue this project. He also provided helpful comments quickly on countless drafts. Anyone who knows Fred's work will recognize his obvious influence on this dissertation. I also thank Phil Bricker, Gary Matthews, and Angelika Kratzer for serving on my committee.
    [Show full text]
  • Dreier-CV-January 2010
    CURRICULUM VITAE James Dreier Department of Philosophy Home: Box 1918 Brown University 110 East Killingly Road Providence, RI 02912 Foster, RI 02825 (401) 863-3226 (401) 647-2267 FAX 863-2719 [email protected] Employment 1988 – 1996 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Brown University. 1996 – 2002 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Brown University. 2002 – present Professor of Philosophy, Brown University. Visiting Positions July 1993 – June 1994 Visiting Senior Lecturer in Philosophy, Monash University, Melbourne, Australia. Jan. 2003 – July 2003 John Harsanyi Fellow at the Social and Political Theory program, ANU. Education Harvard University, A.B. magna cum laude in Government, 1982. Princeton University, Ph.D. in Philosophy, January 1989. Publications 1990 “Internalism and Speaker Relativism”, Ethics 101, 6-26. 1992 “The Supervenience Argument against Moral Realism”, Southern J. of Philosophy 30, 13-38. 1993 “Structures of Normative Theories”, The Monist 76:1, 22-40. 1994 “Perspectives on Normativity”, Noûs 28, 514-525. 1996 “Projectivism”, article for Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy supplement. “Expressivist Embeddings and Minimalist Truth”, Philosophical Studies 83:1, 29-51. “Rational Preference: Decision Theory as a Theory of Practical Rationality”, Theory and Decision 40:3, 249-76. “Accepting Agent Centered Norms”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74, 409-22. 1997 “Humean Doubts”, in Ethics and Practical Reason Cullity and Gaut (eds.), Oxford University Press. 1998 “C. L. Stevenson”, entry for Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 1999 “Transforming Expressivism”, Noûs 33:4, 558-572. Dreier page 2 Publications, continued 2000 “Dispositions and Fetishes”, Philosophy and Phenomenlogical Research 61:3, 619-38. 2001 “C. L. Stevenson” entry for Blackwell’s Companion to Analytic Philosophy, A.
    [Show full text]